Kant’s Questions What is
the Human Being?
1 Herr, was ist der Mensch, das du dich seiner annimmst?
– Psalm 144:3
2 3 The field of philosophy . . . can be reduced to the following questions:
What can I know? What ought I to do? What may I hope? What is
the human being? [Was ist der Mensch?] Metaphysics answers the first
question, morals the second, religion the third, and anthropology the
fourth. Fundamentally, however, we could reckon all of this as
anthropology. (9: 25, cf. 11:249)
“I myself am a researcher by inclination. I feel the entire thirst for
cognition and the eager restlessness to proceed further in it, as well
as the satisfaction at every acquisition . . . [but] I would feel by far
less useful than the common laborer if I did not believe that this
consideration could impart a value to all others in order to establish
the rights of humanity.”
— Immanuel Kant, from private notes written in 1764-5 (20:44)
4 Table of Contents
Acknowledgments
Introduction
Part One: Kant on the Human Being
1
Kant’s Transcendental Anthropology
2
Kant’s Empirical Anthropology
3
Human Evil and Human History
4
Human Diversity
5
Kant’s Pragmatic Anthropology
Part Two: Responses and Alternatives to Kant
6
The Reception of Kant’s Anthropology
7
19th Century Alternatives: Marx, Darwin, Nietzsche, & Freud
Part Three: What is the Human Being Today?
8
Scientific Naturalism
9
Historicism and Diversity
10
Existentialism
11
Normativity
Conclusion
5 Acknowledgements
XXX TO BE COMPLETED XXX
6 INTRODUCTION
[W]hat is man’s ultimate nature? We keep returning to the subject
with a sense of hesitancy and even dread. For if the brain is a
machine of ten billion nerve cells and the mind can somehow be
explained as the summed activity of a finite number of chemical and
electrical reactions, boundaries limit the human prospect—we are
biological and our souls cannot fly free. If humankind evolved by
Darwinian natural selection, genetic chance and environmental
necessity, not God, made the species . . . However much we embellish
that stark conclusion with metaphor and imagery, it remains the
philosophical legacy of the last century of scientific research. No way
appears around this admittedly unappealing proposition. It is the
essential first hypothesis for any serious consideration of the human
condition. (Wilson 1978/2004: 1-2)
If we want to discover what the human being amounts to, we can
only find it in what human beings are: and what human beings are,
above all other things, is various. It is in understanding that
variousness – its range, its nature, its basis, and its implications –
that we shall come to construct a concept of human nature . . . To be
human here is thus not to be Everyman; it is to be a particular kind
of human being, and of course human beings differ . . . [I]t is in a
systematic review and analysis of [different ways of being human] – of
the Plain’s Indian’s bravura, the Hindu’s obsessiveness, the
Frenchman’s rationalism, the Berber’s anarchism, the American’s
optimism – that we shall find out what it is, or can be, to be a
[hu]man. (Geertz 1973: 52-3)1
[T]here is at least one being [the human being] whose existence
comes before its essence, a being which exists before it can be
defined by any conception of it. . . . What do we mean by saying that
existence precedes essence? We mean that man first of all exists,
1
Throughout this quotation and the following one, I’ve changed “man” and “men” here to “the human
being” or “human beings.”
7 encounters himself, surges up in the world – and defines himself
afterwards. If the human being . . . is not definable, it is because to
begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and then
he will be what he makes of himself. Thus, there is no human nature
. . . . The human being simply is. Not that he is simply what he
conceives himself to be, but he is what he wills, and as he conceives
himself after already existing – as he wills to be after that leap
towards existence. The human being is nothing else but what he
makes of himself. (Sartre 1993: 15)
What is the human being? The three quotations with which this
introduction begins lay out three alternatives: E.O. Wilson, one of the
preeminent sociobiologists of the 20th century, sees the answer to the
question, or at least the parameters for the answer, given by biology.
Humans are animals with a particular structure that has evolved over
millions of years. We are biological beings, and what we need in order to
better answer the question “What is the human being?” is better biology,
a more detailed description of how we, as humans, are like and unlike
other animals that inhabit the earth. Clifford Geertz, five years earlier,
articulated a different conception of human beings, one at the core of the
“human” science of anthropology. For Geertz, there is no answer to the
question “What is the human being?” because we are not preeminently
biological organisms, but cultural ones;2 since there is not one human
culture, there is not one kind of human being. What we need, to answer
the question, is not better biological description, but more widelyranging, deeply-investigating anthropological and historical studies of
human variety. Rather than looking for a theory of human nature, we
should seek a catalog of human ways of life. Alternatively, perhaps the
problem of finding human nature is more difficult; perhaps, as the
existentialist philosopher and literary author Jean-Paul Sartre argues,
human beings are “condemned to be free” (Sartre 1956:568). Rather than
trying to discover what human beings are, we should simply make
human nature by free choices. Rather than looking as scientists or
anthropologists at what human beings happen to be, we should take the
role of architects of possibility, whether as artists (literary or otherwise)
imagining and thereby creating new human possibilities, as political or
social activists changing the social landscape, or simply as acting
individuals creating human nature through our daily choices.
2
To be fair to Wilson, this is a point with which he would, in most respects, agree.
8 The world we live in today is one within which these approaches to
the question “what is the human being?” cannot be ignored. Scientific
knowledge about our biological nature – from the coding of the human
genome to the mapping of brain activity – has made it clearer than ever
that humans operate with biological constraints. And as Wilson rightly
points out, our knowledge of precisely how our biology is like and unlike
that of other animals cannot be ignored in any serious consideration of
human nature. At the same time, as the world becomes increasingly
interconnected, human diversity, even if actually diminishing, is
becoming more apparent and more relevant to more and more people
across the globe. Protestant Christians in the United States cannot afford
to be wholly ignorant of the cultures of rural Muslims in Afghanistan or
atheists in China or Buddhists in Sri Lanka. Throughout the world,
diversity is literally on one’s doorstep, as Catholic Filipinos work in Korea
and Dubai, Muslim immigrants serve in European Parliaments, and
Chinese businessmen set up shop in Africa. And the awareness of this
diversity requires dealing with the fact that human nature is diverse.
Finally, the increased power over our world and ourselves that comes
from scientific, technological, and economic progress along with the
awareness of the range of human possibilities that comes from seeing
other cultures gives rise to an ever-more-acute sense that human nature
really is up to us, that we can make ourselves into whatever we want to
be. The situation in which human beings find themselves today requires
thinking carefully about what it means to be human.
But what, precisely, is one seeking when one asks “What is the
human being?” What is the question that Wilson, Geertz, Sartre, and so
many others are trying to answer? Strikingly, none of these thinkers –
not even the biologist Wilson -- treats the question “What is the human
being?” quite like the question “what is oxygen?” or “what is a giraffe?”
All of them see the question as one about our prospects, as one not
merely about the structure of our brain or society, but about the
implications of that structure for human choices, for what we should do
with ourselves. And all recognize that the question “what is the human
being?” is also, and fundamentally, about what is important about us.
When we understand it in this way, we can see why this question
was central for Kant, why Kant would insist,“[t]he greatest concern of the
human being is to know how to properly fulfill his station in creation and
to rightly understand what one must do in order to be a human being”
(20:41). Knowing what it is to be human is – for Wilson, Geertz, and
Sartre no less than for Kant – something worthy of the greatest concern.
Thus Geertz does not simply assert that humans are different, but adds
that their differences are more important than their similarities, more
9 essential to what it means to be human. All of them recognize a point
made by the early 20th century philosopher Martin Heidegger, that “The
being whose analysis our task is, is always we ourselves. The being of
this being is always mine” (Heidegger 1953:39). Or, put another way, they
recognize what anyone who asks “what is the human being?” recognizes,
that asking what a human being is really amounts to asking “who am
I?”, “what is most important about me (to me)?”, “what do I value about
myself?” and even “what do I aspire to be?”
This emphasis on values and aspirations, however, should not
blind us to the fact that claims about human prospects and aspirations
include descriptions of human beings. Even Sartre, who insists that what
human beings are can only be answered after we make ourselves what
we are to be, nonetheless recognizes that we are “condemned to be free”,
that freedom is a “human condition” from which we cannot escape.
Descriptions of the human condition provide the backdrop for his claims
about how humans should act in response to them. Kant, too, recognizes
the importance of accurate descriptions of human beings. In part, this is
for practical reasons: “The question is which condition suits the human
being, an inhabitant of the planet that orbits the sun at a distance of 200
diameters of the sun. Just as little as I can ascend from here to the
planet Jupiter, so little do I demand to have qualities that are proper only
to that planet . . . I do not at all have the ambition of wanting to be a
seraph; my pride is only this, that I am a human being” (20:47). One
needs to know what human beings are to know what we should aspire to
be. And for Kant – as, at least, for Wilson and Geertz – human beings are
also just very interesting to study. Even at a wholly natural and
impersonal level, studying human diversity can be quite entertaining and
humans’ biological and psychological nature is complex and challenging
to explain. Not only must any practical account of human beings reflect
an accurate description of them, but such descriptions are, in their own
right, worth pursuing.
At its core, the question “What is the human being?” combines
careful description of human characteristics with a normative,
aspirational account of what about “us” is or would be truly valuable, an
account rooted in the sense that each human questioner has of herself.
Answering the question, however, involves clarifying what precisely
constitutes a legitimate sort of “description” and also what structure and
importance to ascribe to the normative, from-within perspective on
oneself. And ultimately, as we see in the brief references to Wilson,
Geertz, and Sartre, the answer to the question will combine – either
implicitly or explicitly – these two aspects. The main purpose of this book
is to lay out Kant’s answer to his question and to situate this answer in
10 the context of contemporary debates about human nature and the
historical forces that brought us to where we are today. The first part of
the book thus focuses on Kant’s answer. The second part lays out the
historical reception of Kant’s ideas and the later trends that took the
question in different directions. And the final part brings Kant into
dialogue with the most important contemporary approaches to human
nature, including those of Wilson, Geertz, and Sartre.
1. Kant’s “Anthropologies”
In one of his lectures, Kant is recorded as having laid out his view of
philosophy as a whole:
The field of philosophy . . . can be reduced to the following questions:
What can I know? What ought I to do? What may I hope? What is
the human being? Metaphysics answers the first question, morals the
second, religion the third, and anthropology the fourth.
Fundamentally, however, we could reckon all of this as anthropology.
(9: 25, cf. 11:249)
The term “anthropology” may seem odd here for contemporary readers.
We are accustomed to thinking of “anthropology” as a specific academic
discipline that studies variations between people in different cultures.
Kant, by contrast, uses the term anthropology in its original sense, as
the study (logos) of human beings (anthropos). Thus Kantian
anthropology includes comparisons between different people at different
times, but it also includes – and emphasizes – general features of human
beings as such. Anthropology is simply the discipline that answers the
question, “What is the Human Being?” That is how the term will be used
throughout this book.
But the claim that all of philosophy can be reckoned as
anthropology may seem strange for other reasons, as well. While human
nature may be a part of philosophy, philosophy often deals with other
questions – such as the existence of God or the basic nature of reality –
that seem to go beyond anthropology, and other disciplines deal
(arguably even better) with important aspects of the answer to the
question of the human being. In identifying philosophy and
anthropology, Kant explicitly claims that every really important question
that humans can ask, whether about God or substance or basic laws of
physics or morals or aesthetics, is fundamentally a question about
human beings, about what we can know, or should do, or may hope.
11 A final reason that Kant’s claim to reduce all philosophy to
anthropology might seems strange, especially for those accustomed to
think of anthropology as an empirical discipline, is that this sort of
enquiry seems inadequate to establish the normative claims embodied in
the questions of what one can (legitimately) believe, or should do. Those
familiar with Kant’s work may be even more puzzled. At the end of his
life, Kant did published a book entitled Anthropology from a Pragmatic
Point of View, but this book could hardly be said to include Kant’s most
important contributions to the questions of human knowledge,
obligation, and hope. This Anthropology is striking for being deeply
empirical, while Kant’s most developed answers to the questions of
knowledge, obligation, and hope emphasize that these questions must be
answered non-empirically, or a priori. In his Groundwork, Kant even goes
so far as to emphasize a distinction between “pure moral philosophy,”
which most fundamentally addresses the question “What ought I to do?”
and “moral anthropology,” which is secondary and merely adds empirical
details. Kant’s Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View relates to this
secondary, empirical aspect of human knowledge, obligation, and hope,
and does not articulate the most important dimensions of Kant’s answers
to the three questions that, supposedly, can all be “reckon[ed] . . . as
anthropology.”
In fact, Kant articulates different “anthropologies,” different kinds
of answer to the question “what is the human being?” Most importantly,
he distinguishes between three ways in which one can ask the question
and three dimensions of human life to which each of these three ways
apply. The dimensions of human life arise from Kant’s description of
human mental states as being essentially of three kinds: cognitions (of
truth), feelings (of pleasure), and volitions (for various goods). Kant does
not ascribe consistent names to his three ways of inquiring, but in this
book, I refer to them as “transcendental,” “empirical,” and “pragmatic.”
Put very briefly, transcendental anthropology provides normative, fromwithin accounts of what it’s like to be human, accounts that define how
one should think, feel, and choose based on what we take ourselves to be
doing when we engage in thinking, feeling, or choosing. Empirical
anthropology provides scientific (in a loose sense), observation-based
descriptions and categorizations of how observable humans think, feel,
and act. And pragmatic anthropology puts these two approaches
together, drawing on empirical descriptions to provide advice about how
best to satisfy the norms elucidated within transcendental anthropology.
Part One of this book unpacks these different Kantian “anthropologies.”
12 2. Receptions and Alternatives to Kant
Kant was not the first to ask about the human being, and he was
certainly not the last. In the decades following the publication of Kant’s
three Critiques, Kant quickly rose to prominence and elicited significant
responses to and criticisms of his views. But almost as quickly, Kant’s
specific approaches to thinking about human beings were overshadowed.
At first, Kant was overshadowed by philosophers explicitly taking up his
key themes, then increasingly by quite different philosophies like that of
Hegel, and finally, over the course of the 19th century, by reflections on
human nature by the biologists, psychologists, social scientists, literary
critics and artists. This shift can be represented by the ways in which
Darwin, Freud, Marx, and Nietzsche now dramatically overshadow Kant
in discussions about human beings. Each of these figures not only
developed important alternatives to Kant’s conception of the human
being but helped shift the discussion away from philosophy and into
other arenas of inquiry. The relatively short middle section of the book
traces these responses and alternatives to Kant’s conception of the
human being. Chapter six begins with the initial reception of Kant’s
transcendental anthropology and traces the series of criticisms and
appropriations of Kant that culminated in Hegel’s philosophy. Chapter
seven then turns to Darwin, Freud, Marx, and Nietzsche not only for the
ways in which they directly or indirectly challenge Kant but more
importantly for the alternative visions of the human being that they
present.
3. What is the human being today?
In the end, however, Kant’s approach to the human being cannot
satisfy “the greatest concern of the human being” (20:41) nor achieve the
great goal that Kant assigned for it – “to establish the rights of humanity”
(20:44) – unless it can be brought into conversation with the dominant
approaches to thinking about human beings today. Part Three – chapters
eight through eleven – cultivates this conversation. Each of these
chapters describes one of the most important contemporary ways of
answering the question “What is the human being?”, and in each case,
this answer is brought into dialogue with Kant.
Chapter eight looks at scientific naturalists such as Wilson, who
advocate that the question is best answered by biological or psychological
studies of human beings. There are a wide range of such naturalist
approaches, so this chapter gives only a relatively small sample of the
13 ways in which philosophers and scientists have sought to use biological
or psychological descriptions of human nature – what Kant would call
“empirical anthropology” – to fully answer the question “What is the
human being?” Chapter nine looks at approaches to human beings that
emphasize human diversity, whether in the context of historical changes
that make the human being of today different from the human beings of
other times or in the context of cotemporaneous cultural differences that
make human beings in one culture different from those in another. Both
of these approaches represent attempts to make what for Kant is only
empirical anthropology (or even a subset of empirical anthropology) into
the whole, and both approaches not only raise serious problems for Kant
but also – as I hope to show – suffer from serious weaknesses that Kant’s
anthropology can highlight and alleviate.
Among the most important weaknesses of historicism and
naturalism is their failure to take sufficiently seriously what I will call the
from-within perspective of transcendental anthropology, and chapter ten
looks at a philosophical approach to human beings that seeks to take
this quite seriously, but with a different result than Kant: existentialism.
Existentialists are arguably the most direct heirs of Kant’s work in
transcendental anthropology, taking a core insight of Kant’s – that
human beings are fundamentally free but finite beings – and radicalizing
this insight in such a way that the normative weight Kant ascribes to
principles of reasoning and action becomes subordinated to – rather than
constitutive of – human freedom.
In the end, I argue that while existentialism can reinvigorate and
even enrich certain Kantian emphases, it fails to really speak to human
beings because it fails to provide the right sort of normativity. Chapter
eleven, then, takes up a small sample of contemporary approaches to
normativity, beginning with some that are far removed from Kant and
ending with two of the most prominent contemporary neo-Kantian
philosophers writing today: Jürgen Habermas and Christine Korsgaard.
These philosophers provide models for how Kantians today can integrate
and respond to the insights of naturalism, historicism, and
existentialism while still developing authentically Kantian conceptions of
the human being.
14 PART ONE: KANT ON THE HUMAN BEING
15 CHAPTER 1: KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL ANTHROPOLOGY
“As to the subject matter with which we are concerned, we ask that
people think of it . . . as the foundation of human . . . dignity. Each
individual equally, then, may reflect on it himself . . . [Our work] claims
nothing . . . beyond what is mortal.”
— Francis Bacon, New Organon, quoted by Kant in the Critique of
Pure Reason (Bii)
I. “Transcendental Anthropology”
In the introduction, I claimed that Kant’s answer to the question
“What is the human being?” has at least three different components. Of
these, I will refer to the one that made Kant famous and that he
identified with “the field of philosophy” (9:25) as “transcendental
anthropology.” The term “transcendental anthropology” is taken from
Kant’s handwritten notes, in which he refers to an “anthropologia
transcendentalis,” a “self-knowledge of the understanding and reason”
that would critique all other sciences, including not only “geometry” and
“knowledge of nature” but even “literature . . . theology, law” and
“knowledge of morality” (RA 903, 15:395). But the concept of
transcendental anthropology comes from combining Kant’s insistence
that all of philosophy is reducible to “anthropology” (9:25) with his
description of each aspect of his philosophy as “transcendental” (see
A13/B27; 4:390; 5:113, 266, 270; 6:272; and 8:381).3 Throughout his
philosophical works, Kant answers central philosophical questions in
ways that are “anthropological,” but only in a new, distinctive sense of
anthropology, one that I call “transcendental.”
3
Admittedly, Kant often reserves the term “anthropology” for his pragmatic anthropology, and he often
reserves the term “transcendental” for investigations of the conditions of possibility of experience (the topic
of his first Critique). His inclusion in “anthropology” of questions like “What may I know?” and “What
ought I to do?”, questions most obviously discussed in Kant’s Critiques more than in his Anthropology
from a Pragmatic Point of View, justifies referring to Kant’s “Critical” philosophy (named for his
Critiques) as an “anthropology,” and all of his Critiques are “transcendental” in the sense laid out in the
rest of this section (a priori, normative, from-within investigations of conditions of possibility). But the
term “transcendental anthropology” is fundamentally a term used to contrast this approach to the human
being with the empirical and pragmatic approaches used later in the book. It is not a term typically used by
Kant to describe this approach.
16 While this transcendental investigation is contrasted, for Kant,
with empirical study of human beings, one must be careful not to
confuse “transcendental” with “transcendent” and thereby take
transcendental anthropology (or philosophy) to refer to some aspect of
human beings that transcends ordinary experience, or our animal
nature, or something of that sort. In the same way that God might be
seen as ultimately transcendent, we might want to study the
transcendent aspect of human beings, through art, perhaps, or by
talking about our immortal souls. Kant, however, sharply contrasts his
transcendental philosophy from traditional philosophies of the
“transcendent.” For Kant, “transcendental anthropology” is a kind of
“self-knowledge of the understanding and of reason” (RA 903, 15:395).
By this he does not mean simply that in knowing human beings, we
know ourselves, since this would be true for empirical investigations of
human beings as well. Instead, in transcendental anthropology, one
knows oneself from-within rather than looking at one’s psychology from
the stance of an observer. Transcendental anthropology is a most
immanent sort of self-knowledge, and hence sharply contrasted with both
empirical sciences and divine-like transcendence.
The notion of transcendental anthropology as “from-within” is often
described in terms of a difference between “first person” and “third
person” perspectives, the perspectives of the thinking, feeling, or
choosing subject and perspectives on someone as an object. This way of
describing the distinction can be helpful if one avoids thinking of
“introspective” states as first person, since “from-within” does not imply
that transcendental anthropology is “introspective” in any traditional
sense. One way of making this distinction clear can be seen in the case
of choosing a course of action. One observing humans might say that
what a person chooses in a particular case is determined by accidental
environmental features of which the person is only barely conscious. Or
one might introspect and say that one’s behavior in a particular instance
was caused by, say, a combination of anger and exhaustion. The next
chapter shows how Kant’s empirical anthropology focuses on these sorts
of causal explanations of behavior. But when one actually choosing, one
doesn’t consider these accidental and unconscious influences as bases
for choice. One looks for various reasons for action, and even if these
reasons include what one might in another context see as mere causes of
action (say, one’s desiring something), they have a different character
when one considers them to be reasons to act; they serve not as
explanations for behavior but as justifications for it. From-within the
context of deliberation, one’s anger appears not as a necessary cause of
action, but as a candidate reason for acting, a reason that one may either
17 endorse or reject. Throughout his transcendental anthropology, Kant
offers accounts of what is involved from-within the processes of thinking,
judging, choice, and aesthetic appreciation.
The from-within perspective involves an important evaluative or
normative dimension. When explaining behavior non-transcendentally,
one looks at what the causes of action are, and one need not evaluate
whether these causes are “good.” The question whether, say, anger is a
“good” cause of an action seems misguided; it either is the cause or it is
not. But when thinking about behavior (or judgments, or choices)
transcendentally, one looks at reasons for that behavior, and reasons
invite evaluation. Anger might have caused the behavior, but we can still
ask whether it was a good reason for doing what one did. And this is the
sort of question one asks, not merely when deciding what to do, but also
when deciding what to believe, or how to judge about something, or even
whether something is beautiful. The normative question – “Is this a good
reason for people to do/think/feel such-and-such?” – arises within
transcendental anthropology.
Along with this from-within, normative perspective on human
beings, Kant’s transcendental anthropology employs a distinctive style of
argument. “Transcendental” arguments in Kant proceed from some
“given” to the conditions of possibility of that given. Thus Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason is an extended argument exploring the conditions of
possibility of empirical cognition (what we can know). As an experiencer
of the world, one can think about what must be the case for one’s
experience to be possible, and Kant argues that in order for humans to
have the kind of experience that we have, the world must contain
substances, laws of causality, and other features, and human cognition
of it must be limited in various ways. Similarly, the Critique of Practical
Reason argues from the moral law we find valid within deliberation and
evaluation to various conditions of possibility of that validity.
In sum, Kant’s transcendental anthropology focuses on what can
be known about human beings a priori through an examination of their
basic mental faculties “from-within” that specifically attends to the
conditions of possibility of normative constraints on human beings. In the
rest of this chapter, I take up some details of this transcendental
anthropology as it plays out in Kant’s three famous Critiques of Pure
Reason, Practical Reason, and Judgment. Before turning to those details,
it is worth saying a bit more about the specifics of Kant’s conception of
the human being in order to see how the Critiques hang together as a
whole “transcendental anthropology.” Within both his empirical and his
transcendental anthropology, Kant argues for a threefold division of
18 human mental states into those of cognition (thoughts), volition (desires
and choices), and affection (feelings). Each different aspect of human
beings is governed by its own a priori principles that are prescribed by a
distinct higher cognitive power (5:196). In the Critique of Judgment,
looking back on his philosophy as a whole, Kant uses a chart to show
how his entire transcendental philosophy can be understood in terms of
these different human faculties (5:198).4
Core aspect of Cognitive
A priori Applicati Relevant
the human
power that
principles on to
Critique
being
prescribes
principles for
it
Relevant
Question
Cognition
Understanding Lawfulne Nature
ss
Critique of What
Pure
can I
Reason
know?
(1781/17
87)
Feeling
Judgment
Purposive Art
-ness
Critique of What
Judgment may I
(1790)
hope?
Desire/
Reason
Final End Freedom Critique of What
Practical ought I
Reason
to do?
(1788)
Volition
II. What can I know?
The Critique of Pure Reason as transcendental anthropology of
cognition
4
The first four columns are taken directly from Kant's own work, though I’ve edited them and modified
terminology a bit. I’ve added the final two columns to show the connection with Kant's writings and his
central questions. As with most of Kant’s tidy charts, this one hides many complications (for instance, Kant
typically identifies his question “what may I hope?” with his writings on religion and not directly with the
Critique of Judgment), but it is helpful for a general overview.
19 Kant’s most famous and important work, the Critique of Pure
Reason, was published in 1781 after a “Silent Decade” during which he
published virtually nothing. The work was and is his magnum opus, the
work that defined him as a philosopher. Its specific focus is
anthropological in that it focuses on a particular human capacity:
“getting to the bottom of the faculty we call the understanding and . . .
the determination of the rules and boundaries of its use” (A xvi).
However, Kant is not interested here in the empirical question of how the
understanding operates, but in giving an account of the rules under
which it must operate and the limits that these rules imply for how far
we should seek to extend our knowledge. In the process, Kant aims to
answer the question “What can I know?” as that question applies
specifically to the “objective validity” of “a priori concepts” (A xvi), that is,
“what and how much can the understanding and reason cognize free of
all experience?” (A xvii). Through this transcendental anthropology of
cognition, Kant defends a metaphysics that consists in a priori claims
about the nature of the world and lays out an epistemology that limits
the scope of such claims.
For Kant, metaphysics involves “a priori synthetic” claims. An a
priori claim is one that is universal and necessary and thus not based
merely on empirical generalizations. Many a priori claims, however, such
as the claims that “bachelors are unmarried” or “a=a” merely unpack
concepts and do not tell anything substantive about the world. Kant calls
these sorts of empty claims “analytic” because they merely “analyze”
concepts, showing what is already contained within them. Other claims,
by contrast, are “synthetic” because they synthesize, or put together,
concepts that, in themselves, are distinct. The claims that “Hondas are
reliable” or “honey is sticky” are synthetic; reliability and stickiness are
not part of the definitions of Hondas and honey. Of course, those claims
are also empirical, rather than a priori. But there are some claims, such
as “every change has some cause,” that are both synthetic and a priori.
Here one does not merely define changes as having causes (because then
one could ask whether the ripening of fruit is really a “change” if there is
no obvious cause) but makes a contentful claim about all changes in the
world. But this claim is not based on empirically generalizing our
experience that all changes have causes. We have not actually observed
causes for every change; and were someone to claim that a particular
change lacked a cause, we would insist that the cause had simply not yet
been discovered.5 When we claim that every change has some cause, we
5
The development of modern quantum mechanics both problematizes and confirms this claim. On the one
hand, the dominant Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics does posit uncaused changes, or at
least changes that are undetermined by their causes. On the other hand, Einstein’s reaction to this
20 claim a necessary connection (hence, a priori) between distinct concepts
(hence, synthetic). The need for a metaphysics that is at once synthetic
and a priori raises “the general problem” of the Critique of Pure Reason:
“How are synthetic judgments possible a priori?” (B19, cf. Prolegomena to
any Future Metaphysics, 4:276).
Kant’s answer to this question depends upon conceiving of
metaphysics as a subset of transcendental anthropology. From the
beginning of his Critique, Kant makes clear how radically humancentered his metaphysics is, comparing the fundamental shift in thinking
embodied in this Critique to the revolution in astronomy effected by
Copernicus:
Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must conform
to objects; but all attempts to find out something about them a priori
through concepts that would extend our cognition have, on this
presupposition, come to nothing. Hence let us once try whether we do
not get farther with the problems of metaphysics by assuming that
the objects must conform to our cognition, which would agree better
with the requested possibility of an a priori cognition of them, which
is to establish something about objects before they are given to us.
This would be just like the first thoughts of Copernicus, who, when
he did not make good progress in the explanation of the celestial
motions if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around
the observer, tried to see if he might not have greater success if he
made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest. (Bxvi)
Kant’s reversal is as radical as Copernicus’s but moves in the opposite
direction. Astronomers before Copernicus thought of the earth – and
thus human beings – as the center of the universe. Copernicus’s radical
shift in perspective, describing the earth as just one of many planets
circling the sun, moves humans out of the center of the universe.
By contrast, Kant moves human cognition into the center of
metaphysics. He begins by isolating an assumption of prior metaphysics,
the assumption that in order to know anything about the world, our
judgments about the world have to conform to the way the world really
is. Kant claims that this assumption has made progress in metaphysics
impossible. Broadly speaking, previous philosophers – especially during
interpretation was precisely to argue that its proponents had simply failed to look hard enough to find the
relevant “hidden variables” (see Einstein 1935 and Bohr 1935). I discuss the relationship between
contemporary physics and Kant’s transcendental anthropology of cognition in chapter nine.
21 the 17th and 18th centuries6 – were either “rationalists” who sought
philosophical systems based upon reason alone or “empiricists” who
sought the ultimate foundations of knowledge in experience. But
empiricists fail to account for the aprioricity of metaphysics, while
rationalists fail to properly account for its synthetic status (by mistakenly
overestimating what reason alone can do). Kant’s Copernican turn is
based on the thought that empiricists and rationalists fail because both
are looking for a way to make human cognitions fit onto an
independently given world of objects. There is better hope of showing how
a priori synthetic judgments are possible if one assumes instead that the
world of objects must conform to the structure of human cognition.
Let us once try whether we do not get farther with the problems of
metaphysics by assuming that the objects must conform to our
cognition, which would agree better with the requested possibility of a
priori cognition of them, which is to establish something about
objects before they are given to us. (B xvi)
By assuming that the world must conform to our cognition, it is possible
to have knowledge of the world based on the structure of our cognition
rather than by induction from what we experience. By itself, this claim
does not get beyond merely analytic claims. The world must conform to
my cognition in that bachelors in the world must be unmarried, but to
get a priori substantive claims, Kant must do more.
Kant’s next move both limits the scope of this Copernican turn and
helps show how it functions to make substantive (or “synthetic”) a priori
knowledge possible. Kant claims that human cognition has both a
passive and an active component.
Our cognition arises from two fundamental sources in the mind, the
first of which is the reception of representations (the receptivity of
impressions), the second the faculty for cognizing an object by means
of these representations (spontaneity of concepts); through the former
an object is given to us, through the latter it is thought in relation to
that representation . . . If we call the receptivity of our mind to receive
representations insofar as it is affected in some way sensibility, then .
. . the faculty for bringing forth representations itself, or the
spontaneity of cognition, is the understanding. It comes along with
our nature that intuition [that through which cognition relates
immediately to an object] can never be other than sensible . . . The
6
In his “History of Pure Reason,” Kant traces the distinction between empiricists and rationalists back to
Aristotle and Plato (see A854/B882), but it is most commonly associated with the major empiricists
(Locke, Berkeley, and Hume) and rationalists (Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz) of the early modern period.
22 faculty for thinking of objects of sensible intuition, on the contrary, is
the understanding . . . Thoughts without content are empty,
intuitions without concepts are blind. (A50-1/B74-5, cf. A1920/B33-4)
Despite the deluge of technical terminology, Kant’s point here is simply
that humans’ thoughts about objects have two components, an active
component by which we think about objects, and a passive component by
which thoughts are about objects. When one merely thinks about
relations between concepts, one makes use of an active capacity for
thought, but this capacity is not directed towards any real objects. It is,
as Kant says, “empty.” And when one merely “takes in” the world without
actually conceptualizing it, one does not really see what one is exposed
to; one’s taking-in of the world is effectively “blind.” Knowledge of a real
world involves receiving “impressions” from the world and processing
them using one’s concepts.
Kant’s appeal to “intuitions”7 given through sensibility limits the
scope of the Copernican turn. Kant does not claim, and need not claim,
that everything about the empirical world is determined by the structure
of human cognition. Because we have a receptive faculty, humans have
knowledge we take from the world, such as the knowledge that there are
mountains in the Pacific Northwest of North America, that water freezes,
that dogs and cats cannot interbreed, that large material objects are
made of small molecules, etc. And there are other claims that are false,
but if true, would have to be discovered empirically, such as the
existence of the Loc Ness monster, or fairies, or solid crystalline spheres
rotating in the heavens. For such empirical knowledge, cognition must
conform to the world. The world will not have fairies in it just because we
believe in fairies, nor will it cease to have molecules if we cease to (or do
not yet) believe in molecules. Kant’s Copernican turn justifies the
possibility of some substantive a priori knowledge of the world, but it
does not justify claiming to know everything about the empirical world
simply by reflecting on one’s cognitive capacities.
But Kant also argues that the distinction between intuitions and
concepts (and relatedly between sensibility and the understanding)
provides for the possibility of a priori knowledge that goes beyond mere
conceptual analysis because even our receptivity to the world has an a
priori structure to which the world must conform.
7
Kant’s notion of an “intuition” is quite different from our contemporary use of the term to refer to
judgments of which one is immediately certain. For Kant, an intuition is “that through which [a cognition]
relates immediately to objects” (A19/B33). An intuition is thus something like an immediate, preconceptual, sensory awareness of an object.
23 I call that in the appearance which corresponds to sensation its
matter, but that which allows the manifold of appearance to be
intuited . . . I call the form of appearance. Since that within which the
sensations can alone be ordered and placed in a certain form cannot
itself be in turn sensation, the matter of all appearance is only given
us a posteriori, but its form must all lie ready for it in the mind a
priori. (A20/B34)
Humans’ capacities to be affected by the world have a particular
structure, and it should be possible to develop an a priori science of the
principles of this sensibility. Moreover, precisely because sensibility is a
faculty of intuitions rather than of concepts, an a priori science of
sensibility will not proceed simply by unpacking concepts, and thus may
provide a way of justifying claims that are both a priori and synthetic.
Kant’s approach is made clearer when he turns to the details,
where he argues that space and time are the two a priori intuitions that
structure all empirical intuitions. Both are a priori because we cannot
think of the world as non-spatial or non-temporal and because we could
never think of external objects without an already-given spatial structure
nor of succession without an already-given temporal structure. Both are
a priori intuitions, rather than concepts, because they are represented as
given structures within which particular objects appear, rather than as
constructed concepts under which objects fall.8 Kant reiterates the
status of space and time as a priori intuitions by pointing out that these
intuitions underlie the success of geometry (in the case of space) and
arithmetic (in the case of time), both of which give synthetic a priori
knowledge.9 In geometry, for example, one does not measure shapes to
discern their properties empirically, but one also does not merely analyze
the concepts of those shapes. Instead, one uses mental, spatial images
(or axioms about mental space) to connect concepts not already united
by definition. Thus, for example, we can know (without empirically
measuring every triangle in the world) that the sum of the interior angles
of any triangle makes two right angles, even though this fact is not
contained in the definition of a triangle. As an intuition, space is able to
ground synthetic claims. As an a priori intuition, it grounds these claims
a priori. “Thus,” Kant says, “our explanation alone makes the possibility
of geometry as a synthetic a priori cognition comprehensible” (A25/B41).
8
For these arguments, see A22-5/B37-40 (space) and A30-2/B46-8 (time). The precise details of these
arguments are controversial and the success of the arguments is contested. For discussion, see Allison
1983, Guyer 1987.
9
A25/B40-1.
24 The understanding, like sensibility, has an a priori structure, and
the heart of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason focuses on showing that the a
priori structure of the understanding is a necessary condition for the
possibility of experience. Kant’s argument for this claim is the most
difficult part of the Critique of Pure Reason, and Kant revised the
argument extensively between the first and second editions of the book.10
The essence of Kant’s argument is twofold. First, he looks to “logical
function of the understanding in judgments” for “the clue to the
discovery of all pure concepts of the understanding” (A70/B95). The
basic idea here is that once we are committed to seeing experience as a
product of the understanding, one can examine how the understanding
is used in constructing and relating judgments to discern fundamental
categories of the construction and relation of objects within experience.
Since the operation of the understanding with respect to judgments is
the provenance of a relatively straightforward logic, one can simply use
what Kant calls “general logic” as a clue to the transcendental
anthropology of the understanding. For example, Kant argues that
because all relationships within judgments must be either categorical (x
is y), hypothetical (if x, then y), or disjunctive (x or y), the understanding
must have corresponding a priori categories for cognizing objects.
Respectively, these are: inherence and subsistence (cognizing objects as
things with properties), cause and effect, and community (objects as
reciprocally interacting). Overall, Kant lays out a famous (or infamous)
table of twelve basic categories of the understanding, drawn from a
similar table of twelve functions of thinking.
Of Quantity
Unity
Plurality
Totality
Of Quality
Reality
Negation
10
For very good detailed studies of Kant’s key arguments here, see Allison 1983, Ameriks 2003, Guyer
1987, and Longuenesse 1997.
25 Limitation
Of Relation
Of Inherence and Subsistence (substantia et accidens)
Of Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)
Of Community (reciprocity between agent and patient)
Of Modality
Possibility – Impossibility
Existence – Non-existence
Necessity – Contingency
This table proposes only what the content of a priori categories of
the understanding would be; Kant still needs to show that experience
requires any such categories. In particular, given that objects are
presented in terms of spatial and temporal structures of sensibility, one
might wonder whether any further contribution from the understanding
is needed. For that purpose, Kant lays out a detailed argument for the
necessary role of the understanding in making cognition of objects
possible. The key move in this argument is Kant’s claim that experience
is possible only by virtue of a twofold “unity,” on the side of both the
“object” and the “apperception” of that object. Kant takes the term
“apperception” from Leibniz, for whom it referred to something like
explicit consciousness of an object as opposed to mere unconscious
awareness of it, the difference between hearing sounds when one is
asleep and listening to them when one is awake. For Kant,
“apperception” refers to “the ‘I think’ [that] must be able to accompany all
of my representations, for otherwise something would be represented in
me that could not be thought at all” (B131-2). Kant’s basic idea in this
section of the Critique is to connect experience of unified objects with a
unified “I think” and thereby with the categories, as the principles of any
such unity. First, Kant argues that in order for one to unite different
representations together into consciousness of a single object, those
different representations must be held together in a single
26 consciousness. To have a cognition of a purple cow, it will not do for one
person to have a representation of the color purple and another to have a
representation of a cow. These different representations, to be united into
a cognition of a single object, must be united by a single consciousness.
[C]ognitions . . . consist in the determinate relation of a given
representation to an object. But an object is that in the concept of
which the manifold of a given intuition is united. Now, however, all
unification of representations requires unity of consciousness.
Consequently the unity of consciousness is that which alone
constitutes the relation of representations to an object. (B 137)
The relevant unity of consciousness here is not that “subjective unity of
consciousness which is a determination of inner sense” (B139), that is, it
is not an introspective awareness of oneself as united throughout time.
Rather, the relevant unity is the from-within unity by virtue of which one
becomes conscious of and makes justifiable claims about objects in the
world.
Now just as the table of judgment provided Kant’s “clue” to
discovering a set of a priori categories, so he argues that we see, in the
form of judgment itself, a necessary appeal to this transcendental unity:
“a judgment is nothing other than the way to bring given cognitions to
the objective unity of apperception. That is the aim of the copula is in
them . . . For this word designates the relation of the representations to
the original apperception and its [apperception’s] necessary unity, even if
the judgment itself is empirical” (B 141-2). In other words, in making a
judgment such as “mangos are delicious,” one not only makes an
empirical claim about the world but implicitly asserts the necessary
unity of the I that holds together “mangos” and “delicious” in a single “I
think.” And now Kant comes to his punchline:
Therefore the manifold [of different representations], insofar as it is
given in one empirical intuition, is determined in regard to one of the
logical functions for judgment, by means of which . . . it is brought to
a consciousness in general. But . . . the categories are nothing other
than these very functions for judging, insofar as the manifold of a
given intuition is determined with regard to them. Thus the manifold
in a given intuition also necessarily stands under categories. (B 143)
Thus if, e.g., I make the empirical intuition of a house into perception
through apperception of its manifold, my ground is the necessary
unity of space . . . This same synthetic unity, however, if I abstract
27 from the form of space, has its seat in the understanding, . . . in the
category of quantity. (B162)
Our “apperception” of objects is unified through organizing various
representations together by means of a priori concepts of the
understanding such as unity, reality, or causation. Even spatial and
temporal properties of an object only become properties of an object when
subsumed together by the understanding, under concepts such as
“property (of a substance).” These a priori concepts, or categories, provide
a from-within structure by means of which a human knower can connect
representations in such a way that those representations remain part of
a single “I think,” and they provide the framework according to which a
mere “manifold” can become a coherent object of experience.
At this point, one clarificatory warning is needed lest one think
that Kant’s transcendental anthropology does (or claims) more than it
really does. Rene Descartes, too, emphasizes the importance of the “I
think,” claiming that he could be absolutely certain of the claim, “I think
therefore I am” and reasoning, even further, that the nature of the “I
think” implies the simplicity, unity, and ultimately immortality of the
human soul. For Kant, however, such inferences mistakenly treat the
transcendental unity of apperception that makes (empirical) cognition
possible as itself a possible object of (such) cognition. In his
transcendental deduction, Kant emphasizes that while the
“transcendental synthesis of the manifold” makes me conscious “that I
am,” it reveals neither what “I am in myself” nor how “I appear to myself”
(B157). Kant criticizes attempts to get from the formal requirements of
the “I think” to substantive claims about such an I, calling such attempts
“Paralogisms,” or invalid arguments (see A341/B399-A404/B431). For
example, the inference from the necessity of a unified “subject” of
thought to a unified thinking “substance” erroneously takes the formal
category of “subject” to have objective meaning, when “pure categories
(and among them also the category of substance) have in themselves no
objective significance . . . unless an intuition is subsumed under them”
(A348-9). Because one can have no intuition of the “I think” that unifies
all intuitions, the only possible objective cognition of oneself is of “our
own subject only as appearance,” and this is available “through inner
sense” (B156). And Kant argues in a “Refutation of [Cartesian] Idealism”
(B274-9) that knowledge of this empirical self is secondary to knowledge
of external objections, since “the determination of my existence in time is
possible only by means of . . . actual [persisting] things that I perceive
outside myself” (B 275). Kant’s appeal to the transcendental unity of
apperception is an explanation of cognition from-within, one that shows
that objective empirical cognition requires unifying one’s representations
28 by means of a priori categories. It thereby shows that the objective world
must be unified in that way, but it makes no objective claims about the
apperception that unified that world.
Having laid out the a priori structure of both sensibility and the
understanding, Kant turns to the way in which these two different
cognitive faculties work together to structure the world of experience. By
showing how humans’ a priori categories work with sensibility to
structure the empirical world, Kant’s “system of all principles of pure
understanding” provides the a priori metaphysics promised in his
Preface. The specific details of the various ways in which these faculties
combine is both complicated and contested, but one example (Kant’s best
known) is sufficient to give a sense for his general strategy. One of the
principles that Kant defends as a principle by which human beings
structure the objective world is that of cause and effect: “All alterations
occur in accordance with the law of the connection of cause and effect”
(B232). Kant’s argument proceeds by considering what is necessary in
order for a set of perceptions to be considered perceptions of alteration
(or, more generally, of something happening). Kant distinguishes between
merely subjective perceptions and objective experience. To have objective
experience, one must organize perceptions in accordance with categories.
But to have experience of objective alteration (succession), perceptions
must be ordered in accordance with the category of cause—effect. If
ordered using inherence—subsistence (seeing some perceptions as
properties of others) or community (seeing each perception as part of a
whole), the sequence of one’s perceptions would not refer to an objective
sequence, since objectively, one supposes that the properties of the thing
exist at the same time as the thing and one supposes all the parts of a
thing to exist at the same time.11 Given the Copernican turn, to say that
one must order perceptions in a certain way is just to say that the
11
Kant gives, as an example of a purely subjective sequence, the perception of a house, starting with the
roof, then the windows, then the door, and then the chimney. Here one doesn’t suppose that objectively
speaking there really is first a roof, then windows, then a door, etc. On the other hand, one might actually
suppose that the order of one’s perceptions does correspond to an objective order. For this, Kant gives the
example of a boat. One perceives a boat upstream, a boat midstream, and a boat downstream, and one
supposes not that these are different parts of a complicated stream-wide boat, but that in reality – that is,
objectively – the boat is moving. Kant then considers what sort of concepts one would have to impose on
one’s set of perceptions to order them in such a way that one considers their order objective. His answer is
that the perceptions would have to be thought of as though they have to occur in the order in which they do.
And this necessary sequence of perceptions must be according to some rule. But necessary sequence
according to a rule is just what one thinks of when one thinks of the relation between cause and effect. So if
one is to think of the order of perceptions order as referring to an objective order, one must impose the
concepts of cause and effect on those perceptions.
29 objects of those perceptions must in fact be ordered in that way. By
imposing an aspect of the structure of the human understanding – the
category of cause and effect – on the subjective flow of perceptions in
inner sense, human beings are able to perceive the world (and thereby
structure the world) as a series of causally determined changes.
Throughout his proofs – for the necessity of space, time, the
categories, and causation – Kant does not provide merely empirical
claims about human cognition. Consistent with his insistence on
transcendental anthropology, Kant looks at cognition from-within,
arguing that certain cognitive presuppositions are necessary conditions
of the possibility of justifying the claims that we make about the world.
Because, from-within, we take mathematics to be justified, we must
assume that space and time structure our world. Because we can make
justified empirical claims about objects, we must be organizing and
unifying the diffuse manifold of intuition into coherent cognitions. And
because some of this cognition is of objective succession, we must apply
categories of cause and effect to structure the world we experience. In the
end, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason provides a transcendental analysis of
human faculties of sensibility and understanding that elucidates their a
priori structure and the contributions of this structure to experience of
an objective world. Human beings for whom experience and a priori
synthetic judgments are possible are finite beings dependent upon
sensibility and also spontaneous free thinkers. Moreover, given Kant’s
Copernican turn, this transcendental anthropology provides both an
epistemology that delimits what we can know and a metaphysics, in that
the world itself must conform to the structures of human cognition.
Metaphysics and epistemology turn out, in Kant’s hands, to be reckoned
as (transcendental) anthropology.12
12
The radicality of Kant’s position here can be seen in one of the most famous criticisms of it. Bertrand
Russell critiques Kant’s account of a priori knowledge on the grounds that, among other things, Kant relies
on contingent facts about human nature. As Russell explains,
The thing to be accounted for is our certainty that the facts must always conform to logic and
arithmetic. To say that logic and arithmetic are contributed by us does not account for this. Our
nature is as much a fact of the existing world as anything, and there can be no certainty that it will
remain constant. It might happen, if Kant is right, that to-morrow our nature would so change as to
make two and two become five. This possibility seems never to have occurred to him. (Russell
1912/1998: 87)
Russell’s problem arises because Kant seems to ground the a priori necessity of truths of mathematics (and
even logic) on the conditions of possibility of our sensing and thinking about the world. Because we
humans perceive the world in Euclidian space and time and think about it using various logical categories,
30 With his analysis of the way in which sensibility and the
understanding combine to structure a knowable empirical world and his
defense of several specific a priori principles of human cognition to which
that empirical world must conform, Kant completes the first part of his
answer to the question “What can I know?” But Kant’s transcendental
anthropology of cognition involves two further elements as well. One of
these is not continued until a subsequent work. In his Metaphysical
Foundations of Natural Science, Kant argues that “natural science
presupposes . . . metaphysics of nature,” which includes not only the
“laws that make possible the concept of a nature in general,” laid out in
his Critique of Pure Reason, but also laws that “concern [themselves] with
a particular nature of this or that kind of things, for which an empirical
concept is given, but still in such a manner that, outside of what lies in
this concept, no other empirical principle is used for [their] cognition”
(4:469-70). The general idea is that the nature of the human mind is
such that if it cognizes, say, material bodies, then it will have to cognize
them in particular ways. Given the Copernican turn, these necessary
ways of cognizing would be a priori synthetic principles of material
bodies themselves. What this implies, for Kant, is that the basic
principles of physics itself can be seen as a sort of transcendental
anthropology of cognition. In Metaphysical Foundations of Natural
Science, Kant argues that given the barest concept of matter in motion,
one can derive a priori such claims as the conservation of matter (4:541),
the claim that all motion is relative to a particular frame of reference
(4:487), and Newton’s laws (e.g. that “every change in matter has an
external cause” (4:543) and “in all communication of motion, action and
reaction are always equal” (4:554)). For Kant, not only the most basic
metaphysical claims about the universe, but even its most basic physical
laws are a priori conditions of the possibility of experiencing nature. And
they are a priori conditions precisely because they reflect transcendental
structures of human cognition. For Kant, Newtonian physics is
transcendental anthropology.
The second further element comes in the second part of the
Critique of Pure Reason. There Kant turns from human sensibility and
truths of geometry, arithmetic, and logic must be true in any world that is a world for us. But, Russell
suggests, that makes these truths ultimately contingent upon human nature, and a truth that is contingent
upon human nature cannot be the sort of a priori – and hence necessary – truth that Kant sought in his
Critique of Pure Reason. (See Frierson 2009; Guyer 2006: 66-67, 81-2; and vanCleve 1999: 36-40 for
Kantian responses to Russell’s objection.)
31 understanding to human “reason.” The a priori forms of sensibility and
the understanding are “constitutive” of experience; the objective world is
constituted by conformity with these forms. Reason, by contrast,
presents ideals that regulate humans’ pursuit of knowledge but that are
not constitutive of that knowledge. In the context of this Critique reason
can be understood as that most philosophical of cognitive powers, the
one that constantly asks the question, “Why?” And in asking this
question, reason constantly seeks the “unconditioned,” that is, an
answer that does not itself require a further explanation. For Kant, this
search for the unconditioned plays itself out in every area of knowledge.
Reason prompts humans to seek the causes of phenomena in our world,
then the causes of these causes, and so on. It prompts us to look for the
constituent parts of the objects in our world, the constituent parts of
those, and so on. It prompts us to develop an idea of an ens realissimum,
a most real being whose perfection is not conditioned by anything. In
these ways and more, reason drives human knowers to discover more
and more about the world in which we live.
But with this regulative function of reason comes a dangerous
illusion, one that “does not cease even though it is uncovered and its
nullity is clearly seen into by transcendental criticism” (A297/B353, see
too Avii). Reason drives humans to learn more and more about their
world in a search for the unconditioned, but this impulse naturally
generates the illusion that an unconditioned is there to be found. As we
search for the smallest and most basic particle, or the first cause of the
universe, or the most perfect possible being, reason incites us to assume
that there is in fact a most basic particle, a first cause, or a perfect being.
The second half of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason focuses on showing why
these assumptions are unwarranted. The basic argument in each case is
that the conditions of possibility of objective cognition conflict with the
nature of the unconditioned, such that these ideal goals of reason are the
sorts of things that could never exist in a world structured by human
forms of intuition and understanding. While we should still make use of
reasons’ ideals as ideals guiding inquiry into the world of experience, we
cannot treat them as really existing in that world.
The details of these arguments are unnecessary in this brief
account of Kant’s transcendental anthropology, but it is worth looking at
one of Kant’s specific discussions: the third “antinomy of pure reason.”13
13
Kant does not introduce this discussion in the context of a discussion of human freedom. Instead, the
issue of freedom comes up in the context of thinking about whether, in general, “causality in accordance
with the laws of nature is . . . the only one from which all appearances . . . can be derived” (A444.B472),
but Kant quickly shifts to talking about the possibility of human freedom as a causality that grounds
32 In his antinomies, Kant shows that when one assumes that the ideals of
reason must apply to the objects of possible experience, it is possible to
prove contradictory positions on many of the most important questions
of metaphysics. The third antinomy starts by proving both that
“Causality in accordance with the laws of nature is not the only one . . .
It is also necessary to assume another causality through freedom”
(A444/B472) and that “There is no freedom, but everything in the world
happens solely in accordance with laws of nature” (A445/B473). The
proof of freedom appeals to reason’s need to seek the unconditioned and
argues that no explanation can be sufficient if conditioned by further
explanation. The argument against freedom draws on Kant’s defense of
universal causation in the second analogy (discussed above) to show that
there could never be a cause that was not itself the effect of a further
cause, since any act of causation would have to be an event in the world,
and every event must have a cause.
Kant’s “solution” to the antinomy involves two components, both of
which are important for understanding Kant’s transcendental
anthropology. Kant first draws attention to the merely regulative function
of ideals of reason. Insofar as the demand for sufficiency is a regulative
ideal, the empirical investigation of natural causes should constantly
seek a “sufficient” cause for any appearance by investigating causes as
far back as they will go. But any cause that one in fact finds will, by
virtue of being itself an appearance, call for investigation into its own
cause. Thus we must seek sufficiency in our explanations, but we will
never find it.
But Kant’s resolution of the third antinomy introduces a second
aspect of his transcendental philosophy which is crucial to
understanding Kant’s answer to the question “What is the human
being?” So far, my discussion of Kant’s transcendental anthropology of
cognition has focused on the positive contribution that this anthropology
can make towards a robust metaphysics of nature: given that our
empirical knowledge depends upon the structure of our sensibility and
understanding, we can prove important claims about the empirical world
a priori. But Kant points out that this positive contribution entails “a
very strange result . . ., namely, that with this faculty [of cognition] we
can never go beyond the boundaries of possible experience” (Bxx). We
can establish a priori claims about possible objects of experience, but we
cannot provide any theoretical justification for any claims about
unexperienceable things. Kant calls such things “things-in-themselves”
or “noumena” and distinguishes them from objects of possible
appearances in the world.
33 experience, which he calls phenomena. And throughout his
transcendental account of cognition, Kant reminds his readers that the
nature of human cognition determines only the way in which “objects” (of
possible experience) must be, not the way in which “things-inthemselves” must be. Thus, for example, when he proves a priori that the
world must be spatial-temporal, Kant claims,
Our expositions accordingly teach the reality (i.e. objective validity) of
space [and time] in regard to everything that can come before us
externally as an object, but at the same time the ideality of space in
regard to things when they are considered in themselves through
reason, i.e., without taking account of the constitution of our
sensibility. (A28/B44)
For something to be an empirical object, it must be presented to us
through sensibility. And since the structure of our sensibility is spatial,
all empirical objects must be spatial. But precisely because the spatiality
of empirical objects is due to our sensibility, we are not justified in saying
that such objects are spatial apart from human sensibility. The result is
that Kant’s metaphysics commits him to what he calls an “empirical
realism” but a “transcendental idealism.” His metaphysics is empirically
real because its claims (e.g. about causality) are necessarily true of the
empirical world. But it is transcendentally ideal because such claims are
limited to the empirical world and say nothing about what “things-inthemselves” – apart from human sensibility – might be like.
When Kant turns to the third antinomy, this transcendental
idealism does significant work. Consistent with the insights of his second
analogy, Kant insists that any objective alteration must be the result of
causes in accordance with natural laws. But he turns in his resolution to
the third antinomy to the question of “whether it is a correct disjunction
that every effect in the world must arise either from nature or freedom, or
whether instead both, each in a different relation, might be able to take
place simultaneously” (A336/B564). Given Kant’s transcendental
idealism, the law-governed causality of the empirical world does not
preclude a different kind of causality – freedom – operating at the level of
things-in-themselves:
[F]or a subject of the world of sense we would have first an empirical
character, through which its actions, as appearances, would stand
through and through in connection with other appearances in
accordance with constant natural laws . . . [and] second . . . an
intelligible character, through which it is indeed the cause of those
actions as appearances, but which does not stand under any
34 conditions of sensibility [including universal causation] and is not
itself [an empirical object]. (A539/B567)
This distinction between empirical and intelligible character makes it
possible for Kant to defend the possibility of what he calls
“transcendental freedom,”14 a power “of beginning a state from itself, the
causality of which does not in turn stand under another cause
determining it in . . . accordance with the law of nature” (A533/B561).
We cannot rule out the possibility that humans, as things-in-themselves,
have an intelligible character that is transcendentally free in this sense.
But this intelligible character can itself be the ground of an empirical
character, and one who observes this empirical character will be able to
trace empirical causes for any particular action.
The result is an initially shocking but ultimately quite plausible
account of the relationship between freedom and natural necessity, one
that distinguishes Kant’s account from the dominant accounts of
freedom and causal necessity both in his day and our own. Many
philosophers are “compatibilists,” who argue that freedom is compatible
with causal determination. Generally, compatibilists define freedom as
determination by internal, psychological causes rather than external
ones, such that if an action follows from my choice, it is free, even if my
choice is determined by external factors. Other philosophers defend
incompatibilism, the view that freedom and natural determination
conflict with one another. Such philosophers can be either “hard
determinists” who believe that every event in the world, including every
human choice and action, is causally determined by some set of prior
conditions15 and therefore argue that there is no room for any
meaningful kind of freedom, or “libertarians” who believe that (some)
events in the world are determined by human choices that these choices
are not in any sense determined by prior conditions.16 Kant’s position
has aptly been called a “compatibility of compatibilism and [libertarian]
incompatibilism” (Wood 1984: 74). Like incompatibilist libertarians, Kant
defines freedom in a way that excludes prior causal determination of
one’s choices, but like compatibilists, Kant believes that there is a way in
14
Kant’s terminology is somewhat misleading here because the freedom that Kant calls “transcendental” is
really “transcendent.” It is not a condition of the possibility of experience nor evident from-within
theoretical reasoning, but “transcends” any possible experience.
15
This is the dominant form of hard determinism among secular philosophers today. Other classic forms of
determinism (or “predestination”) claim that every event is determined by Fate or by God.
16
Among libertarians, some (e.g. Kane 1996, 2002) emphasize natural indeterminacy according to which
certain choices are undetermined natural events and others (e.g. vanInwagen 1986) emphasize “agent
causation,” where events that are undetermined by prior conditions are explained as being the effects of
agents who are responsible for them.
35 which one can assert both that something is freely caused and that
something is the result of prior empirical causes. What makes Kant
unique among contemporary theories is that he preserves a
thoroughgoing causal necessity but at the same time an undetermined
freedom. Kant’s transcendental idealism allows him to see free things-inthemselves as grounds of the empirical world, while his empirical realism
allows him to insist that within that empirical world, causation
universally proceeds according to natural laws.17
The Critique of Pure Reason, where Kant develops this account of
freedom, does not posit that such freedom is actual. This Critique focuses
on what can be known a priori about the objective world, the world as it
exists for human knowers. And what can be known about that world is
that every event, including every human action, is causally determined
by prior conditions in accordance with natural laws. Kant’s discussion of
freedom and causation is directed not only against those who argue for
the impossibility of freedom (say, on the basis of Newtonian physics), but
also against those who would claim that one can know that freedom
exists in the world. In the Critique of Pure Reason, the “single thing we
could accomplish and . . . our sole concern” is “to show that . . . nature
at least does not conflict with causality through freedom” (A558/B586).
The theory of freedom that Kant lays out in the first Critique is
thus presented as an option that metaphysics can neither establish nor
rule out, an “extension” that “even if . . . empty, . . . we . . . can fill
through practical data of reason” (Bxxi). And this sort of modesty shows
an important positive aspect of Kant’s limitations of metaphysics. After
noting how his account of cognition precludes metaphysical proofs about
things like God, humans’ immortal souls, and freedom, Kant insists that
while
a critique that limits . . . is, to be sure, to that extent negative, . . .
because it simultaneously removes an obstacle that limits or even
17
There are two dominant ways that Kantians interpret this position. So-called “two-world” theorists read
Kant as positing two metaphysically distinct “worlds,” a noumenal world of things-in-themselves and a
phenomenal world of appearances. The former includes humans insofar as we are free, the latter humans
insofar as we are determined. And the former is the “ground” of the latter. Alternatively, so-called “twostandpoint” theorists claim that Kant posits only a single world that can be thought of in two different ways,
as the sum of objects of possible experience or as a merely thinkable abstraction. When thinking of the
world in the former way, freedom is precluded, but not when thinking of it in the latter way. Because
morality requires thinking of ourselves as free (as we will see in the next section), the “merely thinkable”
perspective gets content as a practical perspective from which we hold ourselves responsible. Thus insofar
as human beings take an agent-standpoint on the world, we must view human beings as free. Insofar as we
take a scientific-observer standpoint, we must see everything (including human beings) as causally
determined.
36 threatens to wipe out the practical use of reason, this critique is also
in fact of positive and very important utility, as soon as we have
convinced ourselves that there is an absolutely necessary practical
use of pure reason (the moral use), in which reason unavoidably
extends itself beyond the boundaries of sensibility. (Bxxv)
Or, as he puts it much more succinctly later, “I had to deny knowledge in
order to make room for [practical] faith” (Bxxx). Given his Copernican
turn, Kant was able to use a transcendental anthropology of cognition to
justify not only epistemic claims about the nature of human knowledge
but even metaphysical claims about the nature of the empirical world.
But precisely because such claims are limited to objects of possible
experience, Kant makes room for non-empirical claims, if there is any
non-cognitive access that human beings have to things-in-themselves.
And Kant finds this non-cognitive access in another part of his
transcendental anthropology, the transcendental analysis of volition
wherein morality provides a non-cognitive role for reason in governing
human life.
III. What ought I to do?
Kant’s moral philosophy as transcendental anthropology of
volition
From the question “What can I know?” Kant turns to the question,
“What ought I to do?” While Kant’s transcendental analysis of cognition
focused on human beings as human beings as free but finite knowers,
Kant aims here to think about human beings as free but finite doers (or
37 agents). 18 As in the case of cognition, Kant focuses on human actions
“from-within,” and in particular explores both the norms governing
human action and the conditions of possibility of being governed by
those norms. Through laying out both the nature of action-guiding
norms and the conditions of possibility of being bound by these, Kant
offers insight – though not “knowledge” in the strict sense – into what
human beings are in themselves. In particular, Kant’s moral philosophy
completes the argument for human freedom by showing that such
freedom is not only possible, but actual19, and by laying out “laws of
freedom” that govern free human beings (G 4:387).20
18
Kant’s Groundwork might seem specifically to avoid developing ethics as a subset of anthropology: “a
law, if it is to hold morally, . . . must . . . hold not only for human beings, as if other rational beings did not
have to heed it . . . [T]herefore the ground of obligation here must not be sought in the nature of the human
being . . . but a priori simply in concepts of pure reason” (4:389, see too 4:410-12, 425). Kant is deeply
opposed to thinking of morality as a subset of human biology or psychology, explicitly rejecting
approaches to ethics that start with “conditions of human volition . . . drawn from psychology” (4:390-1).
Thus Groundwork discounts what Kant calls “practical” or “moral anthropology” as merely a subsidiary
part of ethics, one that “would deal only with the subjective conditions in human nature that hinder people
or help them in fulfilling the laws of a metaphysics of morals” (G4:388, MS 6:217). The core of morality,
Kant insists, must be “pure.” But this dismissal of anthropology at the core of morals is really only a
dismissal of empirical anthropology at that core. As Groundwork progresses, the centrality of the human
being as a free but finite chooser emerges clearly, as this section will show.
19
Both this “possibility” and “actuality” need to be interpreted carefully. Strictly speaking, the Critique of
Pure Reason did not show that human freedom was really possible, only that the fact that human beings as
they appear in the world are governed by natural laws does not necessarily preclude the possibility of
humans being free “noumenally” or “in themselves.” And, as we will see, the “actuality” that is established
in Kant's moral philosophy is, metaphysically speaking, not an actuality in the objective world (since the
“objective” world is a world of appearances), and epistemically speaking, not an actuality of which we can
have “knowledge” in Kant's strict sense.
20
Whereas Kant’s Critical treatment of the question “What can I know?” is concentrated in his Critique of
Pure Reason, his answer to “What should I do?” is scattered throughout several different texts. As early as
1765, Kant claimed to be working on a “Metaphysical First Principles of Practical Philosophy” (10:56) and
in 1768 he assured a former student (Herder) that his “Metaphysics of Morals” would be done within a year
(10:74). Later, he wrote that when he finished his “critique of pure reason” he would then develop his
“metaphysics of nature and metaphysics of morals” (10:145). A Metaphysics of Morals would, in fact, have
made a nice complement to the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, and Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason even suggests such a parallel (A841/B869). In fact, however, Kant’s first Critical work addressing
the question “What should I do?” was neither a Critique nor the promised Metaphysics of Morals but a
mere Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), in which Kant aims at “nothing more than the
search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality” (4:392). This work thus addresses the
question “What should I do?” only in the most general terms. Kant would subsequently write a Critique of
Practical Reason (1788), which recapitulates the overall claims of the Groundwork but greatly elaborates
the psychology and metaphysical implications that Kant sees as connected with this general moral theory.
Not until shortly before his death would Kant finally publish his long promised Metaphysics of Morals
(1797), in which he takes the general moral framework of the Groundwork and articulates a whole theory
of the most important political and ethical obligations of human beings. Throughout this section, I aim to
38 Kant’s argument for the actuality of freedom is based on the nature
of moral obligation. For Kant, the from-within standpoint of volition –
where one seeks to discern what one ought to do – has two important
features relevant to human freedom. First, anyone who asks, in the
broadest sense, what to do, “must regard itself as the author of its
principles independently of alien influences; consequently, . . . as the will
of a rational being it must be regarded of itself as free” (4:448). All choice
happens “under the idea of freedom” (4:448) because the “power of choice
. . . cannot be determined to action through any incentive except so far
as the human being has incorporated it into his maxim” (6:24). This
“Incorporation Thesis”21 claims that, from-within the standpoint of
deliberation, all inclinations and incentives appear only as candidate
reasons for action; one must “incorporate” them into one’s plans for
action before they actually motivate. From-within, one sees this
incorporation as something “free.”
For some contemporary Kantians, this analysis of the deliberative
perspective from-within is sufficient to establish human freedom, but
Kant worries that this argument does “not prove freedom as something
real” but only as a necessary but possibly illusory “presupposition”
(4:448-9). Thus Kant turns from the generic perspective of deliberation to
the more specific stance of one asking the question, “what ought I to do?”,
where “ought” is specifically moral. In the Critique of Practical Reason,
Kant insists that the moral “ought” is ever-present within human
practical deliberation: “the moral law, of which we become immediately
conscious (as soon as we draw up maxims of the will for ourselves), . . .
offers itself to us and . . . reason presents it as a determining ground not
to be outweighed by any sensible conditions and indeed quite
independent of them” (5:29-30, emphasis added). In the process of
devising and considering principles to act on, we become “immediately
conscious” of a “fact of reason” (5:29), the fact that we are bound by a
moral law, one that commands obedience regardless of other incentives.
This fact “forces itself upon us of itself as a synthetic a priori proposition
that is not based on any intuition” and not dependent upon reasoning to
obligation from any “antecedent data of reason” (5:31).
From this fact of reason, Kant aims to establish that human beings
are (transcendentally) free by showing that “a [transcendentally] free will
offer a synchronic account of Kant’s moral philosophy drawing from all of his “Critical” works (starting
with the Groundwork). In several cases, Kant’s positions on important issues in moral philosophy shifted
between these works, most notably with respect to his arguments for freedom and morality, but this section
ignores those changes. For discussion of some of them, see Ameriks 2003: 161-192.
21
The claim was given this label by Henry Allison. See Allison 1990: 5, 40.
39 and a will under moral laws are one and the same” (4:447, cf. 4:450,
5:28-9).22 In order to establish this mutual implication, Kant draws on
“common rational moral cognition” to “search for and establishment of
the supreme principle of morality” (4:392). What could the supreme
principle of morality be? To answer this question, Kant focuses on two
(related) features of the moral ought, its independence from inclination
and its universality. Moral reasons are distinguished from other sorts of
reasons in that they are not tied to things that one happens to find
oneself wanting. When one decides that one “should” buy gasoline for
one’s car, one does so only because one thinks that such an activity will
be conducive to ends that one happens to have. One can always decide to
forgo those ends, and then one need not buy gasoline. But when one
decides that one “ought” to refrain from falsely accusing an innocent
adversary or “ought” to help a stranger in immediate pressing need, one
does not see these decisions as optional in the same way. It does not
matter whether the false accusation fits with other goals that one has,
nor whether one cares about the stranger. Moral obligations do not
depend upon our inclinations. Kant puts this point in terms of a
distinction between what he calls “hypothetical imperatives,” which are
commands that one has to obey if one wants to achieve some particular
end, and “categorical imperatives,” which are (moral) commands that one
simply has to obey no matter what (no “if”-clause). Relatedly, Kant argues
that the moral law is universal: “everyone must grant that a law, if it is to
hold morally . . . must carry with it absolute necessity,” going so far as to
say that “the command ‘thou shalt not lie’ does not hold only for human
beings, as if other rational being did not have to heed it” (4:389). Kant’s
point here is not that everyone ought always act in the same way.
Someone who cannot swim need not jump into a river to save a drowning
child, and someone with remarkable artistic talents may have an
obligation to cultivate them that others would not have. The point,
rather, is that morality itself is universal, in that when one becomes
immediately conscious of obligation in general, one is conscious of it as a
law that binds everyone (even if it binds different people in different
ways).23 Another person who is relevantly similar to me (able to swim, or
possessed of similar talents) will have the same obligations. Unlike
22
Given this “circle” (4:450) or reciprocal implication (5:29), establishing either that one is under moral
laws or that one is free is sufficient to establish both. Although Kant initially (in the Groundwork) tries to
establish the validity of the moral law by first offering an independent and quasi-theoretical argument for
human freedom, his mature position is that we must first know the validity of the moral law, which is given
as a fact of reason and cannot be deduced from any prior knowledge, and only from our knowledge of this
fact of reason can we know that we are free.
23
This is most evident in applications of the moral law that are least situation-dependent, such as “do not
falsely promise,” since in this case, the particular moral requirement is universal as well.
40 inclinations, morality is not something that one can pick and choose. It
obligates everyone.
Given these characteristics of morality, one might think that it
would be impossible to derive a fundamental formula of morality. If all
that we know about morality in general is that it can derive from neither
particular inclinations nor contingent features of ourselves, then there
seems to be nothing left from which to get a “principle” of morality at all.
But in fact, Kant argues that the limitations on the content of the moral
law actually give rise to a “formula” that encapsulates the fundamental
principle of morality.
When I think of a hypothetical imperative in general I do not know
beforehand what it will contain; I do not know this until I am given
the condition [i.e., the end to be promoted]. But when I think of a
categorical imperative I know at once what it contains. For, since the
imperative contains, besides the law, only the necessity that the
maxim be in conformity with the law, while the law contains no
condition to which it would be limited, nothing is left with which the
maxim of action is to conform but the universality of a law as such;
and this conformity alone is what the imperative properly represents
as necessary.
There is, therefore, only a single categorical imperative and it is this:
act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the
same time will that it become a universal law. (4:420-1)
The moral law of which I am immediately conscious within deliberation is
a law that commands me to act only in such a way that the bases for my
actions – my “maxims” – could be bases for the actions of everyone. What
is universally commanded to all is the practice of acting in a way that
could be universal for all.
Kant goes on to redefine this categorical imperative based on a
particular feature of human willing: human beings not only follow
various practical laws, but also act for the sake of ends (4:427). Now the
moral law is not determined by any particular (contingent) ends, but it
does determine a necessary end, “something the existence of which in
itself has an absolute worth, something which as an end in itself could
be a ground of determinate laws” (4:428). And Kant finds just such an
end in “the human being” (4:428). This gives Kant a new way of
describing the categorical imperative:24 “So act that you use humanity,
24
For discussion of the relationship between the different formulations of the categorical imperative, see
Korsgaard 1996a and Wood 1999.
41 whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the
same time as an end, never merely as a means” (4:429, see too 6:462).
This new formulation of the moral law puts human beings at the center
of morals, not only in that the moral law is derived from a transcendental
anthropology of volition, but also in that the ultimate end of morality,
that which must at all times be respected, is nothing more (nor less) than
the human being.25
Finally, Kant adds another formulation of the categorical
imperative that further enriches his transcendental anthropology and
paves the way for his defense of human freedom. Kant insists that “the
human being is . . . subject only to laws given by himself . . . and is
bound only to act in conformity with his own will” (4:432). Kant describes
this independence from external laws as “autonomy” and points out that
this autonomy does not imply lawlessness, but rather that one is subject
always only to one’s own laws. This may seem to be merely a
recapitulation of the Incorporation Thesis, but Kant’s point here is more
specific. If the moral law is to be truly universal and independent of our
inclinations, then it cannot be derived from anything external to our will
itself. Any external command would need to appeal to us for some
reason, either because we feel inclined to obey it (in which case it is not
truly moral) or because we ought to obey it (in which case its authority
derives from rather than grounds morality). For moral laws to be truly
one’s own rather than merely results of outside influences manipulating
our contingent desires, autonomous lawgiving must proceed by means of
laws that have no basis other than our own wills. But laws determined
solely by our wills are categorical. So, for Kant, “autonomy of the will [is]
the supreme principle of morality” (4: 440).26
At this point, Kant has nearly proven that human beings are
transcendentally free. The principle of morality is a principle of
autonomy, or self-governance. But to make the stronger claim that this
“autonomy” is identical with transcendental freedom, Kant goes further.
He offers a quasi-geometric proof starting with the nature of moral
obligation and deriving the necessity of transcendental freedom. He poses
the following problem:
25
Precisely what Kant means by humanity here is hotly contested. See Dean 2006 and Frierson 2007.
Kant takes this argument one step further. The moral law is “the will of every rational being as a willing
giving universal law” (4: 431). But this universal sort of autonomy is tied, for Kant, to the fact that “a
rational being belongs as a member to a kingdom of ends when he gives universal laws in it but is also
himself subject to these laws” (4:433). Respect for humanity in oneself and others involves submitting
oneself only to laws that one legislates for oneself, but also legislating laws for oneself that one also, at the
same time, legislates for all rational agents. Thus human beings are not only autonomous, but autonomous
members of a kingdom of ends.
26
42 Supposing that the mere lawgiving form of maxims is the only
sufficient determining ground of a will: to find the constitution of a
will that is determinable by it alone. (5:28)
That is, Kant considers what sort of will could be determined by a moral
law that dictates only the “form” that one’s maxims must take and says
only that such maxims must be universalizable, without saying anything
about the “matter” of those maxims, that is, what sorts of goals one
should aim for in one’s actions. Kant argues,
Since the mere form of a law . . . is not an object of the senses and
consequently does not belong among appearances, . . . this form as
the determining ground of the will is distinct from all determining
grounds of events in nature . . ., [so] a will [determined by this
ground] must be thought as altogether independent of the law of
causality. (5:28-9)
From-within the standpoint of deliberation, when one considers whether
or not to act on the basis of the moral law, one precisely sees this law as
a law that offers nothing to one’s natural inclinations. There is, in that
sense, no “natural” basis for acting in accordance with it. When one
chooses to act on an ordinary inclination – say, deciding to eat an
appetizing cookie – one can see oneself as “giving in” to the flow of
natural causes. But because its demands are fundamentally formal, the
moral law is not the sort of thing that one can merely “give in” to. It
“presents it[self] as a determining ground not to be outweighed by any
sensible conditions and indeed quite independent of them” (5:29-30).
Thus the only will that can be truly bound by the moral law is a will that
is free from sensible (that is, empirical) conditions. But freedom from
determination by empirical conditions is precisely what transcendental
freedom is, so a will under the moral law is a transcendentally free will.
Kant decries any traditional form of compatibilism as “wretched
subterfuge” (5:96): “Psychological or comparative” freedom, where “free”
just means that “actions are caused from within,” is “nothing better than
the freedom of a turnspit” (5:96-7).
To his abstract argument and violent polemics, Kant adds a more
intuitive thought-experiment to show that when we reflect on actions
from-within, in terms of what we take ourselves to be capable of, even
apparently irresistible temptations are eminently resistible:
Suppose someone asserts of his lustful inclination that, when the
desired object and the opportunity are present, it is quite irresistible
to him; ask him whether, if a gallows were erected in front of the
43 house where he finds the opportunity and he would be hanged
immediately after gratifying his lust, he would not then control the
inclination. One need not conjecture very long what he would reply.
But ask him whether, if his prince demanded, on pain of the same
immediate execution, that he give false testimony against an
honorable man whom the prince would like to destroy under a
plausible pretext, he would consider it possible to overcome his love
of life, however great it might be. He would perhaps not venture to
assert whether he would do it or not, but he must admit without
hesitation that it would be possible for him. (5:30).
The first part of this thought-experiment shows only that human beings
are capable of overcoming particular sensuous desires (such as lust)
when the fulfillment of these threatens more important sensuous desires
(such as love of life). But the second part shows that human beings
recognize in themselves an ability to overcome even love of life for the
sake of the moral law. If our love of life can motivate us to overcome our
everyday sensuous desires, and our respect for the moral law can
motivate us to overcome even our love of life, then there is no temptation
that we are unable to overcome for the sake of the moral law.
Importantly, Kant is not denying that, from-without, our actions
have empirical causes. Even consciousness of the moral law appears as
an empirical cause in a chain of mental events that gives rise to a volition
to act in accordance with it. But from-within volition, we become aware
of a sense of responsibility the condition of possibility of which is the
transcendental freedom that, properly understood, Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason showed to be compatible with causal-determinist explanations
from-without. Through examining the moral law present from-within in
human volition, Kant shows that humans are transcendentally free and
thus “fills the vacant space” (5:49) left open by his theoretical philosophy.
But Kant does more. By specifying the most fundamental principle of
morality, Kant fills this vacant place “with a determinate law of . . . an
intelligible world . . ., namely the moral law” (5:49). That is, Kant shows
not only that human beings are free, but also that human freedom is not
lawless and arbitrary but a law-governed capacity to be moral.27
27
Just as Kant showed that the moral law implies freedom, he also shows that freedom implies morality.
The point here is that if we think about what a law of freedom must be, we know that we cannot derive
such a law from anything about what our natural motives and interests happen to be, since these are all
determined by laws of nature. But we also know that any law of freedom, precisely because it is not based
on contingent empirical details, will be the same for all rational agents. And so, for Kant, the “content” of
the moral law is simply putting these formal criteria of morality into the form of a principle governing the
44 Humans’ sense of moral obligation, properly understood, provides
evidence of freedom and also gives rise to a specific principle of morality.
Kant’s arguments for transcendental freedom as central to human
nature are hardly beyond controversy,28 and the rest of this section
focuses on two key problems that arise for the Kantian account of
freedom and morality offered so far. The first problem is this: if human
beings are really free only insofar as we submit to the moral law, Kant
seems unable to account for the possibility of human beings ever being
responsible for doing what is morally wrong (see, e.g. Sidgwick 1901 and
Reinhold 2006). If the moral law is the law of freedom, then whenever
human beings act contrarily to the moral law, they must not really be
free. But freedom is a condition of possibility of moral responsibility, so
whenever human beings act wrongly, they are seemingly not morally
responsible for their actions. Kant does claim that human beings can be
held responsible for acting badly,29 but how can he do this? Second,
given that Kant’s transcendental anthropology of desire is intended not
merely to lay out the conditions of possibility of moral responsibility but
also to clarify precisely what, from the standpoint of deliberation,
humans find themselves obligated to do. But if Kant’s moral philosophy
is supposed to answer the question, “What ought I to do?,” the mere
formula of universal law (FUL) – “act only in accordance with that maxim
through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal
law” (4:421) – seems too abstract to provide real guidance for action.
Regarding the first problem, as important as freedom is to his
transcendental anthropology, Kant recognizes that human choosers are
not merely morally free beings. Even from-within the perspective of
human volition, we find ourselves to be both free beings subject to the
moral law and members of the sensible world, subject to empiricallyinformed desires and inclinations. Even Kant’s “pure moral philosophy”
articulates what morality means for beings like us, who participate in
will: whatever you do, make it the kind of thing that could be done from freedom, that is, that could be a
law for anyone.
28
Among the problems with the argument that I do not discuss in detail here: (1) Kant’s appeal to a “fact of
reason” makes the argument ineffective against true moral skeptics. (2) Compatibilist freedom is, today,
generally considered in much better shape than Kant’s polemics allow, and even many of Kant’s supporters
think that his moral theory can do without a strongly metaphysical account of transcendental freedom. (3)
Kant’s account of the relation between freedom and morality poses specific problems for making sense of
how finite free beings like ourselves can be bound by the moral law; if humans as empirical entities in the
world are bound by natural, causal laws, how would we ever recognize the free submission of a human
being to morality? Later chapters discuss compatibilism (chapter eight) and the empirical expression of
morally good action (chapter two).
29
We examine this claim in detail in chapter three.
45 both an intelligible world governed by laws of freedom and a sensible
world governed by laws of nature.30 Because of our sensible nature,
human beings have various natural inclinations that can conflict with
the demands of the moral law in particular circumstances.31 It is
because we have such non-moral inclinations that morality takes the
form, for us, of “duties” and “imperatives,” commands that we ought to
obey rather than a moral law that we simply do obey (4:413).
In that context, Kant distinguishes between “positive” and
“negative” freedom.32 Negative freedom is a “property in us . . . of not
being necessitated to act through any sensible determining grounds”
(6:226, cf. 4:446), while positive freedom is the property of acting through
a non-sensible determining ground, the moral law (G 4:446-7, MM
6:213-14). The former, negative freedom, is necessary in order to hold
human beings morally responsible, while the latter, positive freedom, is
what constitutes the full-blown autonomy of a morally good agent. Too
sharp a line between these two sorts of freedom would undermine moral
autonomy. If negative freedom is not identical to positive freedom, why
should we see the moral law as arising from the free choice that makes
us morally responsible? Why see the moral law as any less alien to our
(negatively) free selves than natural causes? In response, Kant argues for
an intrinsic link between negative and positive freedom. Insofar as
negative freedom is a freedom from having one’s actions governed by
anything external to oneself, the only way to remain free is to make one’s
law the law of freedom, the categorical imperative. As one commentator
has put it, “by making the [categorical imperative] its principle, the free
will retains the position of [freedom]” (Korsgaard 1996a:166, cf. 6:227).
By contrast, “the free will that puts inclination above morality sacrifices
its freedom for nothing” (Korsgaard 1996a:167). Not only does (negative)
freedom make morality possible by freeing us from inclination, but the
moral law itself is identical with the internal constitutive standards of
freedom. Because the moral law specifies nothing other than the
30
Thus while Kant’s Groundwork begins by discussing the “good will” in general, which belongs to God
and can also belong to human agents, Kant quickly specifies the nature of this will in such as way that it
applies more particularly to human wills: “we shall set before ourselves the concept of . . . a good will
though under certain subjective limitations and hindrances” (4:397).
31
In his Groundwork and Critique of Practical Reason, Kant names the comprehensive satisfaction of these
interests “happiness,” and he explains that human beings are always tempted by a “principle of self-love”
rooted in our sensible nature, a principle that ought to be – but isn’t always in fact – restricted by the moral
law rooted in our free, rational nature. The scope of natural inclinations is very broad, such that even such
things as a natural philanthropy that “finds an inner satisfaction in spreading joy” (4:398) is a merely
natural inclination. “Self-love” has different forms.
32
This distinction is often linked with Kant’s distinction between the “will” (German Wille) and “choice”
(German Willkühr). The will, which Kant identifies with “practical reason,” has positive freedom. “Choice”
is the human capacity by virtue of which we have negative freedom.
46 condition of freedom, choice based on any other principle limits rather
than reaffirms freedom. Human beings are always negatively free, in that
we need not let our actions be determined by forces external to us, but
we are not always positively free, since we often relinquish autonomy in
the face of temptation.
The second problem, as Hegel classically put it, accuses Kant’s
categorical imperative of being an “empty formalism,” an “abstract
universality, whose determination is . . . without content” (Hegel
1991:162). Precisely because this “specific principle of morality” is purely
formal, it gives only the most abstract account of what is required of
human beings. In order to complete his account of the norms that ought
to govern human volition, Kant must deliver a more complete framework
of normative constraints on human volition. Hegel and others have
argued that this will require “bringing in material from outside [to] arrive
at particular duties [because] it is impossible to make the transition to . .
. particular duties . . . from the determination of duty as absence of
contradiction . . . with itself.” 33 Kant’s abstract moral law seems
insufficient to provide moral content from within.
Kant has a two-fold way of dealing with Hegel’s empty formalism
objection. First, even if the categorical imperative is, in itself, an empty
formalism, it can still be action-guiding in an important way. Hegel
suggests that the categorical imperative would only prohibit the stealing
of property, for example, if one has independent bases for thinking that
property rights are good. But insofar as one tests maxims for action, one
can evaluate those maxims based on the values implicit within them,
without ascribing any independent normative weight to those values.
Thus the thief who acts on the maxim, “I will steal my neighbor’s car in
order to have it for myself,” commits herself to the value of private
property by virtue of her end (having it for herself), and thus her maxim
conflicts with the categorical imperative. The native Hawaiians who acted
on the maxim “We will take the iron nails out of the bottom of that ship
in order to make spears” did not violate the categorical imperative (at
least not directly34) because their maxim implied a commitment to the
value of spears over ships, but not any direct commitment to institutions
of private property. And to this extent, at least, even if the categorical
imperative is insufficient for evaluating the moral status of actions, it
does seem to be an important way of picking out certain maxims that,
because they require making an exception of oneself, are morally wrong.
33
Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, Cambridge 1991, § 135, p. 162.
Kant does argue that a commitment to private property is implied by any external use of one’s freedom,
so the native Hawaiian’s maxims imply, for Kant, an indirect commitment to private property.
34
47 Second, Kant’s emphasis in Groundwork on pure moral philosophy
is explicitly only a foundation for a complete “metaphysics of morals.”
Just as the empirical concept of matter is needed to move from the
metaphysics of the Critique of Pure Reason to the basic principles of
physics, empirical attributes of human beings are needed to move from a
general principle of morals to specific moral duties. As the particular
kinds of embodied, finite agents that human beings are, we have specific
talents, needs, strengths and limitations that give rise to specific duties.
The normative force of these duties comes from their connection to the
fundamental moral principle by virtue of which human beings are
rational, free, autonomous agents. But the specific content comes from
the way that we must act in order for our empirically discoverable needs
and desires to be satisfied through acting on maxims that conform to
that fundamental moral principle (6:217).
The result, when Kant turns to his Metaphysics of Morals, is a
detailed account of human obligations in the face of our finite natures.
First, Kant points out that for embodied free beings, freedom manifests
itself through actions in an empirical world. From this empirical claim,
Kant arrives at his “universal principle of right”:
Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in
accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of
choice of each can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance
with a universal law. If then my action or my condition generally can
coexist with the freedom of everyone else in accordance with
universal law, whoever hinders me in it does me wrong. (6:230)
Interfering with another’s activity or condition is wrong, unless that
other’s activity or condition is itself wrong. This general principle of noninterference involves translating Kant’s general formula of universal law
specifically in terms of human actions rather than maxims, and it
grounds what becomes Kant’s political theory. Political “coercion that is
opposed to [wrong actions]” is justified as a “hindrance to a hindrance of
freedom” (6:231), and Kant specifies political rights based on increasingly
detailed empirical descriptions of human beings, ranging from the need
for private property rights (since human beings depend upon external
goods to exercise their freedom) to parental rights and duties (because of
the vulnerability of children). The result is a detailed Doctrine of Right,
which lays out actions that not only are required or prohibited by the
moral law but also ought to be required or prohibited by enforceable
political laws.
48 Second, given the structure of human volition, which always acts
for the sake of ends, there must be “ends that are also duties” (6:385).
Because humans are dependent upon their own abilities and those of
others to accomplish any ends at all, we have obligations both to
promote our own abilities (for the sake of accomplishing whatever future
goals we might find ourselves to have) and to use our abilities to help
others accomplish their ends (since we, like them, are dependent upon
others’ assistance).35 From the individual abilities that we can improve in
our own case, Kant derives duties prohibiting such things as suicide and
lying and requiring such things as self-examination and the deliberate
cultivation of “powers of spirit, mind, and body” (6:444). From our
obligation to make the happiness of others an end, he derives virtues
such as beneficence and gratitude and vices such as arrogance, ridicule,
and contempt. Kant goes on to discuss friendship as “the most intimate
union of love with respect” (6:469f.) and to mention duties that arise
from specific, empirically-given “differences in rank, age, sex, health,
prosperity or poverty, and so forth” (6:469).
In the end, Kant’s transcendental anthropology of desire offers a
detailed answer to the question “What ought I to do?” and in the process
further expands on the conception of human beings as free and finite
beings that Kant began in the Critique of Pure Reason. Not only are we
free and finite doers as well as knowers, but because transcendental
freedom is a condition of possibility of the moral obligation under which
we find ourselves from-within the standpoint of choice, we can justifiably
believe that humans are transcendentally free things-in-themselves, even
though we can never strictly “know” this. Kant’s promise in the first
Critique that he would “deny knowledge to make room for faith” (B xxx) is
fulfilled in his moral philosophy. In the process, the “faith” for which he
held out hope in the Critique is shown to be not a blind faith, but a solid
conviction grounded in rational arguments based on the conditions of
possibility of moral responsibility. Kant calls such morally-grounded
beliefs “postulates” and says,
35
We do not have a “duty” to promote our own happiness since this is something “everyone already wants
unavoidably” (6:386), and Kant (confusingly) argues that we do not have a duty to promote others
“perfection” since such perfection “consists just in this: that he himself is able to set his end in accordance
with his own concepts of duty” (6:386). This is confusing, since Kant generally uses “perfection” to refer to
nonmoral as well as moral perfections, and it is not clear that, for instance, developing a better memory
requires developing that memory for oneself. But this confusion is relatively benign; insofar as perfections
are non-moral abilities to achieve ends, the obligation to promote others’ happiness includes an obligation
to promote their perfections. Insofar as “perfection” is specifically moral and thus not necessarily linked to
(earthly) happiness, his reason for excluding it applies.
49 All of them proceed form the principle of morality, . . . [which]
requires these necessary conditions [such as freedom] for the
observance of its precept. These postulates are not theoretical
dogmas but presuppositions having a necessarily practical reference
and thus, although they do not indeed extend speculative cognition,
they give objective reality to the ideas of speculative reason . . . (by
means of their reference to what is practical) and justify holding
concepts even the possibility of which it could not otherwise presume
to affirm. (5:132)
Kant even claims that this morally-grounded faith has a sort of “primacy”
(5:119) over knowledge one has through empirical cognition; one’s
theoretical reasoning about the world must “accept” the postulates “as
soon as these propositions belong inseparably to the practical interest of
pure reason” (5:121). The transcendental anthropology of desire fills in
the otherwise “vacant space” for freedom left by human cognition (5:49,
103).
Before closing this section, it is worth attending to one further,
dramatic aspect of Kant’s transcendental anthropology of desire. In the
Critique of Pure Reason, Kant had highlighted three traditional problems
of metaphysics that would be stricken from the realm of knowledge –
“God, freedom, and immortality” (Bxxx, A3/B7) – and in his
transcendental anthropology of volition, Kant comes back not only to
freedom but to the issues of God and immortality as well. As in the case
of freedom (though to a different degree), Kant argues that belief in God
and immortality are practically necessary. Neither God nor immortality
are conditions of the possibility of moral responsibility per se, but when
Kant considers what the ultimate goal of a virtuous agent must be, he
argues that while the “supreme end” will be virtue alone, the “complete”
end – that end from which nothing good is absent – must include both
virtue and “happiness distributed in . . . proportion to morality” (5: 110).
The reason for this is not that the agent merely wants happiness, but
that “an impartial reason” could not deliberately choose a world within
which some beings “need happiness, [and are] worthy of it, and yet [do]
not participate in it” (5:110). Insofar as virtuous agents seek this highest
good, they must believe in whatever is necessary in order for their
activity to reasonably be held to contribute to this highest good. For
Kant, immortality is necessary because virtue can never be fully realized
in one’s finite life but only in endless progress (5:122). God is necessary
in order to ensure that happiness is doled out in proportion to virtue
(5:124ff.). Only by believing in both God and immortality can our efforts
towards virtue be reasonably taken to be efforts towards the complete
highest good.
50 Kant’s arguments for God and immortality are more complicated
that I have suggested here, and their validity is widely disputed. For the
purposes of understanding Kant’s conception of human beings, the
details of these arguments are less important than the overall implication
of Kant’s approach. Just as Kant in the Metaphysics of Natural Science
makes Newtonian physics a subset of a transcendental anthropology of
cognition, he here makes traditional theology a subset of a
transcendental anthropology of volition. By the end of his transcendental
anthropology of cognition, Kant had shown that the a priori structure of
human cognition establishes (among other things) our ability to know an
empirical world as consisting of substances in causal relationships with
one another, and he offers a priori foundations for natural science.
Having added a transcendental anthropology of volition, Kant has laid
out the a priori laws governing the realm of free human agents and
defended even God’s existence as part of a philosophical anthropology.
IV. What may I hope?
The Critique of Judgment as transcendental anthropology of
feeling
Given the results of the previous two sections, Kant’s
transcendental anthropology might seem complete. Human beings are
free, finite knowers and doers, governed within each realm by a priori
laws that we give ourselves. We exist as both fully free things-inourselves and finite, embodied appearances in the empirical world.
Within the empirical world, we see ourselves and everything else as
governed by natural laws. As free, we are governed by moral laws. Kant’s
first and second questions – about knowledge and obligation – have been
answered, and the question “What may I hope?” seems answered by
Kant’s practical postulates of God and immortality.36 Nonetheless,
shortly after finishing his Critique of Practical Reason, Kant set to work
on a third Critique, which would eventually become the Critique of
Judgment and would provide the a priori laws of feeling that could
complete his transcendental anthropology. By this time, Kant had made
36
For a long time, in fact, Kant took his transcendental anthropologies of cognition and desire to complete
his transcendental philosophy as whole and specifically “thought it impossible” to find a priori principles
for the faculty of feeling (A21), and Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason seemed to include analyses of “the
logical functions of the understanding in judgments” (A70/B95) and a “transcendental doctrine of the
power of judgment” (A137/B176), so a specific critique of judgment seemed out of place.
51 three realizations that required a rethinking of the nature of this
anthropology.
First, Kant came to see that his earlier rejection of feeling as a
faculty capable of transcendental investigation was mistaken. Kant had
rightly seen that the pleasures that humans take in what is merely
“agreeable” – food, sex, reputation, baseball – are empirically rooted and
thus incapable of a priori investigation. But as he continued to teach and
study aesthetics, he came to see that judgments that something is
beautiful or sublime are at once subjective because rooted in feeling and
taken to be universal and normative; to claim that something is beautiful
is to claim that all others should find it beautiful. Normativity, perhaps
even of an a priori sort, is applicable to aesthetic feeling. Second, Kant
recognized that his account of the cognition of nature was incomplete in
its application to the empirical world. His Critique of Pure Reason
ensured that the world would conform to certain general structures of
human cognition, but it provided no assurance that humans would be
able to expand the scope of their knowledge in any systematic way.
Finally, Kant’s moral philosophy was incomplete in its application to the
empirical world. The Critique of Practical Reason provided an a priori
argument to show that the end human beings are obligated to promote –
the highest good – is possible, but it provided no basis for this possibility
in the observable order of nature. Kant’s attempt to “deny knowledge in
order to make room for belief” was insufficient to explain how nature and
freedom relate to each other. He needed a Critique of Judgment to provide
a “mediating concept between the concepts of nature and the concept of
freedom, which makes possible the transition from the purely theoretical
to the purely practical, from lawfulness in accordance with the former to
the final end in accordance with the latter” (5:196, cf. 5:176). Kant came
to see his accounts of cognition and of volition as insufficient in their
application to the empirical world, and he lost his early pessimism about
the possibility of a transcendental (a priori, normative, from-within)
analysis of feeling. These realizations led Kant to complete his
transcendental anthropology with a Critique of Judgment that would
investigate the faculty of feeling through the power of judgment.
The general structure of the Critique of Judgment can seem
perplexing, since it is divided into two halves that seem, at first blush,
unrelated.37 The first half – a “Critique of Aesthetic Judgment” – explores
conditions of possibility of making justified aesthetic judgments about
37
For a defense of the claim that they are not significantly related, see MacFarland 1974. For a detailed
reading of the Critique of Judgment as a coherent whole, see Zuckert 2007.
52 beauty or sublimity. The second half – a “Critique of Teleological
Judgment” – lays out Kant’s philosophy of biology, within which Kant
argues that for the study of living things, one must make use of
teleological principles in addition to the laws of mechanical causation
defended in his Critique of Pure Reason and Metaphysics Foundations of
Natural Science. Moreover, while the “Critique of Aesthetic Judgment”
focuses on laying out an a priori principle that governs the faculty of
feeling, there is no direct reference to feeling in the “Critique of
Teleological Judgment.” And while the “Critique of Teleological
Judgment,” especially with its discussion of the ultimate and final ends
of nature, provides a transcendentally-grounded framework for
answering the question “What may I hope?,” the analysis of the beautiful
and sublime seems irrelevant to answering that question. All of this can
make it seem that however helpful this book might be in other respects,
it cannot provide a unified transcendental anthropology of feeling that
would complete Kant’s philosophy.
In fact, however, the book as a whole is unified by the principle of
the purposiveness of nature, an a priori principle of judgment that
provides a basis for universal norms governing feeling. Purposiveness
emerges as an a priori principle of judgment in the context of Kant’s
transcendental anthropology of aesthetic feeling, or taste (20:244). But
this a priori principle can be applied more widely than merely to govern
aesthetic feeling:
once the capacity of the power of judgment to institute a priori
principles for itself is granted, then it is also necessary to determine
the scope of this capacity, and for this completeness in critique it is
required that its aesthetic faculty be recognized as contained in one
faculty together with the teleological and as resting on the same
principle, for the teleological judgment about things in nature also
belongs, just as much as the aesthetic, to the reflecting power of
judgment. (20:244)
Moreover, once purposiveness is established as an a priori principle,
Kant can use it to address the insufficiencies of his transcendental
accounts of cognition and volition. What starts in a transcendental
anthropology of (aesthetic) feeling becomes the unifying principle of
Kant’s transcendental anthropology as a whole and the basis for
answering the final question of Kant’s philosophy: “What may I hope?”38
38
Ultimately, answering this question depends upon Kant’s philosophy of religion and history as well, but
the Critique of Judgment provides at least a partial basis for this answer.
53 Before unpacking the details of this account, we should address
the question of whether a transcendental anthropology of feeling is even
appropriate. Recall that transcendental anthropology has at least three
distinctive features: it is a priori, investigates humans from-within, and
emphasizes normative constraints. Human feelings seem ill-suited to any
of these sorts of analyses. Of all aspects of human life, feelings seem to
be the most empirically contingent. And even though we can
introspectively examine our feelings, there does not seem to be the sort of
“from-within” relationship to feeling that we have with cognition and
desire. Whereas we actively think and choose, feelings seem to be things
that just happen to us. This point is tied to the final one; Kant’s “fromwithin” perspective is fundamentally normative, not a matter of how
things seem to us but a matter of how we govern ourselves in thought or
choice. And normativity does not seem appropriate to feeling; it is at least
a bit odd to say that a person felt wrongly. And even if there is some sort
of normativity governing feelings, it does not seem a priori. It seems that
any anthropology of feeling should be empirical, a matter of introspection
into what one does feel in various circumstances and observation of the
feelings of others, with perhaps some prudentially-normative guidelines
based on what makes for a good human life or some moral restrictions
ultimately traceable to the moral principle at the heart of Kant’s
transcendental anthropology of volition.
Kant raises many of these concerns himself. He points out that
while there are “empirically knowable” connections between objects and
natural feelings of pleasure that give rise to desires for those objects,
such connections are “not grounded in any principle a priori” and thus
do not provide suitable material for a transcendental anthropology of
feeling (20:206, cf. A21). (Kant calls the objects of these pleasures
“agreeable.”) Other objects might give rise to pleasure because they are
useful in some way, and one takes pleasure in their suitability to some
end. Such objects please because they are “good-for” something and their
pleasure will be based in empirically knowable connections between
those objects and the ends for which they are good. There is also respect
for the moral law, which is both a feeling and required a priori, but it is
required only by virtue of its connection with volition. The necessity of
respect does not require a “special . . . critique of the feeling of pleasure
and displeasure” but can be subsumed under a transcendental
anthropology of volition (as Kant does in the Critique of Practical Reason).
In fact, pleasure in both the agreeable and the good (whether useful or
moral) can be explained by reference to the faculty of desire (or volition).
Agreeable objects are the goals of hypothetical imperatives; the
gratification we find in them “arouses inclination” (5:207). Useful objects
54 are the necessary or helpful means to some given ends, so they provide
satisfaction “only as a means” (5:207). And the morally good is the object
of the categorical imperative; we feel satisfaction in the morally good
because of its connection to volition.
But Kant suggests that some pleasures are due to neither
agreeableness nor goodness in their objects. These pleasures, for Kant,
are judgments of “taste” or of “aesthetic pleasure” and have for their
objects things that are “beautiful” or “sublime.” Kant’s primary focus is
on the beautiful, and he structures his transcendental analysis of beauty
around several key claims about how pleasure in the beautiful presents
itself to us from-within: it is disinterested (5:204-211), it is nonconceptually universal and necessary (5:211-219, 5:235-40), and it
presents its object as purposive without a purpose (5:219-235). For these
sorts of pleasures, Kant argues, an a priori principle is both needed and
available.
Kant’s first claim – that aesthetic pleasure is disinterested – merely
emphasizes that beautiful objects are neither agreeable nor good and
thus cause pleasure without connection to “interest” (that is, without
arousing volition). To judge “whether something is beautiful” we consider
it within the standpoint of “mere contemplation,” and from that
standpoint, “one only wants to know whether the mere representation of
the object is accompanied by satisfaction in me, however indifferent I
might be with regard to the existence of the object” (5:204-5). For
example, if I want to know whether “the palace that I see before me [is]
beautiful,” I need know only whether the mere contemplation of it brings
pleasure, even if, “were I to find myself on an uninhabited island . . . and
could conjure up such a magnificent structure through my mere wish, I
would not even take the trouble of doing so” (5:204-5, cf. 29:877-8).
The second claim brings up central dilemma that drives Kant’s
analysis, the “reason why judgments of taste are subject to a critique
with regard to their possibility” (5:191). Aesthetic judgments involve “not
an empirical concept but rather a feeling of pleasure . . . which . . . is
nevertheless to be expected of everyone” (5:191). For Kant, when one
judges that some object is “beautiful” or “sublime,” one does not ascribe
to that object anything that can be expressed in general concepts; one
claims only that the object gives rise to a certain kind of pleasure. But
one nonetheless takes one’s judgment to be “correct,” that is, one takes it
that the object should give rise to that pleasure. And this is not merely a
subjective claim; one takes it that the object should give rise to pleasure
in anyone. Moreover, like other key claims in Kant’s transcendental
anthropology, this insistence that human beings take pleasure in the
55 object is not an empirical-psychological claim; one does not claim that all
others will or do feel this pleasure, but rather than that they should.
Aesthetic judgments present a normativity that is reducible neither to
epistemic norms (since epistemic norms apply to the formation and
application of concepts) nor moral-practical (both because aesthetics is
disinterested and because practical norms require an appeal to
concepts). Because aesthetic judgments, seen from-within, are governed
by a sort of normativity that is irreducible to epistemic and moral
normativity, a separate transcendental analysis of the conditions of
possibility of this normativity is required.
The final key claim about pleasure in the beautiful provides Kant’s
solution to his central dilemma, but it is also the most confusing of
Kant’s claims about the beautiful. Beautiful objects incite pleasure
because they are “purposive without a purpose” (see 5:220). What does
that mean? And why would the purposiveness of beautiful objects be a
ground for universal pleasure? In answering these questions, Kant
connects his transcendental anthropology of feeling with a critique of the
power of judgment. The normative universality of aesthetic feeling is
explicable in terms of purposiveness as an a priori principle of judgment
that governs both experiences of beauty and our investigation of nature.
By showing the connection between aesthetic feelings and purposiveness
as a principle of judgment, Kant also solves the problems of
incompleteness in the first and second Critiques.
Before showing how purposiveness explains the normativity of
aesthetic judgment, Kant explains how it functions in the formation of
empirical cognitions and thereby deals with an incompleteness in the
transcendental anthropology of cognition offered in the Critique of Pure
Reason. In section one, we saw how Kant argues for metaphysical
principles such as universal causation, but in the Critique of Judgment,
Kant points out that the a priori principles that make empirical cognition
possible as such do not ensure the further “unity of experience . . . as a
system in accordance with empirical laws” (5:183) because they do not
preclude the possibility that each different experience of succession is
governed by a different causal law.
[F]or nature in general (as the object of a possible experience) that
law [of causation as such] is cognized as absolutely necessary . . .
[H]owever, the objects of empirical cognition are still . . ., as far as we
can judge a priori, determinable in so many ways . . . that specifically
distinct natures . . . can be causes in infinitely different many ways .
. . Thus we must think of there being in nature, with regard to its
merely empirical laws, a possibility of infinitely manifold empirical
56 laws . . .; and with regard to them we judge the unity of experience
(as a system in accordance with empirical laws) as contingent. (5:183)
The first Critique showed that changes in the world must happen
according to causal laws, but it failed to show that the set of causal laws
governing the world is finite, much less that these laws fit into anything
like a systematic whole within which diverse particular laws are
explicable in terms of more general laws (but cf. A642-68/B670-96). The
first Critique, in other words, gave no indication of the possibility of
anything even approximating the grand unified theories that scientists
seek.
But since such a unity must still necessarily be presupposed and
assumed . . ., the power of judgment must thus assume it as an a
priori principle for its own use that what is contingent for human
insight in the particular (empirical) laws of nature nevertheless
contains a lawful unity. (5:183)
Human cognition involves seeing the natural world in terms of objects
that change over time in accordance with necessitating natural laws, but
we also seek systematic interconnections amongst these objects and the
laws that govern them. While it would be consistent with the conditions
of possibility of experience in general for each change to be governed by
its own causal law, such that the world as a whole was a “manifold” (i.e.,
crazy mess) of different laws, human beings cannot actually think that
this is the case. Our principles for investigating the world assume
uniformity that, strictly speaking, we are not justified in assuming. Kant
refers to “pronouncements of metaphysical wisdom” that are “scattered
about in the course of science” such as that “Nature takes the shortest
path” or “the great multiplicity of its empirical laws is nevertheless unity
under a few principles” (5:182, cf. 5:185). Without such cognitive rules of
thumb, we could never get anywhere in terms of a systematic empirical
science; we would be left with the abstract metaphysical foundations of
science laid out in Kant’s earlier transcendental philosophy.
For Kant, the “power of judgment” provides the transcendental
basis for these scientific rules of thumb. In general, “the power of
judgment is the faculty of thinking of the particular as contained under
the universal” (5:179), and it has two basic forms: determining and
reflecting. Determining judgment is the power to subsume a particular
under an already-given universal. When one sees a particular tree as a
tree, one determines that the particular present object falls under one’s
concept of a tree. Reflecting judgment is the power by which we are able
to “ascend from the particular . . . to the universal” (5:180). When one
57 reflects on the bones of an animal that is somewhat like a human being
but not quite the same, one can gradually form the concept of a
Neanderthal or Australopithecus. And whereas determining judgment
has for its “rule” the (empirical) concepts that it applies,39 reflecting
judgment “requires a principle that it cannot borrow from experience,
precisely because it is supposed to ground the unity of all empirical
principles under equally empirical but higher principles” (5:180). The
rules of thumb used in science are common-sense versions of this a
priori (transcendental) principle of reflective judgment.
This transcendental principle of reflective judgment is
purposiveness. “Nature specifies its universal laws in accordance with
the principle of purposiveness for our faculty of cognition” in that natural
laws are suited “for human understanding in its necessary business of
finding the universal for the particular that is offered to it by perception
and then further connection in the unity of the principle for all that is
different” (5:186). That is, the otherwise “happy accident” that nature is
suited to be understood as a systematic whole is required, a priori, as a
“purposiveness in relation to the cognitive faculty of the subject” (5:185)
that is assumed in every act of the regulative power of judgment. We
treat nature as something to be understood, something that is suited to
our cognitive faculties. (We do not have to assume that there literally is a
designer who gave this purpose to nature. Nature is “purposive” –
conducive to being understood – without literally having this “purpose.”)
For Kant, the assumed purposiveness of nature for our cognition is
connected to our faculty of feeling pleasure (or displeasure). The
connection is, at first, fairly straightforward: “the attainment of every end
is combined with the feeling of pleasure,”40 so if reflective judgment gives
an a priori aim valid for everyone, “then the feeling of pleasure is also
determined through a ground that is a priori and valid for everyone”
(5:187). Specifically, since understanding particulars in terms of general
laws and “bringing heterogenous laws of nature under higher . . . laws”
are demands of reflective judgment made possible through an assumed
“purposiveness of nature for our understanding,” “if we succeed in this
accord of such laws . . ., pleasure will be felt” (5:187-8). When the
paleontologist studying a strange fossil is finally able to classify that
39
Kant does not hold that there is a rule for the application of a concept. His point is that judgment is a
specific power distinct from the power of understanding rules and distinct from the power (reason) of
deriving one rule from another. The power of judgment is the power to apply rules to particulars, and this
power to apply is not identical to the rule that is applied. But there must still always be some rule that is
applied. In the case of determining judgment, this rule is given by the content of the concept.
40
Importantly, Kant’s point here is not that one experiences pleasure only when one attains an end (see
Allison 2001: 56, cf. Guyer 1979: 71), but that whenever one attains an end, one experiences pleasure.
58 fossil as a distinct species falling under some more general genus, she
experiences pleasure at this success. The a priori principle of reflective
judgment that makes possible the search for systematicity in our
understanding of nature thus provides the first guide to a transcendental
anthropology of feeling, since it proposes a necessary end for all human
beings – unifying particulars under increasingly general laws – the
attainment of which is a necessary and universal basis of pleasure for
human beings. The presumption of purposiveness in nature grounds a
necessary pleasure in actually discovering such purposiveness.
This pleasure is not aesthetic because it is both interested and
conceptual. The pleasure is interested because it is a pleasure in
accomplishing a specific goal. The goal is necessary and given by the
structure of our cognitive faculties rather than by particular inclinations,
but the pleasure is still an interested pleasure. The reason that the
pleasure is conceptual is a bit more complicated. Insofar as one
experiences pleasure in the purposiveness of the world through the
systematization of one’s experience, one’s pleasure is pleasure in
empirical concepts. And in these cases, the central dilemma of aesthetic
judgment does not arise. The scientist who wants to explain why the
fossil brings her pleasure can explain that this particular, which did not
seem to fit into a systematic whole, can be understood according to
such-and-such an empirical concept (Australopithecus, say, or Euleptes
gallica). And even if one does not fully share in her pleasure – pleasure of
discovery depends at least in part on working for it oneself – one can
appreciate why pleasure is called for. In that sense, one can explain one’s
pleasure by reference to (empirical) concepts, and it is not purely
aesthetic.
In principle, objects in the world might be purposive only in that
they possess a general conduciveness to be understood. But in fact, Kant
suggests the possibility of a purely “subjective” or “aesthetic”
purposiveness, “the purposiveness of a thing . . . represented in
perception . . . that precedes the cognition of an object, which is
immediately connected with it even without wanting to use the
representation of it for a cognition” (5:189, emphasis added). With the
exception of the final clause, this description could apply to any reflective
judgment, wherein one must first see an object (or a representation of it)
as purposive and only then subsume it under general concepts. In this
case, however, the purposiveness of the object is recognized without
either subsuming the object under concepts or aiming for such
subsumption. “The object is called purposive in this case only because its
representation is immediately connected the feeling of pleasure” (5:189,
emphasis added). Such a representation would be “an aesthetic
59 representation of purposiveness” (5:189). So far, however, this extension
of the notion of purposiveness seems both arbitrary and mysterious. It is
arbitrary because, as Kant immediately notes, it is still an open “question
. . . whether there is such a representation of purposiveness at all”
(5:189). And it is mysterious because is it not clear what such a
representation would be purposive towards nor how any representation
could be immediately connected with pleasure in this way.
At this point, Kant’s dilemma of aesthetic judgment has an
important role to play. Just as Kant justifies the a priori categories of
understanding as conditions of possibility of experience, and the
postulate of freedom as a conditions of possibility of moral obligation, so
here he uses the dilemma of aesthetic to show the nature and necessity
of aesthetic representations of purposiveness.41 Along with his
contemporaries, Kant takes for granted that there are normative
judgments of feeling (“good taste”). Kant’s transcendental anthropology
looks for conditions of possibility of such judgments. They are
problematic, he argues, because they must be both subjective and
universal. But having described the role of purposiveness in reflecting
judgment that aims for systematic, empirical knowledge, Kant presents
an account of what an immediately-felt, non-conceptual representation of
an object’s purposiveness would have to be. And it turns out that such
representations are precisely what would make possible normative
claims that are both universal and subjective.
In particular, for Kant, an immediately-felt, non-conceptual
representation of an object’s purposiveness would have to be a
recognition of the suitability of an object not to any particular concept or
concepts, but simply to humans’ cognitive faculties in general.
If pleasure is connected with the mere apprehension of the form of an
object . . . without relation of this to a concept for determinate
cognition, then . . . the pleasure can express nothing but [the form’s]
suitability to the cognitive faculties that are in play in the reflecting
power of judgment, insofar as they are in play, and thus merely a
subjective formal purposiveness of the object. (5:189-90, cf. 5:222,
217)
The claim that, in the form of the beautiful, one’s cognitive powers are “in
play” is central to Kant’s account. The “play” of these cognitive powers
can be contrasted both with the work that such powers do (when, for
example, reflecting judgment develops empirical concepts or unifies
41
See Ameriks 1982c, which defends Kant’s argument as a regressive one, like the argument of the first
Critique.
60 diverse laws under more general ones) and with a possible conflict
between such powers (such as when one’s perceptions resist being
brought under general concepts).42 For the feeling of beauty, the relevant
cognitive powers are the imagination and understanding; when these
powers play freely together, one feels aesthetic pleasure. What precisely
is this “free play”? While there is substantial disagreement amongst
commentators,43 the general idea can be gleaned from Kant’s examples of
beautiful objects:
Flowers are free natural beauties. Hardly anyone other than the
botanist knows what sort of thing a flower is supposed to be; and
even the botanist, who recognizes in it the reproductive organ of the
plant, pays no attention to this natural end if he judges the flower by
means of taste. Thus the judgment is not grounded on any kind of
perfection, any internal purposiveness to which the composition of
the manifold is related. Many birds (the parrot, the hummingbird, the
bird of paradise) and a host of marine crustaceans are beauties in
themselves, which are not attached to a determinate object in
accordance with concepts . . . but are free and please for themselves.
Thus designs à la grecque, foliage for borders or on wallpaper, etc.,
signify nothing by themselves: they do not represent anything, no
object under a determinate concept, and are free beauties. One can
also count . . . musical fantasias (without a theme), indeed all music
without a text. (5:229).
All of these examples refer to objects that inspire continuous reflection
without getting to any determinate knowledge. Unlike clearly
conceptualizable forms – such as an equilateral triangle (see 5:241) –
that give no room to the imagination to examine them in new ways, a
flower stimulates a constant redirection of attention from one aspect of
its form to another, a constant attempt to reassemble the visually
presented material with different emphases. But in contrast to a merely
chaotic mish-mash of stimuli, the diverse perspectives that one can take
on a flower are all orderly; the understanding is given constant
encouragement to find patterns and generalities in the representations of
the object. Moreover, the activities of imagination and understanding do
not merely take place side-by-side; they are “reciprocally expeditious”
(20:224). Finding patterns in one way of looking at a flower facilitates the
re-presentation of the flower in yet another way, which leads to the
recognition of a new order, and so on. One can continuously contemplate
42
See Allison 2001: 49-50. We will see another important case of conflict between powers when we turn to
the sublime, below.
43
For some discussions, see Allison 2001, Ginsborg 1997, Guyer 1979, and Zuckert 2007.
61 beautiful flowers, birds,44 and musical improvisations, constantly
reinterpreting them in the light of new “imaginative” ways of pulling
together one’s impressions.
The purposiveness of beautiful objects is not towards goals of our
cognitive powers (increasing knowledge of the empirical world) but
towards the activity of those powers. For Kant, pleasure is a feeling of
“the agreement of an object with the productive power[s] of the soul”
(29:894); the “animation of [the] cognitive powers” of imagination and
understanding gives rise to a pleasure, which “is itself” the
consciousness of the purposiveness of the beautiful object (5:222).
Beautiful objects are pleasurable, and because this pleasure lies in the
mere animation of one’s cognitive powers, and not any end brought about
by those powers, it is disinterested. This animation of cognitive powers is
the effect of the mere representation of the object, not dependent upon
any determinate cognition of the object, so one’s judgment that the object
is beautiful is non-conceptual and thus subjective. But – and this is
Kant’s key move – because the subjective basis of one’s judgment is the
free play of cognitive powers that all human beings share, one can
legitimately expect that any human being should feel pleasure at the
representation of the beautiful object. Because the judgment that an
object is beautiful is a judgment that the object is purposive for one’s
cognitive powers, and because human beings share those cognitive
powers in common, an aesthetic judgment carries with it a commitment
to universality. (Of course, one might still get aesthetic judgments wrong.
One’s pleasure in an object might only seem to be due to disinterested,
non-conceptual contemplation. In that case, one might mistakenly call
beautiful what is really agreeable or good.)
The purposiveness that grounds the subjective universality of
aesthetic judgments of beauty also provides the basis for truly free
pleasure. “among all . . . kinds of satisfaction only that of the taste for
the beautiful is a disinterested and free satisfaction; for no interest,
neither that of the senses nor that of reason, extorts approval” (5:210, cf.
5:354). As is typical for Kant’s transcendental anthropology, freedom in
the context of pleasure is normatively governed. Just as free cognition is
governed by a priori categories and forms of intuition, and free volition is
governed by a categorical imperative, so the free experience of pleasure is
governed by a principle of purposiveness by virtue of which one judges
objects to be beautiful and hence worthy of pleasure when they properly
enliven one’s imagination and understanding. Moreover, the free
pleasure in beauty is a particularly human sort of pleasure:
44
Crustaceans, too. See http://www.reefkeeping.com/issues/2007-05/as/index.php, accessed June 4, 2009.
62 “Agreeableness is also valid for nonrational animals; beauty is valid only
for human beings . . .; the good is valid for every rational being in
general” (5:210).
Although aesthetic pleasure is free even from moral considerations,
it provides an important “mediating concept” between morality and our
sensuous nature (5:196, cf. 5:176). Aesthetic pleasure provides an
“analogy” to morality (5:353) and “prepares us” for it (5:267). The
universality, freedom, disinterested pleasure, and non-conceptual basis
of aesthetic pleasure all correspond to similar traits of the moral law.
And feeling pleasure in beautiful objects proves to human beings that we
are not merely the playthings of our instincts and inclinations. Although
aesthetic pleasure is not itself motivational (since it is disinterested), this
possibility of disinterested pleasure reinforces the categorical demands of
morality with a subjective (and pleasing) basis for thinking that one can
be sufficiently free from inclination to meet those demands. Moreover,
the subjective universality of taste promotes the development of cultures
of taste, within which one seeks to conform one’s own aesthetic
judgments to those of others. One’s effort to resist what Kant will later
call “aesthetic egoism” is implicit in the universal nature of aesthetic
judgment itself, and this development into a tasteful, social being
prepares the way for overcoming the “moral egoism” that treats one’s own
desires as more important than those of others.
In an important sense, then, Kant’s account of the feeling of
pleasure in beautiful objects completes his transcendental anthropology.
With this “critique of aesthetic judgment,” Kant presents the entirety of
human mental life – cognition, volition, and feeling – as susceptible to
transcendental investigation. Like cognition and volition, human feeling
is normative and one can investigate the conditions of possibility of this
normative structure from-within. While cognition is governed by a priori
principles of the understanding and volition by an a priori principle of
reason, feeling is governed by an a priori principle of judgment: the
principle of purposiveness. Moreover, Kant uses his account of beauty to
bridge the gap between nature and freedom in both the cognitive and
volitional dimensions. With respect to cognition, the experience of
beautiful objects involves reflectively judging about objects in the world
and feeling the purposive suitability of this world to our cognitive
capacities. This purposiveness of the world for reflective judgment
provides a ground (albeit a subjective one) for regulating the investigation
of nature in accordance with an assumption of its suitability for
systematic understanding, thus bridging the gap between the Critique of
Pure Reason’s assurance that the world would conform to certain general
structures of human cognition and the need to be able to expand the
63 scope of knowledge systematically. With respect to volition, the
experience of beautiful objects reveals, in the most subjective dimension
of human existence, a universality and autonomy that is analogous to
and preparatory for moral choice.
Kant could have ended his transcendental anthropology with his
account of the beautiful, but he added two important dimensions to his
Critique of Judgment: a theory of the sublime, and an account of
teleological judgment. The account of the sublime is a natural addition to
Kant’s critique of aesthetic judgment. Especially with the publication of
Edmund Burke’s A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of
the Sublime and Beautiful, the issue of the relationship between aesthetic
judgments of beauty and of the sublime became a hot topic in the 18th
century. Like the experience of beauty, the experience of sublimity is
something with which human beings find ourselves. When contemplating
the Milky Way, or St. Peter’s in Rome, or a mountain landscape, one can
have a distinctive sort of experience of not being able to “take it all in.”
And while this inability to take it all in involves a certain kind of
frustration, it can also be strangely satisfying. Similarly, when one
experiences “[b]old, overhanging, and, as it were, threatening rocks,
thunderclouds towering up in the heavens, . . . volcanoes with their alldestroying violence, . . . [or] the boundless ocean set into a rage,” one can
feel like one’s “capacity to resist [is] an insignificant trifle in comparison
with their power” (5:261). Again, however, this painful frustration of one’s
powers can be conjoined with a special sort of pleasure. Kant had
“observed” and discussed these “sublime” feelings in detail almost thirty
years before earlier,45 but not until the Critique of Judgment does he try
to give an account from-within of how such a feeling could be warranted.
In the Critique of Judgment, Kant transforms his early, casual
account into a detailed theory of the relationship between these two
forms of aesthetic judgment. The beautiful, for Kant, is the
unambiguously pleasurable feeling of the harmony of our imagination
and understanding. The sublime, by contrast, is the deeply ambivalent
feeling of disharmony between our imagination and our reason. There are
important similarities between the two:
The beautiful coincides with the sublime in that both please for
themselves. And further in that both presuppose neither a judgment
of sense nor a logically determining judgment but a judgment of
45
In Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and the Sublime (1762).
64 reflection: consequently the satisfaction does not depend on a
sensation, like that in the agreeable, nor on a determinate concept,
like the satisfaction in the good . . . Hence both sorts of judgments
are also singular, and yet . . . universally valid in regard to every
subject, although they lay claim merely to the feeling of pleasure.
(5:244).
The sublime, however, is an odd sort of universal pleasure because “that
which . . . excites in us the feeling of the sublime may . . . appear in its
form to be contrapurposive for our power of judgment, unsuitable for our
faculty of presentation, and as it were doing violence to our imagination,
and yet is judged all the more sublime for that” (5:245, emphasis added).
Judgments of the sublime involve recognizing disharmony between the
objects and our powers. In cases of what Kant calls the “mathematically
sublime” (5:248f.), where we can’t “take it all in,” the disharmony is
between human reason, which seeks “the comprehension of every
appearance . . . into the intuition of a whole” (5:257), and the
imagination, which is “inadequate” for this task (5:252). In cases of what
Kant calls the “dynamically sublime” (5:260f.), the disharmony is
between our natural capacities as a whole and a powerful, threatening
object or situation. But if the beautiful pleases through the harmony it
makes evident amongst our cognitive powers, how can the sublime,
which makes evident a disharmony amongst those same powers, also
please?
With the sublime, an initially painful disharmony gives rise to a
feeling of pleasure when one recognizes in oneself a capacity that
outstrips nature itself. With mathematically sublime objects, one sees
that the demands of one’s (theoretical) reason outstrip nature, so that
one seeks a unity in nature that cannot be satisfied by anything one’s
senses can provide. And with the dynamically sublime, one’s recognition
of the frailty of one’s natural life can reveal that one’s natural life does
not exhaust who one is, that human nature includes a moral demand to
have a good will that no natural forces can undermine. In both cases, the
experience of certain natural objects gives rise to a feeling of one’s own
transcendence over nature. Thus, Kant claims, “true sublimity must be
sought only in the mind of the one who judges, not in the object in
nature . . . That is sublime which even to be able to think of
demonstrates a faculty of mind that surpasses every measure of the
senses” (5:256, 250). In reflecting on certain objects, one comes to
recognize a disharmony caused by the superiority of one’s humanity over
the sensible, natural world. While this disharmony initially provokes
displeasure, the source of the disharmony – one’s transcendent reason –
65 inspires an ambivalent, but nonetheless intense and pleasurable, feeling
of self-esteem.
The feeling of the sublime completes Kant’s account of aesthetic
pleasure and supplements his treatment of the beautiful in three
important ways. First, because Kant aims to give a complete
transcendental anthropology, he must account for all of the ways in
which humans’ feelings of pleasure can be governed by a priori norms.
Since humans’ experience of the sublime is governed by such norms, it
must be discussed. Second, the sublime provides an important balance
to the contribution of the beautiful to Kant’s anthropology of cognition,
corresponding to the role that the transcendental dialectic plays in
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. There Kant showed that while the
understanding structures our experience of the world, reason imposes
demands that transcend any possible experience. In the beautiful, we
feel the conduciveness of the world to human understanding; in the
experience of the sublime, we feel how reason imposes demands that
transcend the world. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, the sublime
provides a bridge between nature and freedom that is importantly
different from that of the beautiful. With the beautiful, humans’
experience of fitness between themselves and nature makes us aware of
a free, disinterested, universal capacity for pleasure that is analogous to
moral demands. With the sublime, especially the dynamically sublime,
humans directly feel their moral dignity. The experience of the sublime
involves feeling precisely the same sort of respect for oneself that is
constitutive of moral motivation. Thus while the sublime reflects the
disconnect between oneself and nature, it also marks a bridge from an
experience of nature that is not itself moral to a respect for oneself that
plays a central role in moral motivation.
With his account of the sublime, there is an important sense in
which Kant has completed his transcendental anthropology of feeling.
The rest of the Critique of Judgment does not directly address humans’
faculties of feeling at all. But for Kant, while “[i]t is . . in taste . . . [that]
the power of judgment reveals itself as a faculty that has its own special
principle and thereby makes a well-founded claim to a place in the
general critique of the higher faculties of cognition” (20:244), this a priori
principle can be applied more widely than merely to govern aesthetic
feeling:
once the capacity of the power of judgment to institute a priori
principles for itself is granted, then it is also necessary to determine
66 the scope of this capacity, and for this completeness in critique it is
required that its aesthetic faculty be recognized as contained in one
faculty together with the teleological and as resting on the same
principle, for the teleological judgment about things in nature also
belongs, just as much as the aesthetic, to the reflecting power of
judgment. (20:244)
Already, we have discussed one important non-aesthetic dimension of
the power of judgment. Nature’s purposiveness to our cognitive powers is
not limited merely to free play but also enables an increasingly
systematic determinate understanding of nature. But in the “critique of
teleological judgment” (5:357), Kant goes further. Once “teleological
judging” is “drawn into our research into nature” (5:360), one can
consider the possibility of “objective purposiveness,” wherein certain
objects in nature are understood as natural purposes. Importantly,
nature might not have included objective purposes (20:216) The laws of
physics and chemistry are merely mechanical, though they show that
matter is purposive for our cognitive powers because it can be subsumed
under general laws. But Kant argues that we can think of a different sort
of purposiveness of nature, what he calls “objective purposiveness”:
Experience leads our power of judgment to the concept of an objective
. . . purposiveness, i.e., to the concept of an end of nature, only if
there is a relation of the cause to the effect to be judged which we can
understand as lawful only insofar as we find ourselves capable of
subsuming the idea of the effect under the causality of its cause as
the underlying condition of possibility of the former. (5:366-7)
For objective purposiveness, the “natural laws” under which we subsume
a given phenomenon depend upon thinking of causes of that
phenomenon as for the purpose of their effect. If one can make sense of
an organized being only as “a thing . . . [that] is cause and effect of itself”
(5:370), then this being will be a “natural end.” When one understands
the motion of the heart in terms of its functional role in promoting the
circulation of blood, and the circulation of blood in terms of promoting
the life functions of an animal, and these life functions as in turn
ensuring the continual motion of the heart, one interprets an animal
teleologically, in terms of purposiveness. When, further, one sees an
individual animal as both the effect of its species and the cause of the
continuation of the species, one interprets the animal teleologically; it
exists for the propagation of the species (and vice versa).
In theory, there might not be “natural ends,” but in fact one finds
self-propagating organized beings in the world “which cannot be
67 explained through [mechanism] alone” (5:374). The result is that human
beings are entitled, and even required, to posit a principle for judging
organized (biological) beings: “An organized product of nature is that in
which everything is an end and reciprocally a means as well.” Or, in less
technical lingo, “Nothing is in vain, purposeless, or to be ascribed to a
blind mechanism of nature” (5:376). Importantly, for Kant, these
principles are purely “regulative,” mere heuristics “for guiding research
into objects of this kind” (5:376). But as heuristics, they are
indispensibly necessary . . . In fact, [anatomists of plants and
animals] could just as little dispense with this teleological principle
as they could do without the universal physical principle, since, just
as in the case of the abandonment of the latter there would remain
no experience at all [as shown in the first Critique], so in the case of
the abandonment of the former principle there would remain no
guideline for the observation of a kind of natural thing that we have
conceived of teleologically as an end. (5:376)
For Kant’s transcendental anthropology, the addition of these teleological
principles has two important implications. First, it allows a limit to the
causal explanation that the first Critique justified. While Kant insists that
in principle everything in nature is explicable in terms of efficient causes
and even that we are required to explain nature mechanically – that is, in
terms of basic properties of matter – as much as possible (5:379, 429), he
concedes that for humans studying the living world, such explanations
will often not be possible. Second, Kant shows here a willingness to
introduce new principles for judgment on the basis of empirical
discoveries. The principle of objective purposiveness precedes and guides
empirical research; biologists assume purposiveness prior to finding the
specific purposes of particular aspects of organized beings. But this
assumed purposiveness is itself the result of discovering through
experience that certain beings in nature can only be understood (by us)
in this way.
The need to investigate organized (living) things in accordance with
a principle of purposiveness also gives rise to two further implications
that will prove important for Kant’s anthropology as a whole. The first of
these will be discussed in the next chapter. Briefly, just as Kant’s
Critique of Pure Reason created a space for an empirical anthropology
that views human beings as empirical objects subject to natural laws, his
Critique of Judgment makes clear that, like other living things humans
are irreducible to strict mechanism, requiring instead teleological
explanation. In particular, Kant allows for basic biological powers that
ground causal laws but the origin of which cannot be traced to any more
68 basic powers (say, of matter). The second implication is discussed in
detail in the Critique of Judgment and constitutes the most important
contribution of that work to the third key question of philosophy: “What
may I hope?”
After explaining that organized beings in general must be
understood as natural ends, Kant explains,
It is therefore only matter insofar as it is organized that necessarily
carries with it the concept of itself as a natural end, since its specific
form is at the same time a product of nature. However, this concept
necessarily leads to the idea of the whole of nature as a system in
accordance with the rule of ends . . . (at least in order to test natural
appearance by this idea). (5:378-9)
Once one finds the fruitfulness of studying living beings in accordance
with the principle that “Nothing is in vain,” it is natural to extend this
heuristic principle to studying nature as a whole. This immediately yields
fruitfulness in a scientific ecology studying organisms’ interdependence;
one sees, for example, how plants nourish animals that in turn provide
“for the human being, for the diverse uses which his understanding
teaches him to make of all these creatures,” but also how, in turn,
“plant-eating animals exist in order to moderate the excessive growth of
the plant kingdom” and humans and other meat-eaters exist to keep the
plant-eaters in check (5:426-7). But Kant also insists that this study of
nature naturally leads one to think about what could be the “final end” of
nature as whole. “A final end,” for Kant, “is that end which needs no
other as the [teleological] condition of its possibility” (5:434), that is,
something that we can see as being a self-sufficient end-in-itself. One
can understand parts of organisms as teleologically-ordered towards the
whole, and even individual organisms as ordered towards the species,
but one can still ask “why do these creatures exist?” (5:426). Answering
this ecologically only pushes the question back further, “but why do
those creatures exist?” Naturally, Kant argues, we want an answer that
justifies the whole world.
Given Kant’s transcendental anthropology of volition, the answer is
both obvious and problematic. The answer is obvious in that Kant has
already shown that there is something that is an end-in-itself: humanity.
But the humanity that is an end-in-itself requires the transcendental
freedom that grounds the possibility of a good will. And that cannot be an
end of nature because neither transcendental freedom nor the good will
are objects in nature; Kant establishes freedom and morality from a
practical rather than empirical standpoint, as “things-in-themselves”
69 rather than “appearances.” Thus Kant insists that despite seeking a final
end of nature, “if we go through the whole of nature, we do not find in it,
as nature, any being that can claim the privilege of being the final end of
creation” (5:426).
Fortunately, however, once we know that human beings as
transcendentally free choosers are the final end of nature, we can look
for an “ultimate” end of nature that would identify “that which nature is
capable of doing in order to prepare [the human being] for what he must
himself do in order to be a final end” (5:430). Identifying this “ultimate
end of nature” provides the basis for a rational hope that nature will
cooperate with our moral vocation. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant
focuses on the regulative principles that can guide our empirical study of
nature. Given that humans’ final end is moral, Kant suggests that the
ultimate end of nature, as that which nature can do to support our moral
freedom, must be the human being’s “aptitude for setting himself ends at
all and . . . using nature as a means appropriate to the maxims of his
free ends in general” (5:431). Thus nature as a whole tends towards
humans’ cultivation in “skill” at using things for their purposes,
“discipline” whereby they rise above inclinations, civil societies that
establish objectively right relationships amongst people, and even the
emergence of cultures of taste, within which “beautiful arts and sciences”
flourish (5:432-3). The details of Kant’s account of human beings as the
ultimate end of nature, including the empirical evidence that emerge
from (and in turn support) his regulative principles, emerge elsewhere
and will be discussed in chapter three. But Kant’s Critique of Judgment
shows how purposiveness as the principle of regulative judgment not
only grounds aesthetic judgments but even leads, through its application
to biology and ecology, to a conception of human beings as ultimate ends
of a purposively ordered nature.
Kant’s Critique of Judgment is a transcendental anthropology of the
faculty of feeling and the power of judgment that provides that faculty
with its regulative principle. As an analysis of feeling from-within, the
Critique shows how there can be non-conceptual normative standards for
judgments of taste, and it reveals an analogy to morality in the most
sensuous aspect of human nature: our feelings of pleasure. In its further
analysis of purposiveness in the study of nature, this Critique not only
justifies the assumption of order in nature but even shows how the
assumption of purposiveness plays a necessary role in regulating
humans’ study of objects with a certain kind of complexity. Throughout
this Critique, Kant also emphasizes that purposiveness as a principle of
70 judgment is merely regulative, and in that sense it is more intimately
human than either the cognitive principles of the first Critique, which
constitute the structure of the empirical world, or the moral principles of
the second, which apply to all rational agents. In the end, though, these
intimately human principles provide a foundation for answering the
question “What may I hope?” both affectively and rationally. In aesthetic
pleasure, we legitimately feel hopeful in our cognitive strivings for
systematic understanding of the world and in our moral aspirations for
disinterested, universally-justifiable choices. And in our understanding
of nature as a teleologically-ordered whole, we look for (and find)
evidence that nature as a whole cooperates with our highest moral
vocation.
V. Conclusion
Kant’s three Critiques present a picture of human beings as finite
but free knowers, actors, and feelers. Human knowledge is constituted
by passively received intuitions that are conceptualized by an
understanding that spontaneously (that is, freely) imposes categories to
cognize objects. Human action involves subordinating subjective and
therefore finite maxims to an autonomous moral principle. And aesthetic
pleasure arises from the free play of faculties that testify to our finitude.
Moreover, the transcendental anthropology of volition in particular
provides a (practical) proof that one is a transcendentally free “homo
noumenon,” capable of acting on grounds that are undetermined by
empirical causes. The transcendental anthropology of cognition ensures
that the empirical expression of one’s transcendentally free choices will
always be a “homo phenomenon,” susceptible to empirical description in
terms of natural laws (6:417-8). And the transcendental anthropology of
feeling shows how the empirically given world supplies material that
provokes pleasurable aesthetic feelings that, in different ways, reveal our
freedom to us.
Insofar as humans are homo phenomena, they must be
understood in terms of categories of the understanding and forms of
intuition. But even as homo phenomena, humans are still distinct from
merely physical nature in that we are teleologically-ordered biological
organisms with particular features, many of which have important
implications for applying the moral law in practical life. Insofar as
human beings are free homo noumena, we are both negatively free, in
that our (noumenal) choices are not determined by any particular
empirical causes, and positively free, in that we are subject to the moral
71 law as the law of our own will (autonomous). By virtue of our freedom, we
are worthy of respect and hence the proper “end” of moral choice, and we
are worthy of “awe” and hence proper objects of sublime feeling.
Most fundamentally, human’s noumenal freedom manifests itself
in the freedom of choice that underlies moral responsibility, but all three
of Kant’s critiques deal with human beings as free in the sense that
humans are subject to normativity not only in action but also in thinking
and feeling. All three realms of human life involve laws, norms, and
requirements that are not causal but nonetheless perceived as binding
from-within. Kant’s critical works thus not only set up the general
framework of phenomenal-noumenal humanity but also specifically
address the noncausal laws that govern human beings. Unlike the
observation-based anthropology we’ll discuss in the next chapter, this
transcendental anthropology is thoroughly normative throughout, a
normative account of the human being from-within: an epistemology, an
ethics, and an aesthetics.
However, “transcendental anthropology” is incomplete as an overall
answer to the question “What is the human being?” The Critique of Pure
Reason shows that empirical knowledge is possible and that reason
pursues more and more completeness of knowledge of the empirical
world. Because human beings appear in the empirical world,
transcendental anthropology must be supplemented with an empirical
anthropology that describes what humans look like “from-without.”
Moreover, Kant’s a priori moral philosophy requires supplementation by
an “empirical part” that will involve “judgment sharpened by experience”
to know how the moral law should be applied and how “to provide [it]
with access to the human will” (4: 388-9). And finally, while the practical
postulates of God and immortality and the general teleology revealed
through natural beauty and human biology give some basis for moral
hope, Kant suggests that “experience and history” can provide further
reasons that “we should not despair about our species’ progress toward
the better” (7:329). It should thus come as no surprise that while Kant
was developing his transcendental anthropology, he was also engaged in
detailed empirical studies of human beings. Such empirical study is
necessary to complete his answer to his question “What is the human
being?” and thereby to fully answer his remaining questions: “What can I
know [including empirically about human beings]?”, “What ought I do [to
human beings with the empirical features that we have]?” and “What
may I hope [based on the progress human being have made historically
so far]?” It is to this empirical anthropology, then, that we now turn.
72 CHAPTER 2: KANT’S EMPIRICAL ANTHROPOLOGY
In the last chapter, we examined Kant’s “transcendental”
anthropology, his examination of the cognitive, volitional, and affective
dimensions of the human being from the standpoint of a priori,
normative, autonomously-given laws governing those faculties. But Kant
also engaged intensely in empirical debates about human beings. The
next three chapters focus on different dimensions of Kant’s empirical
anthropology. First, in this chapter, I examine Kant’s overall empirical
anthropology of the human mind, that is, his empirical psychology. This
psychology includes Kant’s accounts of the different faculties of human
beings, the causal laws that describe the activity of those faculties, and
the bases of such faculties in “natural predispositions” found in humans’
biological nature. In chapter three, I turn to two more specific aspects of
Kant’s empirical anthropology, his treatments of human evil and of the
historical nature of the human species. And in chapter four, I turn to
Kant’s accounts of human diversity.
I. The Possibility of Empirical Psychology
Given the importance of Kant’s transcendental anthropology, he
might seem merely to dismiss empirical anthropology. But in fact, one of
the key claims that Kant establishes in his transcendental account of
cognition is that human beings are capable of having empirical
knowledge of their world, and he emphasizes that such empirical
knowledge includes empirical knowledge of human beings themselves. His
Critique of Pure Reason paves the way for the empirical study of human
beings. Although Kant insists throughout the Critique that a human
being cannot cognize itself “in accordance with what it is in itself,” he
constantly adds “that through inner sense we intuit ourselves . . . as we
are internally affected by ourselves . . . [and thus] we cognize our own
subject . . . as an appearance” (B156, cf. B69, 153). Like everything else
we can cognize, human beings can be cognized as appearances, as
“homo phenomenon” (MM 6:418). Even where the Critique of Pure Reason
most emphasizes the possibility of human freedom, Kant insists that
human beings insofar as they appear in the world are subject to
empirical study: “all actions of a human being are determined in accord
with the order of nature . . . [I]f we could investigate all the appearances .
. . there would be no human action we could not predict with
certainty”(A549/B577, cf. 20:196). Kant gives a striking example to
illustrate this general point.
73 Let us take . . . a malicious lie . . . . First, we endeavor to discover
the motives to which it has been due, and secondly, we proceed to
determine how far the action . . . can be imputed to the offender. As
regards the first question, we trace the empirical character of the
action to its sources, finding these in defective education, bad
company, in part also in the viciousness of a natural disposition
insensitive to shame . . . . We proceed in this enquiry just as we
should in ascertaining for a given natural effect the series of its
determining causes. But although we believe the action is thus
determined, we nonetheless blame the agent. (A554-55/B 582-83,
emphasis added; cf. too 29:1019-20)
In the Groundwork, too, Kant reiterates that “everything which takes
place [is] determined without exception in accordance with laws of
nature” (4:455), and in the Critique of Practical Reason, he goes so far as
to say that if we knew the relevant preconditions, “we could calculate a
human being’s conduct for the future with as much certainty as a lunar
or solar eclipse” (5: 99)
Despite Kant’s insistence on empirical study of human beings,
there are three reasons that many call into question whether Kant can
really allow for empirical anthropology. First, it seems impossible for
Kant to admit that humans are susceptible to truly “scientific” study,
since any such study must provide universal claims about its objects (as,
for example, Newton’s laws do about matter), which Kant seems to rule
out for empirical anthropology. In his Metaphysical Foundations of
Natural Science, Kant even claims, “The empirical doctrine of the soul
can . . . never become . . . a science of the soul, nor even a psychological
experimental doctrine” (4:471).46 Second, a completely empirical-causal
anthropology might seem to conflict with Kant’s very strong claims about
human freedom (see chapter one).47 Third, empirical anthropology just
seems fraught with practical problems. Kant discusses epistemic
challenges such as the fact that “if a human being notices that someone
is . . . trying to study him, he . . . either . . . cannot show himself as he
really is or . . . does not want to be known as he is” (7:121) and moral
dangers of self-study, such as that “self-observation . . . is the most
direct path to illuminism or even terrorism, by way of a confusion in the
mind of supposed higher inspirations and powers flowing into us . . .
46
47
E.g. Gouax 1972, Westphal 2004.
Cf. Reath 1989, Baron 1995.
74 from who knows where” (7:133).48 These comments suggest that even if
empirical human science is possible in principle, it is unreliable and
dangerous in practice.49
In fact, however, none of these concerns preclude an empirical
anthropology suitably construed. To start with the first point, Kant
rejects the possibility of an empirical human science in a very strict
sense of “science” (4:471, 20:238, 28:679). Kant uses the term “science”
to refer only to knowledge that is a priori. Newton’s laws count as
science, for Kant, because “outside of what lies in [the empirical] concept
[of matter], no other empirical principle is used” (4:470).50 By contrast,
even if one starts with empirical, psychological concepts – such as the
existence of a mind – one cannot derive further substantive claims about
the mind a priori.51 And unless one can derive claims about human
psychology a priori, one cannot make strictly universal claims:
“Experience tells us, indeed, what is, but not that it must necessarily be
so, and not otherwise. It therefore gives us no true universality” (A1-2, cf.
B3-4, A91/B124, A196/B241). General claims about human beings, if
based merely on experience, might seem to be “merely fictitious”
(A196/B241). In fact, however, Kant’s rejection of a scientific and strictly
universal status for empirical anthropology does not preclude the
possibility of what he calls a “historical systematic natural doctrine of the
inner sense” (4:471), a “natural science . . . improperly so called, . . .
[which] would treat its object . . . according to laws of experience”
(4:468). Kant even compares certain psychological forces to “motive
force[s] in the physical world” (25:577), and he remarks that because
“physics is knowledge of the object of outer sense, and the knowledge of
human beings as the object of inner sense, . . . [empirical anthropology]
deserves . . . to be treated as a science in academia, just as is physics”
(25:472-3). Kant does not here mean that empirical anthropology will be
a science in the same sense as physics, since it will not have a
mathematical, a priori foundation. The claims of empirical anthropology
will, correspondingly, not be necessary claims. But even in the first
Critique, Kant admits a kind of universality that experience can provide:
“empirical rules . . . can acquire through induction . . . comparative
48
The idea here is that “we make supposed discoveries of what we ourselves have carried into ourselves”
(7:133), acting as though the apparently involuntary flow of our thoughts is due to some sort of
supernatural inspiration.
49
Cf. Wood 1999, Louden 2000.
50
As we will see in chapter one, Kant holds that Newton’s laws can be derived a priori from the concept of
matter and the a priori structures of human cognition.
51
Kant gives several reasons for this, including the fact that because the form of inner sense is time, “which
has only one dimension,” “mathematics in inapplicable to the phenomena of inner sense” (4:471) and the
fact that “observation itself already changes and displaces the state of the observed object” (4:471).
75 universality, that is, extensive applicability” (B124/A91, see too B 3-4).
While not “science” in Kant’s strict sense, empirically-grounded laws of
human beings constitute a comparatively-universal, systematic
presentation of human mental and social life.
The second concern about the possibility of Kantian empirical
science arises from Kant’s account of human freedom. Many
commentators have rightly pointed out that the account of free action in
Kant’s transcendental anthropology of volition offers a different
conception of moral psychology than the traditional empiricist beliefdesire model according to which human beings are simply motivated by
their strongest active desire. But those who take this insightful
alternative approach to conflict with Kant’s empirical account of human
action52 are misguided. As we will see in chapter one, Kant’s
transcendental idealism aims to show how an empirical and even causal
model of human behavior leaves room for real freedom, not within the
empirical model but as something distinct from (and grounding) humans’
empirically-knowable character. Kant's transcendental anthropology of
cognition shows that humans experience everything – including
themselves – in terms of a structure of cognition that interprets change
in terms of causal relationships. But this metaphysics of the empirical
world leaves room for a different standpoint from which freedom is
possible, and Kant's transcendental anthropology of desire – his moral
philosophy – makes clear that human agents must see themselves as free
causes of their actions. This implies, of course, that Kant’s empirical
anthropology is only empirical; it does not provide access to what Kant
will call the human being as it is in itself, the “homo noumenon” (MM
6:418, cf. 7:397-400). It is possible to have access to what the human
being is like in itself (as we will see in chapter one), but empirical
anthropology provides no such access.
The final challenge for rigorous empirical investigation of human
beings is the set of specific difficulties with self-study that make
empirical anthropology – as Kant put it at the opening of his first course
in anthropology – a “hard descent into the Hell of self- knowledge” (25:7).
As he says in his published Anthropology,
[A]ll attempts to arrive at such a [human] science with
thoroughness encounter considerable difficulties that are inherent in
human nature itself.
52
One such commentator has said, “if the moral law determines choice by exerting a force that is stronger
than the alternatives, moral conduct will result from the balance of whatever psychological forces are
acting on the will . . . It is not clear that this model leaves room for any real notion of will or choice” (Reath
1989: 290-91). Cf. too Baron 1995:189, Westphal 357-8, and even Wood (2003: 50).
76 1. If a human being notices that someone is observing him and
trying to study him, he will either appear embarrassed (selfconscious) and cannot show himself as he really is; or he dissembles,
and does not want to be known as he is.
2. Even if he only wants to study himself, he will reach a critical
point, particularly as concerns his condition in affect, which normally
does not allow dissimulation: that is to say, when the incentives are
active, he does not observe himself, and when he does observe
himself, the incentives are at rest.
3. Circumstances of place and time, when they are constant,
produce habits which, as is said, are second nature, and make it
difficult for the human being to judge how to consider himself, but
even more difficult to judge how he should form an idea of others
with whom he is in contact; for the variation of conditions in which
the human being is placed by his fate or, if he is an adventurer,
places himself, make it very difficult for anthropology to rise to the
rank of a formal science. (7:120-1)
And in a draft of his anthropology, Kant adds,
[T]he I which has been observed by itself is a sum total of so many
objects of inner perception that psychology has plenty to do in tracing
everything that lies hidden in it. And psychology may not ever hope to
complete this task and answer satisfactorily the question: “What is
the human being?” (7:398-99)
For Kant, empirical study of human beings proceeds by means of both
introspection and observation of others, and both of these forms of study
face several of the problems Kant describes here: mental life is
intrinsically complex, human beings typically act differently when being
observed, self-observation is inhibited by the fact that many of the most
interesting and important activities in human life preclude the calm and
attentive work of introspection,53 and human beings can develop
contingent characteristics – habits of time and place – that seem
essential. We could add even more difficulties today, such as
unconscious motivation or the fundamental attribution error.54 The
53
When one is overcome with anger, for example, it is impossible to actually observe the nature of that
anger because anger prevents the calm interest and introspective attention involved in self-study. And when
the anger has passed, one can no longer see – and may not accurately remember – what the anger looks like
in action.
54
See chapter eight for more.
77 result of all of this can be a desperation about the possibility of ever
(empirically) answering the question, “What is the human being?”
Despite these cautions, Kant regrets that while “[n]othing seems
more interesting . . . than this science, . . . nothing is more neglected”
(25:7) and insists that “an anthropology . . . that is systematically
designed” is possible and “yields an advantage for the reading public,”
including the promotion of “the growth of [this] science for the common
good” (7:121-2). Kant even maintains that anthropology begins with
“general knowledge of human beings” (7:120) and “is provided with a
content by inner sense” (7: 398, cf. 25:252, 863-5). And while Kant
warns about the dangers of such introspection, he insists that it can be
done in a way that is relatively free from danger, claims that observing
oneself is a duty (6:441-2), and gives both general advice and specific
examples of how to introspect well. Moreover, Kant insists that this
introspection provides only a basis for further study; one must make use
of and accordingly adapt general knowledge through interpreting others.
If we want to judge about other people, we must alter our point of
view, namely
1. transpose my point of view and then
2. put myself in the other’s point of view . . . To take a point of view
is a skill which one can acquire by practice. (25:475)
Reading good literature – Kant suggests Shakespeare, Montaigne, and
Fielding55 – further cultivates and supplements proper self-observation.
Travel and the reading of travel literature provides further material for
reflection on both human nature in general and “local knowledge” of the
varieties of human beings (see 7:120). In the end, disciplined self-study
supplemented by careful study of others and reading literature by those
skilled in putting themselves into others’ points of view can alleviate the
problems faced by any attempt “to observe human beings and their
conduct, [and] to bring their phenomena under rules, [which] is the
purpose of anthropology” (25:472). While Kant doubts the possibility of a
wholly satisfactory empirical anthropology, he aims to develop as full an
empirical account as possible, or at least a sufficient account “from
which a prudent use in life can . . . be drawn” (25:472, cf. 7: 119).
55
In other contexts, Kant includes such authors as Samuel Richardson, Moliere, the English Spectator (by
Allison and Steele), and Rousseau. For references to literature as a source of anthropology, see 7: 221,
25:473. For a fascinating recent study of Kant’s readings of Milton, see Budick 2010.
78 Kantian empirical anthropology, then, is general rather than
strictly universal, and thus a science only in a loose sense. Even as such
a science, it is particularly vulnerable to error given humans’ tendencies
to get ourselves wrong. But a fallible quasi-science laying out empiricallyjustified general laws of human beings is, for Kant, possible, interesting,
and useful. The rest of this chapter lays out the overall framework of this
empirical anthropology. The next two chapters get into more specific
topics in Kant’s empirical anthropology: human evil, history, and
diversity.
II. Kant’s Faculty Psychology
When Kant began working on empirical anthropology, the
dominant approach to the empirical study of human beings in Germany
(promoted by Christian Wolff and Alexander Baumgarten) involved laying
out different human mental states in terms of various “faculties of soul”
and then showing how these faculties could be reduced to a single
faculty of “representation.” The idea was that rational cognitions were the
clearest and most distinct representations of the world, and sensory
cognitions, feelings, and desires were representations with varying
degrees of obscurity and indistinctness. Against this view, many
philosophers and emerging psychologists (most prominently, Moses
Mendelssohn, Johannes Tetens, and August Crusius56) argued that
human mental states were irreducibly distinct; the main alternatives
suggested were either a very wide diversity of human mental states, a bipartite model within which belief and desire are irreducible to each other,
or some combination of these within which irreducibly distinct mental
states can be classified broadly into beliefs and desires. Although he
lectured from a textbook (Baumgarten’s) that promoted the single-faculty
approach, Kant’s own work defended mental state pluralism. Unlike his
compatriots, however, Kant insisted upon combining a broad mental
state pluralism with a fundamentally tri-partite structure. The basic idea
was that there are a large number of irreducibly distinct sorts of mental
states that can be grouped into three irreducibly distinct types:
cognition, feeling, and desire.
Kant’s argumentative strategy for this view is two-fold. First, he
develops a general philosophy of science according to which one should
seek to “deriv[e] diverse powers, which we know only through
observations, as much as possible from basic powers” (28:564, cf. 8:1801; 28:210; 29:773-822; A648-9/B676-7). One should assume as many
basic powers as are really necessary, a point Kant emphasizes by
56
Cf. Crusius 1745,§§73, 444; Watkins 2005:91; Hatfield 1990.
79 comparing Descartes, who “explains all [physical] phenomena from the
shape and the general motive power of bodies,” with Newton’s “more
satisfactory” method that allows the assumption of “certain basic powers
. . . from which the phenomena are derived” (29:935-6, cf. A64950/B677-8). The phenomena one finds in both the physical and mental
worlds require more than a single basic power. So while Kant seeks to
reduce powers as much as possible (for instance, by showing that
memory is a form of imagination), his focus is on not overly reducing
mental powers. Second, Kant lays out some specific arguments to show
that particular mental powers are irreducible to one another. For
example, Kant emphasizes his isolation of feeling as a state distinct from
both cognition and desire/volition, noting that feeling is not merely a
confused cognition of a thing, and emphasizing that aesthetic pleasures,
no matter how intense, do not give rise to volitions (29:877-8). He points
out that while cognition is “related merely to the object and the unity of
the consciousness of it,” a volition is “the cause of the reality of this
object” (20:206). More generally, Kant argues that one can only reduce
distinct powers if one can find a power from which they “could be
derived” (8:181n). In the end, Kant insists, “there must be several [basic
powers] because we cannot reduce everything to one” (29:773-822).
For Kant, the set of distinct basic powers includes each of the five
senses; an “inner sense” by virtue of which we are aware of our own
mental states; the imagination; higher cognitive powers of reason,
understanding, and judgment; a power of feeling pleasure and
displeasure; and various powers of volition. Kant groups these distinct
powers into the general faculties of cognition, feeling, and desire, and
further sub-divides them between “higher” and “lower” faculties. “Lower”
faculties are primarily receptive, while “higher” faculties are “self-active”
(28:228, 29:880, 28:584), by which Kant does not mean the
transcendental freedom of the homo noumenon but a “comparative
concept of freedom” according to which “actions are caused from within”
(5:96).57 We can lay out Kant’s overall taxonomy of mental powers as
follows:
Faculties of soul
Cognition
57
Feeling
Desire/Volition
For a discussion of the relation between these sorts of freedom, see Frierson 2008.
80 Higher
Judgment,
Understanding,
Reason
“satisfactions or “Motives” based
dissatisfactions
on practical
which depend on principles
the manner in
which we cognize
the objects
through concepts”
Lower
Sight, hearing,
“satisfactions and
taste, smell,
dissatisfactions
feeling, inner
which depend on
sense, imagination the manner in
(including
which we are
memory)
[sensibly] affected
by objects” (28:
254)
“Stimuli,”
impulses rooted in
instinct or
inclination.
2. Causal Laws Governing Human Beings
Kant did not discuss the structure of human mental faculties
simply to argue against Wolff’s reduction of the mind to a single faculty
of representation. Getting clear on different mental faculties is crucial for
developing a full empirical anthropology because “the concept of cause
lies in the concept of power” (28:564) and in empirical human science we
seek “natural laws of the thinking self” based on “observations about the
play of our thoughts” (A347/B405, cf. 25:472). Each distinct mental
power is governed by its own causal laws (including laws governing how
it relates to other mental powers), and a complete empirical anthropology
describes these laws.
For Kant, faculties of soul are causally ordered such that “pleasure
precedes the faculty of desire, and the cognitive faculty precedes
pleasure” (29:877-8). Moreover, “all desires have a relation to activity and
are the causality thereof” (25:1514, cf. 29:1024); desire plays the same
role in psychology that motive forces like momentum play in physics
(25:577). In fact, desire is defined as a representation that is the ground
of an action that brings about some state of affairs (6:211, 399; 7:251;
29:1012), so there are no actions not preceded by and caused by desires,
and no desires that do not lead to actions (in the absence of external
impediments). For any human action, a sequence of causes can be traced
as follows:
81 At any step along this progression, the causal chain could be cut off. For
example, when a normal human being tastes a mango (cognition), that
taste gives pleasure (feeling), that pleasure causes a desire for the
mango, and that desire leads one to eat (or continue eating) the mango.
But one’s mango might be snatched away, preventing one from eating (or
continuing to eat) the mango. Or one might see a beautiful flower
(cognition) and experience a “disinterested” pleasure that gives rise to no
subsequent desire. Or one might learn that the capital of Iceland is
Reykjavik and thus have a cognition, but without this cognition giving
rise to any pleasure or desire.
This sketch requires filling in. Kant needs to explain what gives
rise to cognitions in human beings, how and when those cognitions give
rise to pleasures, and how and when those pleasures give rise to desires.
As Kant offers the details of these causal laws, his account gets
extremely detailed, so here I only highlight aspects of his account. With
respect to the lower faculty of cognition, Kant distinguishes between the
five traditional senses (sight, hearing, touch, taste, and smell), “inner
sense” (our ability to “observe” our own inner mental states), and
imagination (which, for Kant, includes memory, foresight, and the
imagination as a “fictive faculty” to think of things that we never
experience). About the five senses, Kant lays out only the most general
descriptions, such as that “the sense of touch lies in the fingertips and
the nerve endings (papillae) and enables us to discover the form of a solid
body by means of contact with its surface” (7:155) and that sight, touch,
and hearing are “mechanical” while taste and smell are “chemical”
(25:495). Kant speculates about “a faculty of the nerves [that] underlies
the mind . . . in separating and combining given sensory representations”
and even suggests that some sort of “water of the brain” that is
encountered by the “ends” of the “stimulated optic nerve” or “auditory
nerve” (12:34). But Kant’s dominant approach is basically Newtonian,
that is, not to try to explain how light, for instance, causes a visual
sensation by stimulating the optic nerve, but simply to classify what
physical causes bring about this mental state. Just as Newton does not
solve the “problem” of gravitational action at a distance but instead
names and classifies the phenomenon, Kant does not try to “solve” the
so-called “mind-body problem” of how states of the brain cause mental
states, instead merely classifying the basic powers that underlie these
connections.
The most extensive psychological discussion of lower cognitive
faculties comes with the imagination. Kant posits that imagination is
82 governed by three fundamental laws: affinity, forming intuitions in space,
and association. Association, for example, is the principle that “empirical
ideas that have frequently followed one another produce a habit in the
mind such that when one idea is produced, the other also comes into
being” (7:176). Hearing a particular song may trigger thoughts of the
person with whom one often listened to that song, or the thought of a
certain book may cause one to think of the place where one read that
book. The imagination also figures centrally in Kant’s account of
language: it is by virtue of customary association between sounds and
thoughts that those sounds (and eventually written words) come to stand
as symbols for those thoughts.
Kant’s discussion of the higher faculty of cognition is more
complex. This faculty is subdivided into three basic powers: reason, the
understanding, and judgment. Most generically, “Understanding draws
the general [i.e., concepts] from the particular . . . . Reason draws the
particular from the general . . . . The power of judgment is the
subsumption of one concept under others [or of particulars under
concepts]” (29:890). The power of judgment operates according to the
principles governing analogy – “things . . . which . . . agree in much, also
agree in what remains” – and induction – “what belongs to many things
of a genus belongs to the remaining ones too” (9:133, see too 24: 772).
The understanding generates certain concepts as an immediate
consequence of sensory perceptions, but most concepts of the
understanding are generated through chains of comparison, reflection,
and abstraction. With respect to the former, Kant argues that “on the
occasion of experience” certain “concepts have arisen through the
understanding, according to its nature” (28:233), such as the basic
concepts of causation and substance that make it possible for our
experience to be intelligible as experience of an objective world.58 In other
cases, sensory cognition leads to empirical concepts, such as when
seeing “a spruce, a willow, and a linden” leads one to
compare these objects with one another [and] note that they are
different from one another in regard to the trunk, the branches, the
leaves, etc.; but next . . . reflect on that which they have in common
among themselves, trunk, branches, and leaves themselves, and . . .
abstract from the quantity, the figure, etc. of these; and thus . . .
58
Even in the case of these basic concepts, one “understands” them only in an implicit sense, sufficient for
applying them for cognizing the world. Coming to articulate one’s implicit understanding of causation in
terms of the generic concept “cause” takes a process of “reflection” (28:233) on the experience that they
help to structure. (Small children make use of causal inferences long before they understand what the word
“cause” means.)
83 acquire a concept of a tree. (Jasche Logic, 9:95; see too 24: 252-3,
753, 907)
Reason, finally, operates through principles of logic: the cognition of the
premises of an argument give rise to a cognition of the conclusion of that
argument. When I think about the facts that “Socrates is a human” and
“All humans are mortal,” I am led to the thought that “Socrates is
mortal.”
Thus far, Kant’s account of how higher faculties work tracks how
they ought to work, but Kant knows that people’s higher faculties often
do not function according to these ideal laws, and he develops an
account of how “other activities of the soul . . . are connected with the
judgments of the understanding” to generate a “mixed effect” that can be
mistaken for “a judgment of the understanding” (16:283-4).59 Such
mixed effects result from what Kant calls “prejudices,” which function as
alternative principles by which some cognitions give rise to others
according to causes distinct from the understanding strictly speaking.
For example, “the prejudice of the prestige of the age” leads some to favor
the writers of antiquity more than they should, thereby “elevating the
relative worth of their writings to an absolute worth” (9:79). For those
affected by this prejudice, cognitions of claims associated with a
particular ancient writer will immediately give rise to affirmation of those
claims, a transition inexplicable in terms of properly functioning higher
cognitive powers alone. Prejudices primarily arise from “imitation,
custom, and inclination” (9:76), and Kant especially highlights the role of
intellectual laziness in cultivating prejudices. Prejudices do not wholly
displace higher cognitive faculties, but they provide a way for Kant to
make sense causally of transitions between beliefs that are not actually
justified, and thus cannot be explained in terms of the higher cognitive
faculties alone. This account of prejudice, supplemented with detailed
accounts of various prejudices and an account of how the higher and
lower faculties of cognition relate, make up his overall account of the
faculty of cognition.
Kant’s account of the faculty of the feeling of pleasure and
displeasure is the most original, complex, and confusing aspect of his
faculty psychology. The originality lies in Kant’s claim the faculty of
feeling can be reduced to neither cognition nor volition, and Kant’s basis
for this claim is his account of aesthetic pleasure. Even those who
59
My account of deviations from proper functioning of the higher cognitive faculties here focused on those
deviations that take place in ordinary human knowers. Kant’s account of mental illness will be discussed in
chapter four.
84 argued against Wolff’s attempt to reduce all the basic powers of the soul
to a single one generally ended up describing pleasure as either a
subjective form of cognition like color or scent or as a constitutive part of
desire. But Kant explains,
We have pleasure or displeasure without desiring or abhorring, e.g. if
we see a beautiful area, then it enchants us, be we will not on that
account wish at once to possess it. Pleasure or displeasure is thus
something entirely different from the faculty of desire. (29:877)
The difference between pleasure and volition cannot be explained merely
in terms of strength. Even a mild pleasure in the thought of a sweet treat
brings with it a desire to eat (more of) that treat, while the most intense
purely aesthetic pleasure gives rise to no volition at all. Because there
can be pleasures that are not connected with volition at all, Kant argues,
pleasure cannot be seen as merely a component part of volition. But
pleasure is also a sort of feeling towards an object that cannot be
reduced to cognition of it. Someone could understand everything there is
to know about an object that pleases me and still not find pleasure in it.
Pleasure indicates something about me, not necessarily anything about
the object. So while many feelings might be intimately linked with
cognitions and volitions, feeling in general cannot be reduced to these
cognitive-volitional aspects. Thus Kant articulates what precisely feeling
is in its own right.
On Kant’s general account of feeling, there can be very different
kinds of feelings, but all feelings are, in some sense, feelings of
satisfaction (pleasure) or dissatisfaction (displeasure).60 Because
pleasure is not a kind of cognition, Kant rejects the dominant (at the
time) Leibnizian-Wolffian definition of pleasure as “the [obscure] sensible
representation of the perfection of an object” (20:226, cf. 5:227). Instead,
Kant offers two “definitions” of pleasure:
(1) “The consciousness of the causality of a representation with
respect to the state of the subject for maintaining it in that state can
here designate in general what is called pleasure” (5:220, cf. 20:230,
15:241; 25:459, 785; 28: 247, 586; 29:890; 6:212, 7:231)
(2) “Pleasure is the representation of the agreement of an object or of
an action with the subjective conditions of life” (5:9n; cf. 5:204;
7:231; 15:246, 15:252, 16:133, 25:167-8, 181, 1501; 28:247, 586,
29:891).
60
Kant sometimes uses these terms synonymously, and sometimes distinguishes pleasure as sensuous
satisfaction, where satisfaction is a more generic term. (So God can feel satisfaction but not pleasure, and
we find satisfaction but not pleasure in obeying the moral law.)
85 First, pleasure is defined simply as a mental state (a “representation”)
oriented towards preserving itself. The feeling of pleasure just is a selfpersistent mental state. But Kant relates this feeling oriented to
persisting in one’s state with the concept of “life,” which he connects with
self-activity and sometimes defines as a “faculty of a being to act in
accordance with laws of the faculty of desire” (5:9n, cf. 28:275, 680). In
the case of human beings, “life” involves the full set of mental powers of
cognition, feeling, and desire. The general idea is that when something
seems to promote the activity of one’s powers, a distinctive mental state
arises that reflects this advancement of activity; this mental state is
called “pleasure.” When something seems to inhibit activity, one feels
displeasure. In a lecture on metaphysics, Kant connects his two
definitions:
The feeling of the promotion of life is pleasure, and the feeling of the
hindrance of life is displeasure. Pleasure is when a representation
contains a ground for being determined, for producing again the
same representation, or for continuing it when it is there. (28:586)
Thus we might say that when one feels pleasure, one feels like
continuing in one’s state because one’s state seems conducive to the
activity of one’s powers. When one feels displeasure one feels like ending
one’s state because one’s state feels like an inhibition of activity.
Given his definition(s) of pleasure, Kant divides possible objects of
pleasure into different categories. Most fundamentally, and central to
Kant’s insistence that pleasure is not merely an aspect of desire, Kant
claims that pleasures can be distinguished into those that give rise to
desires and those that do not. The key to this distinction is that desires
are “objective” in that they are directed towards bringing about their
objects in the world, while pleasures, in themselves, are wholly
subjective, both in that they reflect something about the subject (whether
one’s overall state is conducive to life) and in that they aim to preserve
themselves subjectively (as mental states). Generally, preserving
pleasurable states involves acquiring objects or objective states of affairs
that bring pleasure. Pleasure in a mango depends upon actually eating
the mango. Such pleasures, in order to “produce again the same
representation or . . . continue it” (28:586), give rise to desires, mental
states that actually affect the world by causing one to act (e.g. eat the
mango). Kant calls such pleasures “interested” or “practical” and
proposes that other pleasures – aesthetic ones – are not interested: “[A]
judgment about beauty in which there is mixed the least interest is very
partial and not a pure judgment of taste” (5:205). Kant takes this point
quite far, claiming that if “the palace that I see before me [is] beautiful” I
86 will feel a distinct pleasure in the contemplation of it, even if “were I to
find myself on an uninhabited island . . . and could conjure up such a
magnificent structure through my mere wish, I would not even take the
trouble of doing so” (5:204-5, cf. 29:878). Aesthetic pleasures arise from
reflection, and the actuality of the object of one’s reflection is not
necessary in order to promote the “free play of the powers of
representation” (5:217) that grounds the feeling of pleasure. Kant’s
aesthetics (discussed in chapter one) focuses on a transcendental
account of these disinterested pleasures. For the purpose of his empirical
account, his main purpose is to show that there are such pleasures and
thereby distinguish the faculty of feeling from that of desire.
With the exception of aesthetic feelings, pleasures sustain
themselves by means of the faculty of desire. The faculty of desire is the
most complicated faculty in terms of its causal laws, and explaining it
fully requires a discussion of the biological roots of causal laws in Kant’s
account. In general, though, the faculty of desire is “the faculty to be, by
means of one’s representations, the cause of the objects of those
representations” (5:9n, 6:211) or “the self-determination of a subject’s
power through the representation of something in the future as an effect
of this representation” (7:251). The key point here is that desire is a
mental state by virtue of which one becomes a cause of the objects of
that mental state. Whereas cognition merely thinks about its objects and
feeling merely enjoys its objects, desire actually brings about what it
represents.61 To desire something is to have the requisite mental state for
bringing that thing about. Even when desire is not fully self-conscious
(as in animals, or as with bare urges) or when it is merely a response to
sensory stimuli, it still represents a mental state directed towards an
object as a cause of bringing that object about. When desires are more
deliberate and self-conscious, when they follow from the higher faculty of
cognition such that we want something because we understand what it
is, then Kant describes such desire as “a faculty to do or to refrain from
doing as one pleases” (6:213). When one has a desire, one might also
lack the ability to actually bring about the end of that desire. A desire, for
Kant, always involves a volitional commitment to an object, but when one
is committed to bringing about the object while still recognizing that one
lacks the power to actualize that commitment, one’s desire is called a
mere “wish” (6:213). When one desires an object and is also aware of
one’s power to bring about that object, one “chooses” it (6:213). It should
be clear, here, that “desire” is in some ways closer to what we consider
“choice” than it is to what we typically consider “desire.” When a person
61
Thus, contra Wolff, the differences between these faculties, as well as differences between higher and
lower faculties, are not reducible to differences in clarity and distinctness.
87 “desires” something in Kant’s sense, it means that they have the sort of
mental state that will bring about its object if it can. Thus what we might
consider a mere “desire” would for Kant be an inactive ground for a
possible desire. “Concupiscence (lusting after something) must be
distinguished from desire itself, as a stimulus to determining desire.
Concupiscence is always a sensible modification of the mind but one that
has not yet become an act of the faculty of desire” (6:213).
Beyond this general description of desire, Kant must explain why it
is that desires arise for certain objects and not others. Generally
speaking, the account is fairly simple. Given a cognition that gives rise to
a practical pleasure, one will experience a desire for the object of that
pleasure. The problem is explaining why certain cognitions give rise to
practical pleasures while others do not. Kant’s solution to this problem
is, justifiably, extremely complex. Generally speaking, he distinguishes
between higher and lower faculties of desire based on whether they are
moved by pleasures in higher cognitions (principles informed by concepts
or ideas) or lower cognitions (brute sensations or imagination). But
within these classifications, Kant must explain the variety of forms of
human desire, and he articulates that account in the context of a
description of biological and environmental factors that characterize
human beings. To get a fuller empirical anthropology, then, we need to
turn to Kantian human biology.62
3. Human Natural Predispositions
One of the central claims of Kant’s biology is his claim that “it
would be absurd . . . to hope that there may yet arise a Newton who
could make comprehensible even the generation of a blade of grass
according to natural laws that no intention had ordered” (5:400). In
rejecting a “Newton of a blade of grass,” Kant denies one dominant
strand of 17th and 18th century biology, theories of mechanistic
“epigenesis” that aimed to explain the origin and nature of life in terms of
purely physical forces.63 But Kant also rejects the dominant alternative,
“preformationism,” which assumed that all humans (and other animals)
pre-existed in the egg or sperm of their most distant ancestors, formed in
miniature and waiting to emerge. The dominant concept in Kant’s biology
is the “natural predisposition” (Naturanlage), a concept that combines
important aspects of both epigenesis and preformationism. Natural
62
Ultimately, even Kant’s biology is insufficient for understanding human nature, since human beings are
essentially an historical species, so one must turn to his account of human history; see chapter three.
63
Proponents included Descartes, Hobbes, and LaMettrie.
88 predispositions are “grounds of a determinate unfolding which are lying
in the nature of an organic body” (2:434). Kant argues that “chance or
universal mechanical laws could not produce such agreements [adaptive
homologies], [so] we must consider such arrangements as preformed . . .
[and] the mere faculty to propagate its character is already proof that a
particular . . . natural predisposition for it was already to be found in the
organic creature” (2:435). But Kant still insists not only that “outer
things can well be occasioning causes” (2:435) for the development of
these predispositions but also that “even in the case of the structure of
an animal, it can be assumed that there is a single predisposition that
has the fruitful adaptiveness to produce many different advantageous
consequences” (2:126). Like epigenesists, Kant wants to explain natural
variety using the smallest number of explanatory principles, but like
preformationists, he allows that some elements of biological structure
cannot be explained by mechanism alone.64 Moreover, the way in which
Kant suggests that outer things affect the development of natural
predispositions ends up being selective rather than purely mechanical.
That is, natural predispositions “lie ready . . . to be on occasion either
unfolded or restrained, so that [an organism] would become suited to his
place in the world” (2:435). Kant’s use of predispositions is thus a sort of
adaptationist65 account of biological (including human) development:
organisms are born with a set number of predispositions that develop in
response to various environmental conditions in accordance with what is
needed to thrive within those conditions.
By appealing to “predispositions” in living beings, Kant does not
commit himself to any particular metaphysical conception of the
development of living things. Instead, he aims to effect an epistemic and
methodological shift. Unlike epigenesists, who try to account for the
emergence of biological structures from simpler processes, Kant argues
that investigation of living beings proceeds best when one seeks to
discover the minimal number of predispositions from which one can best
explain the full range of biological phenomena one finds in the world.
One corollary of this epistemic use of predispositions is that Kant’s
pessimism about a Newton of a blade of grass is not a denial that the
generation of a blade of grass may in fact be causally determined
according to mechanistic laws, but only an admonition to distinguish
biology from physics and allow forces in the former that might be
inadmissible in the latter (see 5:411, 415, 422).
64
As we will see in chapter eight, there is a sense in which current biology does account for natural
predispositions in terms of purely physical causes. What for Kant are inexplicable natural predispositions
turn out to be genes that evolved through processes of natural selection.
65
One might even say “proto-Darwinian” here. See chapter eight.
89 This gives rise to a further aspect of Kant’s biology. Given that
organic predispositions serve purposes within organisms, Kant adds, as
a “heuristic principle for researching the particular [biological] laws of
nature” (5:411), a “principle of final causes” (5:387) “in order to
supplement the inadequacy of [mechanical explanation] in the empirical
search for particular laws of nature” (5:383). According this heuristic
principle, “nothing in [an organized product of nature] is in vain,
purposeless, or to be ascribed to blind mechanism” (5:376). By relegating
teleology to the status of a heuristic, a “maxim of the reflecting power of
judgment” (5:398) that “is merely subjectively valid” (5:390), Kant can
adopt a biology that explains natural organisms in terms of purposive
structures. Predispositions that are not further explainable either
physically (through mechanist epigenesis) or supernaturally (through
divinely ordained preformationism) are susceptible to a teleological
analysis. One can biologically explain why these developmental
possibilities and not others are present through explaining what purpose
they serve. The result is that in Kant’s biology, one can legitimately ask,
about any biological structure, what purpose that structure serves, and
answers to such questions are legitimate parts of biological investigation.
Kant’s preformationism has several important implications for his
empirical anthropology. First, it allows Kant to forego describing how
human predispositions came into existence: “we begin with something
that human reason cannot derive from prior natural causes – that is,
with the existence of human beings,” including all of their natural
predispositions (8:110). Kant’s empirical anthropology reduces given
powers to as few natural predispositions as possible, explaining
environmental factors that allow certain predispositions (but not others)
to flourish in (certain) human beings and using this small number of
natural predispositions to explain what we observe of human beings.
Second, Kant’s emphasis on teleological explanation of these
predispositions gives him additional resources for “explaining”
predispositions without mechanistically explaining them. Kant gives
teleological explanations of phenomena as diverse as sleep (7:166, 175,
190), laughter (7:261), distinctions between the sexes (7:305), and that
“illusion” by which someone “who is naturally lazy” mistakes “objects of
imagination as real ends” (7:175, 274). Third, Kant’s preformationism
contributes to his general disinterest in giving materialist explanations of
psychological predispositions. Kant contrasts his approach to the
empirical anthropology of his contemporary Ernst Platner, which Kant
identified with “subtle, and . . . eternally futile inquiries as to the manner
in which bodily organs are connected with thought” (10:145). Through
positing predispositions as fundamental concepts in biology, Kant’s
90 empirical anthropology can focus on explaining diverse mental
phenomena in terms of as few basic powers as possible, tracing these
basic powers back to purposive natural predispositions and the
environmental influences that cause these predispositions to unfold,
without being preoccupied with finding the physical structures that
underlie those predispositions.
In laying out his empirical anthropology, then, Kant takes basic
powers to be developed forms of natural predispositions. These natural
predispositions provide bases for connections between mental states,
grounds in human beings for observed laws covering such connections.
Thus for any two mental states, we can describe their connection in
terms of a causal law that is grounded in a basic power, which is itself
the determinate unfolding of a natural predisposition.
↑
Actualized Natural Predisposition
The concept of natural predisposition allows Kant to expand the sense of
“basic power” beyond the limited and abstract structure of his empirical
psychology. Especially in the context of the faculty of desire, Kant
develops a vocabulary for natural predispositions that provides the
flexibility and variety needed to make sense of the myriad different ways
in which human beings can be motivated to actions.
With respect to the faculty of cognition, Kant’s treatment of natural
predispositions is fairly straightforward. The senses, inner sense, the
imagination, and the higher faculties of judgment, understanding, and
reason are all different natural predispositions in the human being (A66,
6:444-5, 25:1172, 29:915). Humans have natural predispositions to
sense, imagine, and think in accordance with the laws described above.
Thus in explaining the connection between one cognition and another,
one appeals to the natural predispositions active in effecting that
transition. For example, when the transition from the thought of one’s
dog to the thought of dog food is effected by the imagination, one can
describe this transition as follows:
-food
91 ↑
Imagination (the predisposition governed by the law of association)
By contrast, the transition from the thought of one’s dog to the thought
“animal” would be effected by the understanding, hence the relevant
predisposition would be different. In both cases, however, a complete
explanation of the origin of a particular cognition must include, for Kant,
not only the prior state that caused the cognition and the causal law
according to which that state caused that transition, but also the natural
predisposition that is the ground of that law.
There are variations amongst human beings in terms of the
exercise of natural cognitive predispositions. Some of these are rooted in
variations amongst predispositions themselves, such as certain forms of
mental illness. Others involve a deficiency in the development of natural
predispositions. And others, including all prejudices, involve
circumstances in which some predispositions (linked either to
imagination or to the faculty of desire) override the understanding and
reason, leading to erroneous judgments. There are also positive
variations in cognitive powers, such as wit or originality of thought,
which Kant calls calls “talents,” a sort of “excellence of the cognitive
faculty which depends not on instruction but on the subject’s natural
predisposition” (7:220). Altogether, Kant develops an account of cognitive
predispositions that identifies the basic powers of cognition as
predispositions and then accounts for variations in cognitive abilities
through either hereditary or acquired defects in these predispositions or
their expression.
Predispositions become more important and complex with respect
to the faculty of desire and the practical pleasures related to one’s
desires. As noted in the last section, the causal structure that
determines whether particular cognitions give rise to desire or aversion
can be exceedingly complex. Many things that give rise to desires in one
person do not do so in others, things can give rise to desires sometimes
and not others, and humans – even as objects of empirical study – seem
capable of a kind of freedom of choice that might seem to preclude causal
explanations. In every case, desires are preceded by cognitions that
provoke feelings of pleasure that in turn provoke desires. But while
virtually all feelings of pleasure cause desires for their objects (the only
exceptions being the special cases of aesthetic pleasures), cognitions can
92 cause pleasure, displeasure, or no feelings at all. Kant seeks to trace this
complex volitional structure back to two kinds of natural predispositions:
instincts (Instinkte) and propensities (Hänge).
The nature and role of instincts is fairly straightforward. Among
natural predispositions present in human beings are a set of instincts
that ground connections between various cognitions and practical
pleasures (or pains) that give rise to desires (or aversions) for objects of
those cognitions. Given the distinctness between the faculties of feeling
and desire, there would be, strictly speaking, separate predispositions
underlying the connection between, on the one hand, a particular
cognition and subsequent feeling, and, on the other hand, that feeling
and its consequent desire. But because all practical pleasures give rise to
desires and Kant offered an account of non-practical desires that
explains how they cause feelings without subsequently generating
desires, his detailed account of human motivation conflates the power
that grounds a connection between cognition and feeling and the power
that grounds the connection between the feeling and desire. Kant
ascribes the transition from cognition to desire to a single basic natural
predisposition. (For ease of presentation, I sometimes drop the reference
to the intermediary practical feeling in Kant’s account and simply
describe the role of natural predispositions as relating cognitions to
desires.) In the case of instinct, Kant’s model of motivation maps
straightforwardly onto his account of predispositions in general.
↑
↑
Instinct
For example,
↑
↑
Instinct for sweet foods
Often, instincts become operative when one is in the presence of the
object that one’s instinct predisposes one to desire (or avoid): “little
chicks already have from nature an instinct of aversion to the hawk, of
which they are afraid as soon as they merely see something fly in the air”
(28:255). With respect to human beings, Kant explains how smell, by
93 means of “its affinity with the organ of taste” and “the latter’s familiar
sympathy with the instruments of digestion,” serves as an “instinct” that
“guided the novice . . . allow[ing] him a few things for nourishment but
for[bidding] him others” as though it were a kind of “faculty of presensation . . . of the suitability or unsuitability of a food for gratification”
(8:111). Central to these operations of instinct is that instincts ground
connections between cognitions and anticipatory pleasures that give rise
to desires. And these connections occur even before any experience of
pleasures that might follow from the satisfaction of the desire. In cases
where the objects of instincts are not present, Kant even suggests that
instincts can be “directed to an indeterminate object; they make us
acquainted with the object” (25:584). As he illustrates,
One knows that children, who are hardly born, show an instinct for
nutrition, without knowing what they need, and immediately carry
out the art of the physical law to suckle the breast; if they did not
have the instinct, but one first had to accustom them to this, then
many would perish. . . . We can see that the sexual instinct is a
natural instinct by the fact that, even if they were in the monastery,
when [the time of] puberty comes, persons are still disturbed by the
instinct, and feel the need for an object which they do not yet know.
(25:584)
One can have instincts with definite objects of present awareness, but
one can also have instincts with indeterminate and unknown objects,
instincts that agitate to activity in such a way that one comes into the
presence of their objects. Moreover, the power of imagination can greatly
expand the scope of instinct. Kant describes a scene where “a fruit
which, because it looked similar to other available fruits which he had
previously tasted, encouraged him to make the experiment” of eating it
(8:111).66 Given an association between a particular visual experience
and a particular olfactory experience, a similar visual experience will – by
virtue of the laws that govern the imagination – give rise to an
imaginative idea that corresponds to that olfactory experience. Given a
sufficiently strong instinctual connection between that olfactory
experience and practical pleasure, the mere sight of a similar fruit will
give rise to a desire to consume that fruit.
66
In this essay, Kant emphasizes the cooperation between imagination and reason in the extension of one’s
natural instincts and inclinations. However, one can also conceive of an extension that is purely due to
imagination, as I suggest here.
94 Even with this expanded conception of instinct, however, most of
human life is not directly governed by instinct, for two important
reasons. First, much of what humans desire is not reducible to particular
instincts. Human desires for the company of one’s friends, wearing
fashionable clothes, resting on comfortable sofas, watching one’s favorite
television programs, attending baseball games, and even for things like
smoking cigarettes and eating fine foods, cannot be explained by appeal
to brute instincts. These are all, in varying degrees, connected with
habits that give rise to desires for certain objects. Second, even when we
pursue objects for which we have instincts, humans typically do not
pursue those objects directly from instinct. Instincts give rise to what we
might call a desire, but we have a capacity to reflect on whether or not to
pursue the object of that desire. Humans frequently decide not to follow
through on instinct for the sake of something else, often something for
which they do not have particularly strong instinctual desires at that
moment. When I decide not to eat that delicious ice cream because I
know that it will make me sick later, I do not act from any instinctual
desire for long term health. If humans acted only from instinct, the task
of explaining human motivation would require merely a catalog of
relevant instincts and careful descriptions of environments in which
those instincts play out. But human behavior is, as Kant recognized,
much harder to explain.
One might be tempted, at this point, to appeal to human freedom
as a reason for the difficulty of explaining human behavior. And many
have thought that the complexity of human motivation provides some
support for Kant’s account of freedom. But within his empirical
anthropology, Kant takes the complexity of human action not as a reason
to posit any kind of transcendental human freedom, but rather as a
basis for a much more complicated but still wholly empirical
anthropology. Kant adds the requisite complexity through a generous use
of the category of a “propensity.” In one lecture, Kant defines a
propensity as a “natural predisposition” that provides “the inner
possibility of an inclination” (25:1111-2; cf. 7:265, 25:1517). More
generally, a propensity is a natural predisposition that does not itself
provide a ground for connections between cognitions and practical
pleasures (and thereby desires), but that makes it possible for the
human being, in the context of environmental factors, to develop a
ground for such connections. Having introduced this notion of a
propensity, Kant puts it to use to address the two problems mentioned in
the previous paragraph.
First, Kant focuses on human propensities for “inclinations,” which
he identifies as “habitual grounds of desire” (25:1114) and which, for the
95 purposes of his empirical anthropology, are distinguished from
instincts.67 Like instincts, inclinations provide bases for connections
between cognitions and desires. Unlike instincts, however, inclinations
are not natural predispositions but rather tendencies brought about
through certain experiences. For example,
[S]avages have a propensity for intoxicants; for although many of
them have no acquaintance at all with intoxication, and hence
absolutely no desire for the things that produce it, let them try these
things but once, and there is aroused in them an almost
inextinguishable desire for them. (6:29; cf. 25:1112, 1339, 1518)
In some cases, one needs only a single experience of an object for an
inclination to be awakened. Generally, however, inclinations require
“frequent repetition” (25:1514). Kant adds that there is a generic
propensity to develop habits, such that when one experiences something
consistent over a long period of time, one develops an inclination for it
(cf. 9:463-4). In any case of inclination, however, it is not enough to
simply have exposure to something to develop an inclination for it.
Experiences give rise only to inclinations when human beings already
have requisite propensities. The model for explaining human action in
those cases looks like:
(sight or smell of intoxicant)
(desire to consume intoxicant)
↑
Past experience (
↑
Propensity (for intoxicants)
In these cases, the immediate explanation for why a particular cognition
gives rise to a practical pleasure and thereby a desire will be similar to
the case of instinct, but because inclinations are not themselves innate,
the account requires an extra level of complexity. And this complexity
67
Within his moral philosophy, when Kant refers to “inclinations,” this term includes instincts as well.
Kant adds, in his empirical anthropology, a special category of inclination called “passion.” I discuss
passions in chapter six.
96 provides for much of the richness and diversity that one finds in human
desires. Fancy clothes, comfortable sofas, cigarettes, and baseball are all
possible objects of inclination, even when we have no instinctual desire
for them. And because humans differ in their experiences, even those
with the same propensities (and Kant allows for some, but not much,
variation in basic human propensities68) will end up with very different
patterns of desire. A general propensity for competitive sport (or, even
more generally, for esteem and physical exertion), leads to widely varying
inclinations depending on the particular sports to which one is first
exposed. Because propensities are natural predispositions, Kant does not
give mechanical accounts for them, but he does aim to reduce the
number of posited propensities to as few as possible; ideally, he would
also provide teleological explanations for each propensity.
Kant also suggests that inclinations generally involve pleasure in
ways that differ from instinct. For both instinct and inclination,
experience of the object of desire brings a subsequent pleasure distinct
from the practical pleasure that causes the desire. For instincts, this
subsequent pleasure plays no explanatory role in the development of the
instinct. The instincts for nursing or for sex motivate human beings to
seek milk or sex innately, not because one has experienced their
pleasures already. Instincts ground pre-sensations (8:111) of pleasure.
But in the case of inclinations, the anticipatory practical pleasure that
gives rise to desires generally follows from past experiences of the
pleasure that one experiences when one attains the objects of desire. One
accidentally experiences some object, gets pleasure from the experience,
and forms an inclination that grounds future connections between the
cognition of that object and the desire to experience it. One might taste
an intoxicating beverage out of thirst or conformity (rather than a desire
for intoxicants) or might literally fall into a pleasantly cool pool of water
on a hot day. When the experience of such objects brings pleasure, one
will seek intoxicating beverages even when one is not thirsty, or one will
intentionally seek out and immerse oneself in cool pools of water. In
these cases, we might specify the past experience as past experience of
68
Even in the case of intoxicants, Kant’s famous reference to the propensity of “savages” for intoxicants is
more likely an assertion of the universality of this propensity than a limitation of it to a particular group.
Kant’s view seems best captured by his claim in a lecture on anthropology that “Human beings across the
whole world have a propensity to drink [alcohol]” (25:1112). Elsewhere he uses “northern peoples”
(25:1339), “the wildest peoples” (25:1112), “nations that have wine” (25:1518), and even (with respect to
intoxicants more generally) the “people in Kamtschatka, [who] have a certain cabbage, which when they
eat it, works in them a kind of madness, for which they love to have it” (25:1518). The point of these
examples is not to pick out any particular group as uniquely susceptible to intoxicants, but to show that a
propensity to drink that is undeniable in the case of Europeans is equally present in savage, or “raw” (rohe),
people.
97 pleasure in the objects. Of course, one need not always experience
pleasure in order to form an inclination. One who has started smoking
can find herself craving cigarettes even while the actual experience of
smoking is still generally unpleasant, and one who develops a habit of
acting in a particular way can develop an inclination to continue acting
in that way, even if it is not, in itself, particularly pleasurable. Generally,
however, a propensity brings about a corresponding inclination at least
in part through pleasure in attaining its object.
The addition of inclinations to Kant’s account of human motivation
greatly enriches that account, and it makes it possible to explain why
there is such a wide range of divergent human interests. But
inclinations, like instincts, still do not involve the reflective desires that
characterize much human action. Kant captures this limitation by
ascribing both instinct and inclination to the “lower” faculty of desire.
Both affect human beings insofar as we are motivated by sensory or
imaginative mental states, but not insofar as we govern our actions by
means of concepts, principles, or maxims (the “higher” faculty of desire).
For Kant, the higher faculty of desire, to which Kant assigns the term
“choice” (6:213), “cannot be determined to action through any incentive
except so far as the human being has incorporated it into his maxim”
(6:24).69 To explain how “maxims,” or cognitive principles, can give rise to
volitions and thereby actions, Kant cannot merely appeal to instincts or
inclination. Instead, he appeals to yet another propensity, a propensity to
what he calls “character.”
Kant uses the term character in several senses throughout his
writings. In the broadest sense, the character of a thing is the “law of its
69
This passage is typically, and rightly, used to analyze the practical perspective from which we are
transcendentally free vis a vis all of our actions. Kant’s specific language in this passage confirms that he
primarily has this transcendentally free power of choice in mind, rather than the specifically empirical
faculty of choice. But the claim about acting on the basis of maxims here also has an empirical correlate.
Empirically, the higher faculty of desire is the human capacity to have volitions that result from
consideration of maxims, or principles of action, rather than mere stimuli. Insofar as one’s volition falls
under the higher faculty of desire, any lower incentives based on instinct or inclination must be conjoined
with the recognition of a principle of action in order to motivate.
Seeing the connection between the transcendental importance of incorporating incentives into
maxims and the empirical nature of higher volition highlights the distinctive role of maxims for Kant’s
account of motivation. What essentially distinguishes higher from lower volitions is that the motivating
cognitions for lower desires are particular, while the motivating cognitions for higher desires are general.
Thus, for example, Harry Frankfurt’s discussion of first and second order desires (in Frankfurt 1988) does
not track Kant’s distinction between higher and lower cognitions, since one could – at least in principle –
have general first order desires and particular second-order desires. For Kant, the generality of a desire – its
lawlike form – is distinctive of human (rational) agents. For Frankfurt, it is second-order desires.
98 causality, without which it would not be a cause at all,” such that “every
effective cause must have a character” (A539/B567, cf. 25:634). In this
sense, gravity reflects the “character” of matter, and one’s instincts are
part of the “character” of one’s lower faculty of desire. In a quite different
sense, Kant uses “intelligible character” to refer to the free ground –
“which is not itself appearance” – of one’s appearances in the world
(A539/B567). Character in this sense has no role to play in empirical
explanations of action, although Kant argues that this intelligible
character grounds the empirical character of the higher faculty of desire.
The character that plays an important role in Kant’s empirical theory of
the higher faculty of desire is distinct from though grounded in
intelligible character, and more specific than the character of an efficient
cause in general. Kant defines this sense of character as “that property of
the will by which the subject has tied himself to certain practical
principles” (7:292) or “a certain subjective rule of the higher faculty of
desire” (25:438, cf. 25:277), and this sense of character plays the same
role for the higher faculty of desire that instincts and inclinations play for
the lower. As Kant explains, “the man of principles, from whom we know
for sure what to expect, not from his instinct, for example, but from his
will, has character” (7:285, cf. 25:1514).
One can describe such motivations as follows:
↑
Character
“Character” is a matter of commitment to various principles or “maxims”
of action. Thus, one may have a commitment to the principle “early to
bed, early to rise.” In such a case, one’s actions might be explained as
follows:
↑
99 Fixed commitment to “Early to bed, early to rise”
Of course, this example is too simple in several respects. For one thing,
the cognition of the principle “Early to bed, early to rise” is not in itself
sufficient to generate the desire to go to bed, since one must also have
awareness of the fact that it is evening – time for bed – rather than
morning or afternoon. In order for one’s character to ensure that the
principle will be efficacious in generating its corresponding action, one
requires both perception of one’s situation – the sky is growing darker,
the clock says 9 PM, etc – and the consciousness of the relevant
principle.70
Moreover, one’s commitment to the principle “early to bed, early to
rise” is itself the result of other causes. Kant needs an account of the
causes of character as such, that is, the ability to act in accordance with
principles at all, and an account of the origins of the particular principles
upon which individuals act. Regarding the first, Kant’s account of
character development is similar to his account of the development of
inclinations. There is a “propensity to character” (25:1172, cf. 25:651,
823, 1176) that is actualized by various experiences (cf. 25:1172; cf.
7:294), such that one might have the propensity but lack character, just
as one might have a propensity to intoxicants but never develop the
inclination. In the case of character, habit does not play a role in its
formation. Instead, Kant emphasizes the role of education (25:1172),
examples (7:294), and “moral discourses” (25:1173n1, cf. too 9:492-3),
and he gives specific recommendations regarding the kinds of education
that are most effective, such as avoiding “imitation” (25:635, cf. 7:325;
5:154; 25:599, 722ff., 1386) and using “discipline” (9:449) that can “first
clear away the passions” so that character can develop without
hindrance (9:486). Beyond these direct influences, Kant suggests oblique
factors that play roles in character cultivation, such as stable and just
political regimes, peace, and even progress in the arts and sciences. He
even suggests that politeness cultivates character by combating passions
and promoting self-control.71 And finally, Kant points out how other
natural predispositions (especially temperament) facilitate character
development (cf. 7:285, 290; 25:1388). All these elements work together
70
These elements might themselves be causally related, and often are. When a practical principle comes to
mind, one may be led to look for the presence of its conditions of application and thereby come to perceive
those conditions. Alternatively, the perception of conditions of application (a darkening sky, a late clock)
may remind one of one’s practical principles.
71
For more on the role of politeness in cultivating character, see Brender 1997, 1998, and Frierson 2005.
100 to transform a mere propensity into an active ability to govern oneself
with conscious principles rather than reactive instincts and inclinations.
Many of the influences responsible for the development of
character as such also foster specific practical principles, but Kant
emphasizes that most of these principles still “rest on sensibility, and . . .
merely the means for arriving at the end are presented by the
understanding” (28:589). For example, one might learn “early to bed . . .”
through instruction, but this instruction is effective because it proposes
a plausible principle for satisfying one’s instincts and inclinations. Even
in the absence of specific instruction, one with experience can form
principles of action based on what actions best promote desired ends.
Such principles are intellectual rather than sensible, but they still “rest
on sensibility” because one formulates them for the sake of “lower” (i.e.,
sensible) inclinations and instincts. Even actions described as following
“from inclination” are generally grounded in a character committed to
principles that make objects of inclination its ends.72 Generally,
inclinations for sweets do not directly cause one to eat them; rather, one
understands that eating this food will satisfy a felt inclination, and
(because of one’s character) this thought causes one to eat it.
Actions motivated by these “impure” principles of character are
explained by an extremely complicated motivational picture. Through
natural higher cognitive powers, sensory data are transformed into a
conceptual understanding of one’s situation. At the same time, by virtue
of one’s instincts and inclinations, one’s sensory awareness of one’s
situation gives rise to various lower desires.73 The understanding then
provokes the thought of one or more practical principles based on how
reason connects its conception of one’s situation with one’s felt lower
desires. Thus one who recognizes the darkening sky under the concept of
“early evening” might be led to think of the principle “early to bed…” by
virtue of understanding this as the time at which going to bed will best
facilitate the satisfaction of various inclinations over the long term. These
practical principles give rise to practical pleasures and thereby desires –
72
Most human desires flow from principles to which we are committed in order to satisfy the instincts and
inclinations of our lower faculty of desire. Sometimes these connections will be straightforward: human
beings in wealthy nations typically consume food not immediately from instinct but from principles
according to which we recognize the eating of food to be both immediately worthy of pursuit (because
pleasurable) and ultimately useful for providing nourishment. Even foolish consumption of junk food is
generally not directly instinctual but is a deliberate effort to satisfy the cravings of instinct according to
principles – “Snickers really satisfies” – that we incorporate into the character of our higher faculty of
desire.
73
Or, more strictly speaking, proto-desires. If one reserves the term “desire” for the active desires that
constitute real volitions (as Kant often does), then these are not yet desires in the strict sense.
101 which Kant, in these cases, calls “choices” – by means of a character that
has been formed through education, social-cultural influences, one’s own
past behavior, and the cooperating or hindering influence of inclinations
and instincts. Both character in general and the inclinations that largely
determine the content of the principles on which one acts are grounded
in natural propensities. Thus human beings, due partly to different
natural propensities but largely to different past experiences, will be
motivated by similar sensory data to behave in different ways.
As complicated as this picture is, Kant thinks that human
motivation is even more complicated, for three important reasons. First,
the account given above assumes that for any given set of sensory data,
there is only one way in which one’s natural powers can conceptualize
that content and, more importantly, that this conceptualization only
lends itself to a single practical principle. But it might well be that the
recognition of the darkening sky is conjoined with a recollection of an
invitation to a social gathering that promises to be particularly enjoyable.
Here one may be led to think of the principle “early to bed, early to rise”
but also the principle “don’t forgo opportunities for enjoyable social
gatherings” (cf. 6:473, 7:277-82), when one cannot in fact act in ways
that follow from both practical principles. In such cases, even one with a
well-formed character will have conflicting possible grounds of action.
One’s character could enable the former principle to give rise to a
practical pleasure that would motivate one to stay home, or it could
enable the latter principle to give rise to a practical pleasure that would
motivate one to go out. From within practical reflection (transcendental
anthropology), what one does is a matter of free choice. But empirical
anthropology must provide a psychological explanation. Kant first
insists, “in empirical psychology, wholly equal incentives cannot be
thought” (28:678; cf. 25:278) because in the case of equal incentives,
there would be no choice and thus no action (29:902). As a result, Kant
distinguishes “living” and “dead” grounds of desire. Even when one has
only a “dead” ground, one might still be left with something like a desire,
with what Kant calls a “wish,” where the “ground determining one to
action . . . is [not] joined with one’s consciousness of the ability to bring
about its object” (6:213), in this case due to one’s pursuit of other ends.
Thus one goes to bed because one’s overall character subordinates the
principle of socialization to that of prudent rest, but one falls to sleep
wishing that one could somehow both go to bed early and partake in the
enjoyable party.
The second added complication to this account of choice is that
although, strictly speaking, character requires commitment to act from
consistent principles, very few people have character in this fully
102 developed sense. In a lecture, Kant specifically mentions difficulty with
the practical maxim “early to bed, early to rise”:
[one] who is not steadfast in this, often lays hold of a resolve, of
which he knows for sure that nothing will come, because he knows
that he has already often broken resolutions. Then the human being
is in his [own] eyes a wind-bag. He no longer has any confidence in
himself . . . This is how it is with things for which one wants to break
one’s habit . . ., such as sleeping in; for it is always said, just one
more time, but then no more, and thus one again philosophizes
oneself free of one’s plan . . . (25:624)
Sometimes inclinations directly overpower one’s higher faculty of desire,
such that in the strict sense, one acts on the inclination alone, without
the reflection that characterizes choice. But such cases are rare. More
often, inclination corrupts the grounds of choice and one “philosophizes
oneself free of one’s plan” by acting on a maxim that differs from what
one had resolved. For Kant, this tendency is quite common. Truly firm
character “is fixed very late,” only “com[ing] at a ripe old age” (25:654,
1385, cf. 7: 294). Most people have a kind of “bad” or “flawed” character
(schlechte Charackter: 25:650, 1172; Fehlerhafte im Charackter:
25:1172). Such “character” is a “constitution of one’s higher powers”
(25:227) according to which, rather than acting on from fixed principles,
one allows the principles of choice to vary based on inclinations active at
the time of choice. Here inclinations and instincts not only affect to
which practical principles one commits oneself but also determine
whether and to what extent those affect principles deliberation at
particular moments. One with a firmly established character decides, by
assessing the impact of various principles on her life as a whole, how to
prioritize such principles. When the time comes for action, which
practical principles determine action are set by this prioritization. One
with flawed character might similarly rank practical principles, resolving,
for instance, to prioritize an early start to the day over satisfying the
inclination to sleep in, but inclinations of the moment, rather than
resolved-upon rankings, determine which principles become effective.
A final, crucial component of Kant’s account is that humans are
capable not only of “impure” principles of action that are “intellectual . . .
in some respect,” but also of purely intellectual principles of action.
Human beings have a “predisposition to the good” (6:26), a “moral
predisposition” (7:324) that gives motivational force to a principle that is
“purely intellectual without qualification” because it is an “impelling
cause” that “is represented by the pure understanding” (28:589). A
purely intellectual principle is not based in any way on one’s instincts or
103 inclinations but proceeds solely from practical reason itself. In chapter
one, we saw the importance from the standpoint of transcendental
anthropology (moral philosophy) of the possibility of an “autonomous”
moral law, a principle governing human actions that does not require
appeal to inclination for its justification. Within Kant’s psychology, the
role of pure practical principles is different. They are principles of the
higher faculty of desire that do not require positing any instincts or
inclinations as factors in its explanation. In chapter two, we noted that
Kant must show how moral laws can motivate human beings that are
objects of empirical description. Kant’s empirical anthropology in general
provides the basic biological-psychological background for such an
account. Like other natural predispositions, the predisposition to the
good is simply posited in human nature. Like instincts, Kant suggests
that this predisposition is innate in human beings (6:27-8, 7:324), and
he even offers empirical evidence for it (7:85). But like all predispositions
of the faculty of desire (including instincts), experiential factors
determine the extent to which the moral predisposition is living and
efficacious or amounts to mere wish. Thus, for example, when one
person “confronts [another] with . . . the moral law by which he ought to
act . . . , this confrontation [can] make an impression on the agent, [so
that] he determines his will by an Idea of reason, creates through his
reason that conception of his duty which already lay previously within
him, and is . . . quickened by the other . . . [to] determine himself
accordingly to the moral law” (27:521). And Kant discusses various ways
in which, for instance, moral education (5:155, 6:479), polite society
(6:473, 7:151), and moral-religious communities (6:94ff.) can enliven
one’s innate moral predisposition.
From the standpoint of the environmental and predispositional
bases of moral motivation, Kant’s account of moral motivation thus fits
well into his general empirical anthropology. Because of the importance
of moral motivation for his transcendental anthropology, however, and
especially the importance of making sense of how a finite, empirically
situated being can be motivated by a pure moral law, Kant adds detailed
specific accounts of the nature of the “feeling of respect” that serves as
the anticipatory “pleasure” causing choice in accordance with the moral
law. Kant’s account of respect for the moral law is notoriously difficult to
interpret. On the one hand, Kant says that “there is indeed no feeling for
this [moral] law” (5:75), but he proceeds to give a detailed analysis of the
“feeling of respect for the moral law,” the “moral feeling” that is
“produced solely by reason” (5:75-6).74
74
Understandably, readers of Kant are largely split into those that favor a “cognitivist” reading of respect –
104 Given that Kant posits both a transcendental and an empirical
anthropology, it is understandable that he might give different accounts
of the role of pleasure in moral motivation. From the standpoint of
transcendental anthropology, pleasure cannot play any role in grounding
decisions to act in accordance with the moral law. If I choose to do what
is right because it is (or will be) pleasurable, I do not choose
autonomously, and hence do not really choose to do what is right.
If the determination of the will takes place . . . by means of a feeling,
of whatever kind, that has to be presupposed in order for the law to
become a sufficient determining ground of the will, so that the action
is not done for the sake of the law, then the action [may] contain
legality indeed, but not morality. (5:71)
As an account of moral choice from the (transcendental) perspective of
deliberation, this is exactly right. Whereas non-moral choices are often
based, directly or indirectly, on various feelings or anticipated feelings,
when one decides to do what is morally good, it should be done because
the choice is morally good. And Kant rightly adds that, from this
transcendental perspective, “how a law can be of itself and immediately a
determine ground of the will . . . is . . . insoluble . . . and identical with . .
. how a free will is possible” (5:72). But the fact that one must see oneself
as free, and as bound to freely adopt the moral law as the law of one’s
will, does not preclude an empirical analysis of what such a free choice
“effects . . . in the mind insofar as it is an incentive” (5:72). That is, Kant
can still explain how it appears when a person freely chooses to follow
the moral law.
In the context of empirical anthropology, Kant could allow,
consistent with his general account of human motivation, that the
thought of the pure moral principle gives rise to volition by means of
pleasure. In his lectures on empirical psychology, Kant even talks about
an “intellectual pleasure” that arises from “representation of the [moral]
law” (29:1024)75 and that serves as the motivational transition from
cognition of that moral law to action in accordance with it. Elsewhere,
however, Kant worries about subsuming his account of moral motivation
too closely under his account of motivation in general. In those contexts,
for whom mere cognition of the moral law, independent of feeling, motivates action in accordance with it –
and those that favor a “sentimentalist” reading of respect within which the feeling of respect plays an
essential motivational role. For detailed studies of these passages, see Allison 1989, Beck 1960, Grenberg
2005, McCarty 1993 and 1994, and Reath 1989.
75
This account fits well with Kant’s insistence in the Critique of Practical Reason that “respect for the
moral law is a feeling that is produced by an intellectual ground” (5:73). See too 19:185-6, R6866; 28:2534, 674-5; 29:890, 899-900, 1013.
105 Kant suggests that “this singular feeling . . . cannot be compared to any
pathological feeling” (5:76, cf. 20:207). In addition to its wholly
intellectual ground, Kant suggests that the feeling of respect is not,
strictly speaking, a feeling at all. Cognition of the moral law directly
causes one to choose in accordance with it, without any specific feeling
functioning as an intermediary. But “inasmuch as it moves resistance [of
inclinations] out of the way, in the judgment of reason this removal of a
hindrance is esteemed equivalent to a positive furthering” and so “this . .
. can be called a feeling of respect for the moral law” (5:75). This account
would involve modifying Kant’s empirical account of action in the context
of moral actions, for which feeling would not properly speaking mediate
between cognition and volition but only provide the subjective impression
of cognition directly causing volitions counter to our inclinations.
Whether, in the end, respect for the moral law functions just like any
other feeling in mediating higher cognition (of the moral law) and volition,
the fundamental structure of Kant’s empirical anthropology allows him to
posit a predisposition to morality that, in conjunction with one’s
character, can ground volitions that are empirically caused by the
cognition of the moral law as such. Kant thus provides a framework for
empirically describing what, from the standpoint of transcendental
anthropology, are free choices of a morally good will.
4. Conclusion
Insofar as they are objects of empirical study, humans are
biological beings with complex mental lives. As biological beings, we have
various predispositions that are best discussed in terms of the purposes
that they serve, and these predispositions provide grounds for causal
laws that determine how our environment shapes our cognitions,
feelings, and desires. The result is a complex causal account that allows
for significant differences between individuals in terms of beliefs,
pleasures, and choices, while still situating these differences in the
context of universal laws of human psychology. So far, this account of
human beings has been relatively free of moral implications. As a strictly
empirical anthropology, there is no direct basis for ascribing moral value
to any particular psychological structures over others. But Kant uses his
empirical anthropology to argue for an important moral claim about
human beings. As we will see in the next chapter, Kant argues that there
is good empirical evidence that human beings have a predispositional
structure that can rightly be called “radically evil.” Moreover, this chapter
has emphasized humans’ empirical nature as both universal and fixed.
But Kant’s empirical anthropology also includes accounts of the historical
106 change of the human species and of significant diversity in humans’
make-up. The next chapter investigates Kant’s account of human
historicity, and we turn to Kant’s account of human diversity in chapter
five.
107 CHAPTER 3: HUMAN EVIL AND HUMAN HISTORY
In the last chapter, we saw that Kant has a detailed empirical
account of human beings. While this account does not rise to the level of
a “science” in Kant’s strict sense, it qualifies as a highly systematic
account of universal human characteristics. In this chapter, we look at
two further and related aspects of Kant’s empirical account of human
beings. These aspects flesh out Kant’s empirical anthropology and
complete the unfinished business left by the Critique of Judgment with
respect to the question of what we may hope for humanity as a species
(see 11:429). First, we look at Kant’s account of human evil. Kant argues
that human beings are evil “by nature” and that evil is “radical” in that it
affects the root of all choices. Despite this apparently glum assessment,
however, Kant endorses a realistic hope for human goodness. Second, we
will look at one component of this hope, Kant’s philosophy of human
history, beginning with the emergence of human beings as a new kind of
animal with a rational nature and moral vocation and progressing
towards a future of perpetual peace amongst nations and increasingly
cosmopolitan political, ethical, and social lives.
I. Radical Evil in Human Nature
a) “The Human Being is Evil by Nature”
Kant discusses human evil in his Anthropology (7:324f.) and in
various lectures and notes on ethics, anthropology, and religion, but his
most sustained discussion of it takes place in Religion within the
Boundaries of Mere Reason, a work in which Kant aims “to make
apparent the relation of religion to a human nature partly laden with
good dispositions and partly with evil ones” (6:11). Religion starts with an
argument for the existence of human evil that is complicated by what
appear to be contradictory claims. At times, Kant seems to rule out the
possibility of knowing anything about one’s moral status at all, saying
such things as that “we can never, even by the strictest examination,
completely plumb the depths of the secret incentives of our actions”
(4:407) and that
108 A human being’s inner experience of himself does not allow him so to
fathom the depths of his heart as to be able to attain, through selfobservation, an entirely reliable cognition of the basis of the maxims
which he professes. (6:63, see too 6:36-37, 8:270)
Elsewhere, Kant suggests that even if we know that human beings are
evil, we should avoid drawing attention to this evil, especially in others:
“It is a duty . . . not to take malicious pleasure in exposing the faults of
others . . . but rather to throw the veil of philanthropy over their faults,
not merely by softening our judgments but by keeping these judgments
to ourselves” (6:466). When Kant does propose arguing for human evil,
he claims that it “can only be proved [by] anthropological research” (6:25)
and that “the existence of this propensity to evil in human nature can be
established through experiential demonstrations” (6:35, see too 6:32),
but he also insists that “the judgment that an agent is an evil human
being cannot reliably be based on experience” (6:20). And insofar as he
does appeal to experience, Kant sometimes seems to argue directly from
“the multitude of woeful examples that the experience of human deeds
parades before us” (6:32-33), but elsewhere insists that his claim that
“the whole species” is evil can be justified only “if it transpires from
anthropological research that the grounds that justify us in attributing . .
. [evil] to human beings . . . are of such a nature that there is no cause
for exempting anyone from it” (6:25), which suggests that mere examples
of evil, even if widespread, are insufficient. From a quick look at these
passages, it becomes unclear whether there can even be an argument for
human evil, and if there is, whether that argument is a priori or
empirical.76
Fortunately, things are not as hopeless as they seem, and Kant’s
various statements fit together into a complicated but plausible
anthropological defense of human evil. The key to putting together Kant’s
argument comes at the very beginning of his Religion, in “Part One: . . .
Of the Radical Evil in Human Nature”:
We call a human being evil . . . not because he performs actions that
are evil . . ., but because these are so constituted that they allow the
inference of evil maxims in him . . . In order . . . to call a human
being evil, it must be possible to infer a priori from a number of
consciously evil actions, or even from a single one, an underlying evil
maxim. (6:20)
76
For various views on Kant’s account of and arguments for radical evil, see Allison 1990, 2001; Frierson
2003; Grenberg 2006; Wood 2009 and 2000:287
109 Kant’s argument for evil involves both an empirical component (the
experience of “a number of evil actions”) and an a priori component that
justifies the inference from these to the “evil maxim” that underlies them.
The rest of this section unpacks this argument and its implications for
the nature of human evil.
The passage above implies that one can infer one’s maxims from
one’s actions. While this might seem to contradict the claims quoted
above about the impossibility of self-knowledge, Kant is actually
remarkably consistent. Whenever Kant emphasizes the inscrutability of
humans’ motives, he emphasizes only that we can never know that our
maxims are good.77 But with moral evil, the case is different. While there
are no actions that cannot be done from bad motives, there are some
actions that cannot be done from good motives. Kant’s reference, in the
above quotation, to “actions that are evil” and his specification of these
as “contrary to law,” is important. Generally, for Kant, it is maxims
rather than actions that are good or evil. But there are “actions . . .
contrary to duty” (4:397), and in his Metaphysics of Morals, Kant
articulates a political theory based on the intrinsic wrongness of actions
that cannot “coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a
universal law” (6:231). Precisely because these actions are wrong
regardless of the end for which one performs them, one can legitimately
infer bad underlying maxims from the performance of such actions.
Moreover, because moral inscrutability comes partly from humans’
tendency to self-flattery, it is implausible that one would pretend to a
motive less noble than one’s actual motive, so when one finds an evil
motive in oneself, one can reasonably trust that there is no underlying
righteous motive. Motivational inscrutability is asymmetrical: one can
never know that a person – including oneself – is morally good, but one
can know that people are evil.
Even if Kant’s claims about inscrutability do not preclude
knowledge of human evil, though, how can Kant make inferences from
experience to the existence of human evil given that “the judgment that
an agent is an evil human being cannot reliably be based on experience”
77
One’s moral status is inscrutable because any action that accords with the moral law might also be done
from some (hidden) inclination and because human beings have a self-deceptive tendency to overestimate
the moral worth of our actions. In the passages quoted above, when Kant says that “we can never . . . plumb
the depths of the secret incentives of our actions” (4:407), this is a response to the fact that “We like to
flatter ourselves with the false claim to a more noble motive” (4:407). And when Kant insists that a human
being cannot “fathom the depths of his heart,” (R 6:63), the problem is that we cannot tell whether our
maxims have the “purity and stability” necessary to be morally good. (There is another, more metaphysical,
reason for inscrutability. Since the maxims that are relevant to assessing moral worth are freely chosen and
thus “noumenal,” they can never be objects of “knowledge” in Kant’s strict sense. For discussion of this
point, see Frierson 2003.)
110 (6:20)? Neither experience nor a priori arguments alone are sufficient for
Kant’s proof of evil (hence both are necessary). Experience of actions
contrary to duty would not be sufficient for ascribing an evil will to
human beings without an argument that links those actions to evil
maxims. So what is needed in order to move from evil actions to evil
maxims? Given evil actions, one knows that if those actions are
grounded in freely chosen maxims, then the maxims are evil. So in order
to establish a connection between evil actions and evil maxims, all that is
needed is an argument that human beings are free agents who choose in
accordance with maxims that can ground evil actions such as those
found in experience. Kant already provided much of this account in his
transcendental anthropology. In his Religion, Kant insists that
“experience can never expose the root of evil in the supreme maxim of a
free power of choice, for, as intelligible deed, the maxim precedes all
experience” (6:39n), but Kant’s transcendental anthropology has already
shown that human actions are the phenomenal expressions of
noumenal, free choices; we act only on the basis of incentives that we
freely incorporate into maxims of action.78
In Religion, Kant adds to his general account of human
transcendental freedom an account of the specific structure of the
fundamental maxim that grounds evil actions. In particular, Kant makes
two important additions to the account of free choice found elsewhere in
his Critical philosophy. First, he argues that human choices must be
grounded in a basic maxim that is either fundamentally good or
fundamentally evil; no middle ground is possible. As Kant puts it,
[I]f [someone] is good in one part [of life], he has incorporated the
moral law into his maxim. And were he . . . to be evil in some other
part, since the moral law of compliance with duty in general is a
single one and universal, the maxim relating to it would be universal
yet particular at the same time: which is contradictory. (R 6:24-5)
Because morality requires unconditional and universal compliance
(4:416), one who sometimes but not always acts in conformity with the
moral law never really makes the moral law his ultimate motive, since
any law whose application depends upon circumstances cannot be the
moral law.
Second, Kant connects the account of humans’ free finitude from
his transcendental anthropology with the account of human
predispositions in his empirical anthropology. As we saw in the last
78
We discussed this principle in terms of the “Incorporation Thesis” in chapter one. For a discussion of the
relationship between empirical claims about human motivation and the ascription of transcendental
freedom to them, see Frierson 2008.
111 chapter, Kant’s conception of a “predisposition” has wide application,
covering all basic human powers and the instincts and propensities that
direct the faculty of desire. In Religion, Kant employs this notion of a
predisposition in his discussion of a fundamental “predisposition to the
good” in human nature that consists of three distinct “elements of the
determination of the human being,” animality, humanity, and personality
(6:26-7, cf. 7:322-5). The predisposition to animality includes basic
instincts and even propensities to various inclinations that support
human life. In particular, Kant emphasizes instincts for self-preservation,
for propagation of the species (sexual instinct), and “for community with
other humans, i.e. the social drive” (6:26). The predisposition to
humanity includes our innate tendency to compare ourselves with others
and thereby a propensity to “the inclination to gain worth in the opinion
of others” (6:27). Finally, the predisposition to personality is
“susceptibility to respect for the moral law as of itself a sufficient
incentive in the power of choice” (6:27). As we saw in the last chapter,
higher cognitions are generally capable of determining the power of
choice, but there is a particular predisposition by virtue of which a pure
higher cognition is capable of determining choice.
By subsuming the variety of human volitional predispositions
under the general category of “predisposition to the good,” Kant
emphasizes that no natural human instincts or inclinations are evil in
themselves: “the ground of evil cannot . . . be placed . . . in the sensuous
nature of the human being” (6:34). But because the good predispositions
of human beings include some that are not unconditionally or morally
good, there is a basis in human nature for evil.
The human being (even the worst) does not repudiate the moral law .
. . The law rather imposes itself on him irresistibly, because of his
moral predisposition; and if no other incentive were at work in him,
he would also incorporate it into his supreme maxim as sufficient
determination of his power of choice . . . He is, however, also
dependent upon the incentives of his sensuous nature because of his
equally innocent natural predisposition, and he incorporates them
too into his maxim . . . Hence the difference, whether the human
being is good or evil, must not lie in the difference between the
incentives that he incorporates into his maxim . . . but in their
subordination . . .: which of the two he makes the condition of the
other. It follows that the human being (even the best) is evil only
because he reverses the moral order of his incentives in incorporating
them into his maxims. (6:36, see too 6:32)
112 In this important passage, Kant lays out the essence of his account of
human evil. Importantly, the account can be read both in terms of
transcendental freedom and in terms of empirical anthropology.
The
transcendental reading is crucial since in the absence of a
transcendental perspective on the subordination of moral to nonmoral
incentives, no empirical claim can imply anything about human evil: “In
freedom alone is evil” (18:212, cf. 27:295). From the perspective of
freedom, when one looks at one’s action from-within, what Kant claims
here is that in all choices, we have concern both for morality and for
well-being (defined in terms of animal and social inclinations), but that
ultimately, we subordinate one concern to the other. Our free (noumenal)
nature is constituted by whether we unconditionally prioritize the moral
law to nonmoral concerns or whether we allow nonmoral concerns of
sufficient weight to trump the moral law. This aspect of Kant’s account
depends crucially upon the account of morality from Kant’s
transcendental anthropology, within which Kant shows both that human
beings are transcendentally free and that morality requires unconditional
obedience. Here, Kant uses these claims to argue that because morality
requires unconditional obedience from a transcendentally free will, any
subordination of moral to nonmoral concerns is wholly evil.79
But Kant’s argument for human evil is not merely an argument
directed towards helping readers recognize evil from-within. He also aims
to make an empirical-anthropological point, that human beings are evil
by nature. From the standpoint of empirical anthropology, the key
passage above can be read as a step towards completing his empirical
account of human nature. Human beings have various predispositions
that can be classified in terms of animal instincts, social inclinations for
recognition, and moral interests. But a complete empirical account of
human beings must discern how these needs interact in cases when
more than one is active. Kant thus looks for empirical evidence to
suggest that the empirical character of human volition is structured such
that moral grounds are inactive when they conflict with sufficiently
strong nonmoral grounds. What is this empirical evidence? At the most
fundamental level, Kant finds in the “multitude of woeful examples” of
human misdeeds evidence for the empirical claim that humans’ volitional
79
Kant highlights the from-within character of his argument by addressing it to individual, free agents. He
emphasizes that we “notice (at least within ourselves) [actions that] are consciously contrary to [moral]
law” (6:20) and gives examples of vices, especially those in civilized society, that his readers will –
reluctantly – have to admit as applying to themselves. When he concludes his argument for evil in human
nature, he even emphasizes this personal aspect of it. Whether or not “every man has his price, for which he
sells himself” is something, Kant suggests, that “everyone can decide for himself” (6:39).
113 structure is such that moral incentives are subordinated to nonmoral
ones. To show that this corrupt volitional structure cannot be ascribed to
societal influence alone, Kant points out the presence of “unprovoked
cruelty” in the state of nature, and to show that this corrupt volition is
not limited to uncivilized savages, he lays out a host of vices of the
“civilized state,” including “secret falsity even in the most intimate
friendship . . . , a propensity to hate him to whom we are indebted . . .,
many other vices yet hidden under the appearance of virtue, [and] those
of which no secret is made [wherein] . . . someone already counts as good
when his evil is common to a class” (6:33). This evidence gives Kant
grounds for the empirical-anthropological claim that humans’ particular
choices are grounded in a power of choice wherein moral predispositions
are subordinated to nonmoral ones. Humans have predispositions that
make evil possible and a volitional structure in which the moral
predisposition is made inactive by sufficiently strong sensuous
incentives. Given our transcendental freedom (established by Kant’s
transcendental anthropology), human beings are thus evil.
Transcendentally speaking, there is no necessity for human beings to
have this volitional structure; it is contingent upon transcendentally free
choice. But empirically speaking, when one seeks to discern human
nature based on empirical evidence, there is good reason to think that
human volition subordinates pure higher volition to impure higher
volition. And given that Kant’s transcendental anthropology shows this
empirical character to be grounded in free choice, there is reason to
describe this subordination as “evil.”
In the end, Kant’s argument for evil in human nature is simple in
outline and rich in detail.
1. In widely varying circumstances, human beings perform actions
that contradict the moral law and/or consciously perform actions
that are immoral.
2. Human actions result from the influence of empirical causes
through ordered predispositions that determine how empirical causes
effect particular actions.
3. Human beings have both a moral predisposition according to
which they can be motivated by the moral law and nonmoral
predispositions to pursue natural and social goods.
4. The moral law is essentially unconditional, requiring stable and
pure adherence.
114 5. Thus, human behavior is characterized by a prioritization of
nonmoral predispositions over the moral predisposition.
6. Humans’ empirical behavior and character express their
transcendentally free choices.
7. Thus, human beings are morally evil.
The first three premises are empirical generalizations, of different levels
of complexity. The first is a straightforward generalization of observations
about human beings. The second and third80 generalize an
anthropological explanatory model from a number of cases in which it
has been observed to be a good explanation for observed human
behavior. These premises are developed in much greater empirical detail,
as we showed in chapter two. The fourth premise is a moral premise, a
part of Kant’s a priori, transcendental anthropology of volition. The
evidence for this claim is thus a priori. In the context of a properly
empirical argument, this a priori premise would be taken as stipulative.
In that sense, the preliminary conclusion at (5) could be taken to be a
properly empirical-anthropological conclusion. Given that prioritizing the
moral predisposition would involve (by definition) consistency in following
that predisposition, it is clear from premises (1)-(3) that human beings
act according to a complex structure of predispositions within which the
“moral” predisposition is subordinated to others. And in that sense, (5)
expresses an empirical fact about human nature. But premise (6) is
essentially transcendental; there is no empirical evidence for humans’
status as free grounds of their empirical characters. Given this premise,
however, the prioritization of nonmoral predispositions over the moral
predisposition that was shown to be a part of human nature is also
revealed as an expression of moral evil. The conclusion which is both
transcendental (a priori) and empirical, is that human beings are evil by
nature, that is, that moral evil can be ascribed to every member of the
human species.
b) The nature of radical evil
Having shown that human beings are evil, Kant elaborates on the
nature of evil. Most importantly, Kant emphasizes that human evil is
80
In his Critique of Practical Reason, Kant also offers an “a priori” argument for his third premise (see
5:78). Given our obligations, we can know a priori that we have a capacity to act out of respect for the
moral law, which implies that we have a power to do so. For the purposes of his proof in the Religion,
however, this premise is taken as part of Kant’s empirical anthropology.
115 “radical” in that “it corrupts . . . the subjective supreme ground of all
maxims” (6:37). The “maxim” by which humans subordinate moral to
nonmoral incentives is their most fundamental maxim. In general,
humans act in accordance with various principles (maxims) of action,
which can be ordered in a kind of hierarchy. To take one of Kant’s own
examples, one might act on the maxim “when I believe myself in need of
money I shall borrow money and promise to repay it, even though I know
that this will never happen” (4:422), but this maxim is merely a
particular application of more general maxims such as “I will trust my
own assessments of my needs” and “when I can make use of others to
satisfy my needs, I will do so (regardless of whether I treat them as ends
when I do so),” and this latter maxim is a more specific application of an
even more general maxim that Kant explains in terms of the relative
subordination of inclinations and morality, something like “I will obey the
moral law only insofar as doing so is compatible with satisfying other
desires, and I will seek to satisfy some nonmoral desires.” This maxim,
Kant suggests, is the fundamental guiding maxim of an evil human
being’s life, and all other maxims are merely applications to particular
cases where inclinations and/or the moral law are in play. Because this
corrupt maxim lies at the root of all one’s choices, Kant refers to human
beings as “radically evil.”
In laying out this account of radical evil, Kant also clarifies some
important details about the nature of evil. For one thing, radical evil is
not only “itself morally evil, since it must ultimately be sought in a free
power of choice” (6:37), but it is also tied to a “natural propensity to evil”
that structures particular evil choices that human beings make.81
Moreover, the source of radical evil in choice implies that radical evil
“cannot be placed, as is commonly done, in the sensuous nature of the
human being and in the natural inclinations originating from it” (6:34-5).
At one level, this claim should be quite obvious. As a moral category, evil
cannot properly be located in the human being qua object of empirical
investigation but must be traced to the free, noumenal agent that
grounds empirically observable behavior. But Kant’s claim shifts the
focus even within empirical character. The empirical expression of
radical evil is not in the lower faculties – the senses and inclinations –
but in the higher faculties, especially in the higher faculty of desire.
Human agents, even as empirically observed, have a capacity – what
Kant calls “the power of choice” – to act from principles, and it is the way
81
Many commentators see this propensity to evil as a precondition of radical evil (cf. Allison 1990, Wood
2000), but I see Kant as portraying the propensity to evil as both a consequence of humans’ radical evil and
as a ground of further evil choices (see Frierson 2003).
116 in which this capacity is used that gives empirical evidence of freely
chosen evil.
Kant also describes three ways in which evil might express itself in
one’s choices: frailty, impurity, and depravity. The first involves merely a
lack of character, or what Kant calls in his anthropology lectures a “bad
character,” an “inability to act according to principle” (25:650). In these
cases, the principles of one’s higher faculty of desire are good, but when
it comes to acting, these principles do not actually determine one’s
actions. As we noted in the last chapter, there can be conflicting
underlying grounds of action, and often one or more powers are “dead” or
“inactive” while others are active in effecting a transition to a new mental
state or an action. Those with frail wills understand the principles
according to which they should act, and the character of their higher
faculty of desire is such that “I incorporate the good (law) into the maxim
of my power of choice, but this good . . . is subjectively the weaker (in
comparison with inclination) whenever the maxim is to be followed”
(6:29). In the paradigm cases of frailty, one’s higher faculty of desire is
properly oriented such that, if active, it would cause one to do what is
right. But when the relevant moment comes, the higher faculty of desire
is weaker than inclination (the lower faculty of desire) and hence
inactive. We might imagine more complex cases, where inclination does
not wholly overcome the higher faculty of desire but prevents it from
actually bringing about effects in accordance with its character; here the
inclination subverts the normal operation of the higher faculty, rather
than preventing its operation altogether. In these cases, the propensity to
be governed by fixed principles is not fully developed. And Religion
argues that this empirically observable badness of character can be
ascribed to a free (noumenal) choice to subordinate morality to
inclination.
The other two forms of evil are more straightforward; both involve
acting in accordance with principles of a corrupted higher faculty of
desire. “Impurity” occurs when one’s “maxim is good with respect to its
object . . . [but] has not . . . adopted the law alone as its sufficient
incentive” (6:30). One who is impure generally chooses what is morally
required, but always only because it is both morally required and
conducive to satisfying other desires. This conditional adherence to the
moral law is, as Kant’s argument for rigorism shows, no adherence at all.
The final form of radical evil is “depravity,” which involves a specific
“propensity of the power of choice to maxims that subordinate the
incentives of the moral law to others (not moral ones)” (6:30). One who is
depraved might still often act in ways that seem moral, but the depraved
person’s power of choice is structured by a fundamental commitment to
117 nonmoral desires, regardless of whether these are morally permitted or
not.
Importantly, Kant rejects the possibility of what he calls “diabolical”
evil, the “disposition . . . to incorporate evil qua evil . . . into one’s
maxim” (6:37). For Kant, even the most evil person is not motivated by
evil as such. There are no immoral desires in human beings, since all
desires can be traced to one form of the predisposition to the good. One
is evil when one allows nonmoral desires to trump the moral law, not
when one chooses evil as such. Thus Kant does not allow the possibility
of cases like St. Augustine’s famous theft of pears “not to eat for
ourselves, but simply to throw to the pigs[, for] our real pleasure
consisted in doing something that was forbidden” (Augustine 1961: 47).
For Kant, Augustine’s self-diagnosis must be mistaken; human beings do
not have a desire to do what is morally forbidden per se. Evil arises only
from putting nonmoral desires ahead of our innate moral predisposition.
Finally, it is important to note that in all of these cases, radical evil
need not imply that one always chooses contrary to the moral law. To be
evil is to be disposed to allow the moral law to be overridden given a
sufficient sensuous incentive.
A member of the English Parliament exclaimed in the heat of debate:
“Every man has his price, for which he sells himself.” If this is true
(and everyone can decide for himself), if nowhere is a virtue which no
level of temptation can overthrow, if whether good or evil wins us over
only depends on which bids the most and affords the promptest payoff, then what the Apostle says might indeed hold true of human
beings universally, “There is no distinction here, they are all under
sin – there is none righteous (in the spirit of the law), no, not one.”
(6:39)
Frailty, impurity, and even depravity all involve, in different ways, a
subordination of the moral law to nonmoral desires. But one can be
radically evil and still often do what is good, if one does what is good only
because the price of doing good is, in a particular case, not too high.
c) The problem of radical evil
Kant’s claim that human beings are radically evil raises a serious
problem at the intersection of transcendental and empirical
anthropology, a problem that Kant spends the rest of his Religion trying
to solve. Put simply, the problem is that evil seems inextirpable.
118 This evil is radical, since it corrupts the grounds of all maxims; as a
natural propensity, it is also not to be extirpated through human
forces, for this could happen only through good maxims – something
that cannot take place if the subjective supreme ground of all
maxims is presupposed to be corrupted. (6:37, cf. 6:45)
Because evil lies at the root of human choice, one cannot extirpate it
through that same (evil) power of choice. One might think that being evil
“by nature” precludes transcendental freedom and thus moral
responsibility, but for Kant, we are evil “by nature” through our free
choice. Radical evil is a consequence of humans’ use of their
transcendental freedom; it is only because we freely choose to
subordinate moral to nonmoral incentives that such a choice can be
considered evil. But given that we freely choose evil as the basis of all of
our other choices, it seems impossible to use that freedom to rid ourselves
of evil.82 That is, it seems impossible that we can both choose evil and
choose to extirpate that evil. And the problem of radical evil is made even
worse by our propensity to evil. Human beings not only choose in evil
ways but also deliberately cultivate both themselves and their
environment (especially their social environment) in order to promote the
easy exercise of evil tendencies. One whose evil manifests itself primarily
in a frail will, for example, has cultivated a weakness of character that
will be hard to overcome even if one tries to do so. And one who is
depraved has developed patterns of self-deceptive moral justification and
corrupting social interaction that will make it difficult for good intentions
to fully overcome selfishness. Finally, the problem is even more acute
because no matter how good one might be able to become, one has
chosen badly, so one can never be a person who always chooses in
accordance with the moral law:
however steadfastly a human being may have persevered in such a
[good] disposition in a life conduct conformable to it, he nevertheless
started from evil, and this is a debt which is impossible for him to
wipe out. (6:72)83
Altogether, not only is one’s choice oriented in such a way that one
rejects moral reform (radical evil), but even if one were somehow to begin
82
The case here is similar to the case of “passions,” of which Kant says in his Anthropology that “they are
incurable because the sick person does not want to be cured and flees from the dominion of principles by
which alone a cure could occur” (7:266).
83
There are obvious connections between Kant’s account of evil and the Christian doctrine of original sin.
Although I do not read the Religion as merely a rational reconstruction of Christian doctrine, the
similarities are undeniable. For more, see Adams 1998; Hare 1996; and Quinn 1984, 1986, and 1990.
119 such a process of reform, one would have to contend with self-wrought
influences that make morally upright action difficult (the propensity to
evil), and even if one somehow overcame these influences, one would
never have a life that was wholly good from start to finish (one started
from evil).
The inextirpability of radical evil need not pose a philosophical
problem for Kant. Kant might just say that the empirical evidence shows
that human beings are radically evil through their own fault, and so
much the worse for us. Even Kant’s claim that “ought implies can” need
not be compromised by the claim of radical evil because radical evil is an
evil that is self-wrought through our own freedom. Humans could be
good, but we universally (but not necessarily) choose not to be; evil’s
“inextirpability” is due to choice, not a constraint on it. But Kant is
committed to a moral vision that goes beyond mere insistence upon
moral responsibility for wrongdoing: “In spite of the fall, the command
that we ought to become better human beings still resounds unabated in
our souls; consequently, we must also be capable of it” (6:45). Even if
radical evil does not eliminate moral responsibility, it does seem to deny
the real possibility of moral reform, which would undermine the force of
the obligation to improve. In response, Kant defends moral hope, the
possibility of reforming oneself morally despite one’s radical evil. And this
commitment to hope generates a problem: how can one reconcile moral
rigorism, radical evil, and moral hope?84
At one important level, Kant does not even try to explain how moral
reform is possible given radical evil. When he points out that evil cannot
be extirpated, he adds “through human forces” (R 6:37) and then
suggests, “Some supernatural cooperation is also needed to [a person]
becoming good or better” (R 6:44).85 But this “supernatural cooperation”
is ultimately beyond rational comprehension and even practical use.86
The main role of such cooperation, which Kant calls “grace,” is simply to
reinforce the need for human beings to do their part to “make themselves
antecedently worthy of receiving it” (R 6:44, cf. 6:118). Kant emphasizes
that the inscrutability of grace is no greater than the inscrutability of
freedom and even that humans’ continuing recognition of their moral
obligations reveals an enduring “germ of goodness . . . that cannot be
extirpated or corrupted” (R 6:45-6; see too 6:49; SF 7:43, 58-9; A 7:322).
The enduring germ of goodness shows that all people still have a capacity
for goodness, and one’s freedom gives an enduring but inexplicable hope
84
For discussion of this problem in similar terms, see Hare 1996.
For discussion and further references, see Frierson, 2003, pp. 114-22.
86
E.g. R 6:117-8, 191; SF 7:43-4. For discussion, see Mariña 1997, Frierson 2003, and Adams 1998.
85
120 that this capacity can still be used well. Of course, none of these claims
about inscrutability actually address the central problem of radical evil.
Even grace seems inadequate, absent further explanation and especially
given Kant’s insistence on humans’ need to be antecedently worthy of
that grace.
But Kant’s theoretically inadequate discussion of radical evil does
highlight the proper stance to take towards the problem. Given his
transcendental anthropology of cognition, Kant is surely correct that the
metaphysical mechanisms by virtue of which radical evil might be
overcome will never be understood by human beings. But the problem of
radical evil is not, fundamentally, a metaphysical problem but a practical
one. What ought one do in light of radical evil and what may one hope
with respect to it? In one sense, the practical aspect of radical evil is easy
to address. If evil is a free choice to subordinate the moral law to
nonmoral desires, then what one must do is subordinate one’s nonmoral
desires to the moral law. Here Kant can do little more than exhort people
to goodness and warn against self-deceptive despair or weakening of
moral demands.87 But radical evil is also a self-wrought tendency to act
immorally, and it is, moreover, a tendency that is in evidence in the
human by nature. And these aspects of radical evil require some account
of the grounds for moral hope in the human species as a whole as well as
an account of how one can work to undo and arm oneself against selfwrought evil tendencies. Kant deals with the former task in his
sophisticated philosophy of human history, a history situated in the
context of radical evil but one that justifies hope in humanity’s future.
Kant deals with the second task in his “moral anthropology,” which deals
with “the subjective conditions in human nature that hinder people or
help them in fulfilling [moral] laws . . ., with the development, spreading,
and strengthening of moral principles” (6:217). The rest of this chapter
focuses on Kant’s philosophy of history. Kant’s moral anthropology will
be discussed in chapter five.
II. Human Beings as a Historical Species
87
To be fair, Kant’s doctrine of grace can do a bit more than mere exhortation. Kant offers a detailed
account of justificatory grace whereby suffering in one’s life atones for the misdeeds of one’s past and
within which progress towards the good comes to be counted as perfect goodness. For discussion of these
more specifically religious aspects of Kant’s justification of moral hope, see Quinn 1984, 1990; Mariña
1997; Michaelson 1990; Frierson 2003, 2007b, and 2010b. My focus in this book will be on more
specifically “anthropological” answers to the question of what one may hope, both through Kant’s
conception of historical progress and through his account of the moral anthropology that radical evil makes
necessary and grace makes possible.
121 While Kant’s conception of human evil draws from and leads to a
historical conception of human beings, Kant is not generally known for
his philosophy of history, and a historical conception of human beings
can seem to be at odds with other important aspects of Kant’s
philosophy. Nonetheless, during the height of work on his transcendental
philosophy, Kant wrote a series of papers on human history that develop
his empirical anthropology through, among other things, the claim that
human “predispositions . . . develop completely only in the species [and
over history], but not in the individual” (8:18). The rest of this chapter
lays out this historical conception of humanity.
a) Methodology
Like the anthropology discussed in the last chapter, Kant’s
historical methodology is primarily empirical. Kant begins his “Idea”
essay by emphasizing this point:
Whatever concept one may form of the freedom of the will with a
metaphysical aim, its appearances, the human actions, are
determined just as much as every other natural occurrence in
accordance with universal laws of nature. History, which concerns
itself with the narration of these appearances, however deeply
concealed their causes may be, nevertheless allows us to hope from it
that if it considers the play of the freedom of the human will in the
large, it can discover within it a regular course. (8:17)
But history is not “mere empirical groping without a guiding principle”
(8:161), and Kant’s account of predispositions provides this principle.
While the empirical anthropology of the previous chapter focused on
predispositions as bases of causal powers, Kant’s history studies
predispositions teleologically. In his Critique of Judgment, Kant argued
that organic life could be interpreted via purposive predispositions: all
organisms are “conceived of teleologically under the concept of a natural
end” (5:376). In his writings on history, Kant adds an important
presupposition of ascribing any purposive structure to an organic being:
All natural predispositions of a creature are determined sometime to
develop themselves completely and purposively. . . An organ that is
not to be used, an arrangement that does not attain to its end, is a
contradiction in the teleological doctrine of nature. For if we depart
from that principle then we no longer have a lawful nature but a
purposelessly playing nature; and desolate chance takes the place of
the guideline of reason. (8:18)
122 For most animals, this teleological assumption has implications only for
the study of individual organisms. To identify a feature of an organism as
a physical or behavioral predisposition, one must assume that it serves a
purpose, which implies that at some point in the development of the
organism, the feature will develop in the way needed to serve that
purpose. For human beings, however, some predispositions are not fully
realized in the life of any single person. The full development of human
reason in the arts, sciences, and politics does not occur in any
individual’s life but happens over the history of the species. But insofar
as one still treats capacities such as reason as natural predispositions,
one must apply the same regulative principles to them as to other
predispositions; one assumes that they will develop toward their end.
And this assumption provides an “Idea” that can underlie a rationallyguided but empirically-based history that looks for ways in which
humans’ natural predispositions unfold over time.
b) The beginning of human history
Kant’s treatment of the earliest human history is laid out in
“Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History,” which offers a quasiscientific commentary on the story of humans’ creation from Genesis.
While some philosophers and anthropologists in the 18th century sought
to show how human beings developed from other primates – the issue of
the relationship between the upright posture and human reasoning was
a hot topic of the day – Kant starts with “the existence of the human
being . . . in his fully formed state . . . [and] in a couple” (8:110, see too
8:179). By “fully formed” Kant means only that the humans have all of
their natural predispositions, not that these are all fully developed, but
even this assumption means that Kant does not need to explain, as his
student Herder aimed to do, how “psychology” arises from “determinate
physiology,” how higher cognitions arise from the contractions and
expansions of “irritated little fiber[s]” (Herder 2002: 196,189). Instead,
Kant starts with primitive rational and sexual beings and shows how
humans developed from that stage. In this essay, the key development
that inaugurates truly human history is “the first development of
freedom from its original predisposition in the nature of the human
being” (8:109). In his “Idea,” Kant had argued that “Nature has willed
that the human being should produce everything that goes beyond the
mechanical arrangement of his animal existence entirely out of himself”
123 (8:19), and “Conjectures” shows how an animal with the mere potential
for this sort of free species-development comes to have actual freedom.88
Kant outlines four steps into actualized human freedom. Blending
Genesis with Rousseau, Kant first describes how human beings come to
desire objects that are not natural objects of instinct:
Instinct . . . guided the novice. It allowed him a few things for
nourishment but forbade him others . . . Yet reason soon began to
stir and sought through comparison of that which gratified with that
which was represented to him by another sense than the one to
which instinct was bound, such as the sense of sight, as similar to
what previously was gratifying, to extend his knowledge of the means
of nourishment beyond the limits of instinct . . . The occasion for
deserting the natural drive might have been only something trivial;
yet the success of the first attempt . . . was . . . decisive for his way of
being. (8:111-12)
The first stage in the development of human freedom comes when
humans’ cognitive faculties develop to the point at which they are
capable of modifying desires. Whereas the earliest humans pursued
objects to which they were instinctually drawn, at some point human
beings decide to try “a [new] fruit whose outword look, by its similarity
with other pleasant fruits . . ., invited him to the attempt” (8:112).
Humans’ faculties of desire are no longer wholly at the mercy of their
lower, sensory faculties of cognition, but become capable of control by
the higher faculty of cognition, by conceptual awareness and principles
for action.
Following Rousseau (and Genesis), Kant does not see this first step
into freedom as wholly beneficial. The ability to generate new desires
includes an ability to generate unhealthy desires; one can “concoct
desires not only without a natural drive . . . but even contrary to it”
(8:111). Moreover, freedom over desires causes a new problem:
Anxiety and fright . . . concerning how he, who still did not know the
hidden properties and remote effects of any thing, should deal with
this newly discovered faculty. He stood, as it were, on the brink of an
abyss; for instead of the single objects of his desire to which instinct
88
This freedom is still merely empirical, in that it is part of an empirical-historical account of human
beings. It is a sort of capacity to act on the basis of principles (character) rather than mere inclinations.
Because this empirical sort of freedom is correlated, for Kant, with transcendental freedom (see Frierson
2008), one might see this as the historical origin of transcendental freedom. Strictly speaking, however,
Kant’s history of humanity, as a part of his empirical anthropology, cannot describe how transcendental
freedom emerges.
124 had up to now directed him, there opened up an infinity of them, and
he did not know how to relate to the choice of them. (8:112)
One motivated solely by the lower faculty of desire need barely think
about proper means to one’s ends. But once capable of generating new
desires through reasoning, one must decide which objects are worth
pursuing among an apparently infinite expanse of possibilities. But one
still lacks any framework for making such determinations.
While the first stage in human freedom transformed desires in
general (especially desires oriented towards personal physical needs), the
second stage transforms the most intense and powerful social instinct in
human beings: the sexual instinct. Following Rousseau, Kant sees a
fundamental difference between the raw desire for sex and the way in
which sexuality plays out in human life. Human beings overlay onto their
desire for sexual gratification an interest in the beauty and even
personality of the sex object. Picking up on the Biblical reference to
Adam and Eve covering themselves with fig leaves, Kant envisages
reason’s rising influence over human desires. By covering themselves,89
Adam and Eve make themselves more desirable, and the sexual instinct
gets infused with ideals of beauty and propriety. Here reason “make[s] an
inclination more inward and enduring by withdrawing its object from the
senses,” which “shows already the consciousness of some dominion of
reason over impulse and not merely, as in the first step, a faculty for
doing service to those impulses within a lesser or greater extension”
(8:113).
The third step involves the “deliberate expectation of the future”
(8:113), which requires still higher and more organized interactions
between reason and desire. Like the first steps, the effects of this are
ambivalent: it “is the most decisive mark of the human advantage of
preparing himself to pursue distant ends in accordance with his vocation
– but also simultaneously it is the most inexhaustible source of cares
and worries which the uncertain future incites and from which all [other]
animals are exempt” (8:113).
Finally, in the last stage the human being “comprehended (however
obscurely) that he was the genuine end of nature” (8:114). Human beings
come to see the products of nature as possible instruments for their own
use (cf. Genesis 3:21), but they also recognize – albeit obscurely – that
every other human being is an “equal participant in the gifts of nature”
89
In the account in “Conjectures,” Kant sees this artifice of refusal as used by both Adam and Eve.
Elsewhere (cf. Anthropology, Observations, Remarks) Kant suggests that the art of refusal is a distinctively
feminine art.
125 and thus can rightly make “the claim of being himself an end, of also
being esteemed as such . . ., and of being used by no one merely as a
means to other ends” (8:114). Kant does not, of course, think that the
earliest human beings had worked out theories of human rights, nor that
they actually treated all other human beings as equals. Kant is well
aware that human beings seek to dominate each other and treat others
as mere instruments to personal ends. But this domination among
human beings has, according to Kant, a fundamentally different
character than the struggle with the rest of nature. Among beings who
are all capable of forming plans for themselves on the basis of “a faculty
of choosing . . . a way of living” (8:112), influence takes a form either of
blameworthy domination or of cooperation.
c) The development of human history
The emergence into freedom marks only the beginning of Kant’s
historical account of humans. Before emerging into freedom, human
beings were distinguished from animals only by latent predispositions to
higher cognitive and volitional faculties. But upon becoming free,
humans could become a truly historical species. At this stage, the
importance of the claim that “human . . . predispositions . . . develop
completely only in the species” (8:18) comes to the fore, and Kant adds to
this a further claim central to his account of human history: “Nature has
willed that the human being should . . . participate in no other happiness
or perfection than that which he has procured for himself free from
instinct through his own reason” (8:19). A human’s faculty of choosing
for himself a way of living combined with his decisive ability to “prepar[e]
himself to pursue distant ends in accordance with his vocation”
generates the structure of human history, according to which all
development of human predispositions occurs by humans’ own
deliberate work. But Kant almost immediately adds an important caveat
to this emphasis on freedom. While human history progresses by means
of human choices, Nature90 uses human choices to achieve ends that
diverge from the immediate ends of the choices themselves.
The means nature employs in order to bring about the development
of all [humans’] natural predispositions is . . . the unsocial sociability
of human beings, i.e., their propensity to enter into society, . . .
combined with a thoroughgoing resistance that constantly threatens
to break up this society. (8:20)
90
Throughout his writings on history, Kant associates Nature with “Providence” on the grounds that
“supreme wisdom is required for the fulfillment of this end” (8:310).
126 Human beings have both a natural inclination to enter into society with
others and a desire to exert superiority over others. Elsewhere, Kant
explains that humans have a set of “predispositions to humanity” that
“can be brought under the general title of a self-love that is physical and
yet involves comparison . . . that is, only in comparison with others does
one judge oneself happy” (6:27). One must be in the company of others
(in order to compare oneself to them), but because “the inclination to
gain . . . equal worth” fast becomes “an unjust desire to acquire
superiority for oneself over others” (6:27), there arises constant strife as
each seeks to assert superiority over others, even when this superiority
brings no further advantage in terms of natural needs. Humans can
bring themselves neither to leave the company of others nor to willingly
subordinate their desires to those of their fellows.
For Kant, this “unsocial sociability” is the primary driving force of
human progress: “it is this resistance that awakens all the powers of the
human being [and] brings him to overcome his propensity to indolence”
(8:21). Like Rousseau, Kant suggests that humans’ merely natural needs
for food, rest, and sex are sufficiently limited that they do not require
much development of human capacities. But the capacity to develop new
desires, especially in the context of a need to prove oneself superior to
others, requires that one cultivate the full range of human capabilities.
“Thus happens the first true steps from crudity toward culture . . .; thus
all talents come bit by bit to be developed, taste is formed, and even,
through progress in enlightenment, a beginning is made toward [forming
society] into a moral whole” (8:21). At first, this might happen on a purely
individual level, as human beings cultivate speed, strength, and
dexterity, and then increasingly the ability to imagine and reason, along
with the effort to make progress not only in sciences but in the arts. All
of these steps are motivated primarily by “ambition, tyranny, and greed”
(8:21, cf. 6:27), but these motives are sufficient to bring people out of
indolence and into the hard work of becoming more and more perfect
(though not morally perfect) human beings. Through humans’ unsocial
sociability, nature achieves the great goal of bringing to fruition what are
at first mere latent potentials for reasoning, character, scientific
development, and artistic creativity.
The story does not end with individual progress, however, nor with
mere cultivation of individual talents. Kant insists that the ultimate end
of nature for human beings includes not merely human culture, within
which human predispositions are developed, but also a form of society as
a moral whole: “the greatest problem for the human species, to which
nature compels him, is the achievement of a civil society administering
127 right” (8:22).91 Nature not only seeks to bring about individual cultivation
of predispositions and the culture that follows from and facilitates that
development; it also aims to bring about just relations among humans, a
“society in which freedom under external laws can be encountered . . ., a
perfectly just civil constitution” (8:22). This “civil constitution” has two
fundamental aspects. First, it involves unions of people under
“republican” forms of government.92 Second, it involves governments at
peace with each other. True right cannot be established until all nations
together affirm the principles of right, and this depends upon perpetual
peace amongst nations. Human history, then, tends towards a condition
within which all human societies will be organized under just, republican
forms of government united into a “pacific league” of nations, a
“federative union” that can “secure a condition of freedom of states
conformably with the idea of the right of nations” (8:356).
Within his moral philosophy, Kant argues that just government
and peace among nations are morally required ends for human beings.
Given the need for freedom to express itself outwardly, we must establish
conditions within which our outward expressions do not wrong others.
This moral requirement gives Kant a moral reason to believe that history
can progress toward such a state:
I shall . . . be allowed to assume that, since the human race is
constantly advancing with respect to culture . . ., it is also to be
conceived as progressing toward what is better with respect to the
moral end of its existence . . . I do not need to prove this
presupposition; it is up to its adversary to prove his case. For I rest
my case on my innate duty . . . so to influence posterity that it
becomes always better. (8:309)
Given the obligation to promote justice in human relations, one is
entitled to believe that progress towards this condition is possible. But
Kant’s philosophy of history also emphasizes empirical evidence that the
moral interest in political right is a real force in human affairs. For
example, in the response of spectators to the French Revolution,
91
The relationship between culture and a just political society shifts through Kant’s works. In the Critique
of Judgment, a just civil society is part of the ultimate end of nature only as “the formal condition under
which nature can achieve . . . the greatest development of the natural predispositions” (5:432). In the “Idea”
and Perpetual Peace, a just civil society seems to be an ultimate goal of nature for human beings in
addition to (and not merely instrumentally towards) the development of human culture.
92
For Kant, a “republican” form of government is one that works on behalf of the people as a whole in
accordance with principles of justice. Such governments can have different structures (monarchic,
aristocratic, or democratic).
128 the mode of thinking of the spectators . . . manifests such a universal
yet disinterested sympathy for the players on one side against those
on the other, even at the risk that this partiality could become very
disadvantageous for them if discovered. Owing to its universality, this
mode of thinking demontrates a character of the human race at large
and all at once; owing to its distinterestedness, a moral character of
humanity, at least in its predisposition, a character which . . .
permits people to hope for progress towards the better. (SF 7:85).
Kant does not argue that the motives of the revolutionaries themselves
can be known to be good. But the universality of moral sympathy for
those revolutionaries, even without any apparent cause for personal gain,
provides empirical evidence of a universal moral interest (even if it does
not provide evidence that this interest in fact governs most human
actions). And this provides a basis for hope that human beings are still
capable of genuine moral improvement.
But Kant’s primary basis for hope in political progress towards
more just civil society is not based on personal duty nor even on the
hope that humans’ moral interest in justice will outweigh their
selfishness. Instead, as in the case of the development of human culture,
Kant argues that humans’ unsocial sociability provides grounds for
progress towards more and more just institutions.
The problem of establishing a [just] state, no matter how hard it may
sound, is soluble even for a nation of devils (if only they have
understanding), and goes like this: Given a multitude of rational
beings all of whom need universal laws for their preservation but
each of whom is inclined covertly to exempt himself from them, so to
order this multitude and establish their constitution that, although
in their private dispositions they strive against one another, these yet
so check on another that in their public conduct the result is the
same as if they had no such evil dispositions . . . [W]hat the task
requires one to know is how [the mechanism of nature] can be put to
use in human beings in order to arrange the conflict of their
unpeaceable dispositions within a people so that they themselves
have to constrain one another to submit to coercive law and so bring
about a condition of peace in which laws have force. (8:366)
In Leviathan (1660), Thomas Hobbes had shown how the unsociability of
human beings – their “greed, diffidence, and pride” – gives rise to human
lives that are “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short,” and Hobbes
argued that this state of affairs leads humans to subordinate themselves
to lawgivers in order to maintain the order necessary for survival.
129 Following this suggestion, Kant argues that even without any moral
interests, conflicts among humans will lead them to find laws to which
they can subordinate themselves and others in order to achieve the
peace and stability necessary for the satisfaction of their desires. Kant
further argues, “even if a people were not forced by internal discord to
submit to the constraint of public laws, war would still force them from
without to do so” (8:365). All that is necessary is some people willing to
assert their value over others by force in order to bring all into
communities united under common laws. Moreover, war pushes human
societies more and more towards republican forms of government (“Idea,”
8:26; PP 8:365-6), and the trials of war (combined with the “spirit of
commerce”) drive nations increasingly towards “honorable peace.” As
governments become more republican, the people who bear the costs of
war increasingly control whether the nation goes to war and thus
increasingly seek peace with other nations. And as the benefits of
international commerce grow, they outweigh the benefits of war, such
that nations seek a peace within which economic exchange can enrich
all. Kant concludes by drawing together his empirical argument for
political progress with the moral argument in such a way that the
burden of the empirical argument is considerably alleviated: “In this way
nature guarantees perpetual peace through the mechanism of human
inclinations itself, with an assurance that is admittedly not adequate for
predicting its future (theoretically), but that is still enough for practical
purposes and makes it a duty to work toward this (not merely chimerical)
end” (8:368).93
Finally, Kant insists that political progress be supplemented by
“ethical community.”
The dominion of the good principle is not otherwise attainable . . .
than through the setting up and the diffusion of a society in
accordance with, and for the sake of, laws of virtue . . . Just as the
juridical state of nature is a state of war of every human being
against every other, so too is the ethical state of nature one in which
the good principle, which resides in every human being, is
incessantly attacked by the evil which is found in him and in every
93
While significant, neither cultural nor political progress exhaust Kant’s account of human beings as an
historically-progressing species. Kant emphasizes, for example, the importance of pedagogical and
educational progress towards “enlightenment,” “humans’ emergence from their self-incurred immaturity”
(8:35), a progress facilitated by political rights – especially freedom of speech (8:37f.) – and also by the
emergence and development of better educational institutions (2:445-452; 9:444, 448-51). Kant was, in
fact, such an avid supporter of emerging new educational movements that took the striking step of
collecting contributions for this project, making himself available for 3 hours a day during the period in
which he was most intensely working on the Critique of Pure Reason (see 2:452)!
130 other as well . . . [This] ethical state of nature is a public feuding
between the principles of virtue and a state of inner immorality that
the natural human being ought to endeavour to leave behind as soon
as possible. (R 6:94, 97)
Leaving this ethical state of nature behind requires the establishment of
an ethical community, just as leaving behind the juridical state of nature
requires a political community. But while political community is
established by “external legal constraint,” ethical community depends
upon mutual encouragement towards virtue; the only “constraint”
applicable here is through a supposed divine lawgiver “who knows the . .
. most intimate parts of the dispositions of each and everyone and . . .
give[s] to each according to the worth of his action” (6:99). Even with God
as “moral ruler of the world,” Kant insists that an ethical community
have “purity: union under no other incentives than moral ones (cleansed
of . . . superstition . . .)” (6:102). God provides no additional incentive to
good actions, but merely a unified “supreme lawgiver” under whose
authority members of an ethical community unite as a single “people”
(6:99). As in the case of political and cultural progress, Kant suggests
that progress towards this community depends upon the cooperation of
nature (6:100-101) but Kant insists particularly strongly that “each must
. . . conduct himself as if everything depended upon him. Only on this
condition may he hope that a higher wisdom will provide the fulfillment
of his well-intentioned effort” (6:101). Whereas political and even cultural
progress happens through unsocial sociability, progress towards ethical
community occurs only in conjunction with properly motivated
cooperation.
For Kant, human beings are historical. Humans progressively
develop innate talents and predispositions, contributing towards a
culture within which arts and sciences flourish. We progress towards
more just political structures, both within and among states.94
Educational progress contributes to bringing about enlightenment, a
state in which humans think for themselves. And ethical community
contributes to moral development. Precisely how far this moral
development goes is unclear. Given his transcendental anthropology of
desire, according to which each human being is free and responsible for
her own moral status, Kant seems committed to the view that
fundamental moral character is an individual affair. In some of Kant’s
works on human history, he emphasizes that historical progress is “not .
94
Kant insists throughout his works that humans’ historical progress is not progress towards happiness:
“only culture can be the ultimate end that one has cause to ascribe to nature in regard to the human species
(not its own earthly happiness . . .)” (5:431, see too 8:20).
131 . . an ever increasing quantity of morality in its attitudes [but only] . . .
an increasing number of actions governed by duty, whatever the
particular motive behind these actions may be, . . . i.e. . . . the external
phenomena of man’s moral nature” (CF, 7:91). Elsewhere, though, Kant
suggests that historical progress does have an effect on human beings at
their deepest moral level. Ethical community seems oriented towards
making human beings morally good, and Kant suggests that “since the
human race is continually progressing in cultural matters (in keeping
with its natural purpose), it is also engaged in progressive improvement
in relation to the moral end of its existence” (TP, 8:308-309).95
One way to think about moral progress in history is in terms of the
problem of radical evil. In the context of the Critique of Judgment’s aim
of bridging the gap between nature and freedom, Kant’s reference to
morally good wills as the final end of nature cannot refer simply to a
noumenal will-in-itself, but must also refer to the appearance of that will
in the world. The final end of nature is good human wills actually
expressed in concrete human lives. And perfection of human capabilities
is an important part of good wills expressing themselves. Progress in arts
and sciences makes it possible for humans who aim for the happiness of
others to more effectively promote that happiness, and the good will that
seeks its own perfection requires a cultural context within which the
resources for that pursuit are available. Moreover, given the necessity of
external freedom for the full expression of one’s choices, political rights
are needed for good wills to fully express themselves in the world.
But radical evil poses three deeper problems for the concrete
expression of goodness in human lives. Because human beings “started
from evil” (6:72), the final end of nature cannot be perfect human wills
but only wills that unendingly progress towards goodness. And given that
radical evil involves an ongoing propensity to evil facilitated through selfdeception, even this ongoing progress involves struggle against selfwrought evil tendencies. Finally, since human evil is both fundamental
and rooted in the human species, it is not clear how one could ever begin
to progress beyond one’s fundamental commitment to prefer happiness
to morality.
95
A similar tension arises in Kant’s Critique of Judgment, where he carefully distinguishes the “final end”
of nature in human beings – the good will that is the only unconditional end – from the “ultimately end” of
nature in human beings – the political and cultural progress that can be an object of empirical study (see
5:434-6), but then connects the ultimate and final purposes of nature, saying that “the ultimate end [is] that
which nature is capable of doing in order to prepare him for what he must himself do in order to be a final
end” (5:431).
132 Kant’s account of historical progress can address at least the first
two issues, and may be able to address the third. We saw in chapter one
that Kant postulates immortality as a condition of the possibility of fully
satisfying the moral law, but Kant’s philosophy of history provides a
naturalistic, secular way of understanding immortality. A human life can
be considered a good life as a whole insofar as it not only gradually
improves in its own individual pursuit of virtue but also works towards
an unending progress in the expression of morally good deeds through
reforming the society of which it is a part. The historicity of human
nature makes it possible for one’s own struggle against evil to be part of
an enduring struggle of humanity as a species. In particular, and this
aligns the first issue with the second, part of one’s struggle against
radical evil involves enacting social conditions that work to strengthen
virtue rather than one’s evil propensities. The nature of self-deception is
such that one seeks both to excuse misdeeds on the grounds of
incapacity or comparison with others and to ignore the moral law itself.
Progress in culture, for Kant, involves as a central component the
“culture of discipline,” that “consists in the liberation of the will from the
despotism of desires” (5:432). This progress directly combats the frailty of
will by virtue of which one lets one’s good intentions be overwhelmed by
inclinations. And the “ethical community” is a community of people
constantly reminding one another of their moral obligations, holding one
another accountable in ways that, without being judgmental, makes it
increasingly difficult to ignore the demands of morality in self-deceptive
ways. In the context of human beings as initially radically evil but
potentially in revolution against that evil, even not-strictly-moral cultural
and political progress can profoundly affect the extent to which one’s
revolution expresses itself in concrete improvements. Those whose
fundamental moral disposition is one of struggle against evil might, in
early phases of human history, be largely dominated by evil tendencies
and show only the slightest glimmers of success in the struggle against
it, while those at later stages of historical progress, being increasingly
armed against the evil principle through social structures that facilitate
morality, will express their good wills more and more fully in their
concrete, embodied lives.
These sorts of moral progress in history still leave open the
question of whether historical progress can go all the way down, actually
enabling or facilitating the revolution in fundamental maxims. And here
one might take a clue from Kant’s discussion of supernatural influence.
Just as “the concept of a divine concursus is quite appropriate and even
necessary” “so that we should never slacken in our striving towards the
good” (8:362), but we should not use appeals to divine cooperation to
133 excuse moral complacency; so we might appeal to moral progress in
history as encouragement that our struggle against evil will bear real
fruit, but must appeal to this progress only in such a way that it
prevents rather than justifies complacency. Kant’s philosophy of history
can thereby provide empirical support for the moral hope that is justified
religiously by appeal to God’s grace and our immortality.96
III. Conclusion
In chapter one, we saw how Kant’s transcendental anthropologies
of volition and feeling contribute to answering the question “What may I
hope?” through the postulates of God and immortality and through the
recognition of human beings as ultimate and final end of nature. But
when Kant introduced his questions, he associated “What may I hope?”
with religion and claimed that Religion within the Boundaries of Mere
Reason is where he tried to answer that question (11:429). While Kant’s
transcendental anthropology provides an overall framework within which
hope can be justified, it is only in his religion and history that this
framework is given an empirical content. While the empirical
anthropology laid out in the last chapter primarily fills in the empirical
account of human beings for which Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason paved
the way, the empirical studies of human evil and history are needed to
complete his transcendental philosophy as a whole by providing
assurance that the empirical world is conformable to the moral demands
of freedom for radically evil beings like us.
96
For further discussion of the possibility of moral progress in history, see Anderson-Gold 2001, Cohen
2010, Frierson 2003, Kleingeld 1995, Louden 2000, Wood 1999, and Yovel 1980.
134 CHAPTER 4: KANT ON HUMAN DIVERSITY
Much of Kant’s anthropology emphasizes universality and
uniformity. His transcendental anthropology implies that there are proper
ways of cognizing, acting in, and even feeling about the world that are
universally applicable to all people. Even Kant’s empirical anthropology
describes general properties of human nature; while Kant recognizes that
“circumstances of place and time . . . produce habits which, as is said,
are second nature,” he insists that anthropology should aim to overcome
this “difficulty” in order to “rise to the rank of a formal science” (7:121).
And Kant’s claim that “the human being is evil by nature” is supposed to
be based on “anthropological research that . . . justif[ies] us in
attributing . . . [evil] to human beings” in such a way that “there is no
cause for exempting anyone from it” (6:25).
Throughout his life, however, Kant was also preoccupied with
human differences. Kant lectured more on “physical geography” than any
other subject, and especially during its early years, this course included
substantial attention to cataloging differences between different types of
human beings. He describes the content of this course in 1765, saying
“The comparison of human beings with each other, and the comparison
of the human being today with the moral state of the human being in
earlier times, furnishes us with a comprehensive map of the human
species” (2:312-3). Moreover, from the start of his anthropology course in
1772, Kant included discussion of differences between human beings
based on variations in temperament, nationality/ethnicity, and sex. In
his published Anthropology, Kant emphasizes “an advantage for the
reading public” in offering “headings under which this or that observed
human quality . . . can be subsumed” and thus offering “readers many
occasions and invitations to make each particular into a theme of its
own, so as to place it in the appropriate category” (7:121-2). Among these
“headings” one find classifications of different sorts of talents and
inclinations, mental illnesses, temperaments, and ethnic and gender
differences. Thus even while unifying human diversity under universal
135 normative and descriptive headings, Kant also distinguishes between
human beings, which helps make his anthropology both more “popular”
(7:122) and more practically relevant. Given his aim, in his anthropology
and physical geography, of “making good [the] lack of experience” of his
pupils, one might helpfully compare many of Kant accounts of human
diversity to popular contemporary ways of making people more adept at
dealing with one another through the use of personality profiles such as
the Myers-Briggs test, popular books on gender differences, or programs
fostering intercultural awareness.
This chapter focuses on Kant’s account of human variation. I start
with a brief treatment of Kant’s accounts of individual differences,
including ordinary variations between people in terms of talents,
inclinations, and natural aptitudes as well as those extraordinary
variations that Kant classifies as mental disorders. I then turn to human
temperaments, the four basic affective-volitional structures into which
every human being can be classified. Finally, I turn to two of the most
controversial aspects of Kant’s account of human beings, his discussions
of sexual and racial/ethnic difference. Most readers of Kant (rightly) see
him as deeply misogynistic, though precisely in what way he is
misogynistic is complicated and controversial. Likewise, Kant’s
comments on other races – especially Black Africans – are shameful, but
precisely how these comments relate to his more systematic concerns –
including his systematic race theory – is far from straightforward.
I. Individual Variations
Within Kant’s empirical anthropology, human beings are unique in
their particular configurations of predispositions and powers. Chapter
two noted that human beings have universal, natural predispositions
that govern cognition, feeling, and desire, but the precise way in which
these predispositions unfold is not universal. Many differences between
individuals are ascribable to environmental differences, such as why one
person plays cricket while another plays baseball or why individuals have
different beliefs and tastes. But other differences are, to varying degrees,
innate.
The most extreme individual differences are found in Kant’s
accounts of mental disorders.97 For Kant, mental disorders affect each of
the three fundamental human psychological faculties: cognition, feeling,
and desire. Because cognition is sub-divided into different powers
97
For detailed discussion, see Frierson 2009a and 2009b and Shell 1996:368-305.
136 (imagination, judgment, etc.), Kant distinguishes cognitive disorders
according to power is affected and how. For example, dementia
(Wahnsinn) is “deranged” imagination, while craziness (Aberwitz) is
deranged reason. Kant distinguishes between mere deficiencies and
positive forms of derangement, such that, for instance, stupidity is a
deficiency of judgment whereby one simply lacks the ability to figure out
whether a particular case falls under a general rule, while insanity
(Wahnwitz) is a derangement of judgment whereby one groups together
disparate particulars under false universals. Deficiencies involve lacking
a particular power or having a power that is so weak as to be largely
inactive. Derangement takes place when a cognitive power is governed by
laws different from those of other human beings. Whereas judgment
normally groups particulars under universals in accordance with certain
real similarities, one who is insane connects particulars in ways without
comprehensible bases. (Kant suggests that those with deranged
judgment can often be entertaining poets, precisely because they link
together particulars in bizarre but quasi-systematic ways.) Further, Kant
adds melancholia and hypochondria as cognitive disorders distinct from
those that fall under more general groupings. Regarding feeling and
desire, Kant treats all disorders of feeling under the general name of
“affects” and disorders of desire under the general name of “passions.”
Both are states wherein a particular feeling or desire overpowers the
reflection needed to compare that feeling or desire with others, so a
single feeling or desire motivates action without (sufficient) reflection.
Finally, Kant describes origins of mental disorders and ways of treating
them. Madness is ascribed to a biologically-inherited “germ” that sets on
at a particular time and takes on its particular character due to
circumstances present when it sets on (7:217). Hypochondria results
from a “natural predisposition” (7:104) that has the form of a propensity
and can be resisted through “intentional abstraction, [which] may
weaken the feeling[s on which the hypochondriac dwells], and if the
abstraction becomes habitual, make it stay away completely” (7: 212).
While interested in “bringing a systematic division” into mental
disorder, Kant also classifies differences between ordinary, mentallyhealthy human beings. Such people have the same mental powers that
operate by the same general rules, but there is still room for difference in
the details of their operation and the relative weight of different
influences on thought and action. Kant classifies these human
differences into two general categories, those that “indicate what can be
made of the human being” and those that “indicate what he is prepared
to make of himself” (7:285). The former can be further sub-divided into
137 talents, natural aptitudes, and temperament.98 The latter is identified by
Kant with “character purely and simply” (7:285) and has been discussed
in chapter two. While character is an important source of human
differences, the biological basis of these differences is the universal
propensity to character; what determines whether and how this
propensity manifests itself in particular human beings is largely99 a
matter of non-biological influences on one’s life, including “what one . . .
make[s] of oneself.” By contrast, talents, natural aptitudes, and
temperaments are variations in natural predispositions, or at least
variations “founded upon . . . [different] natural predisposition[s]” (7:286,
see too 7:220). None are distinct mental powers in themselves; rather,
they describe the degree to which various natural powers are capable of
being exercised or improved. Talents refer to “excellence[s] of the
cognitive faculty” (7:220), natural aptitude “has more to do . . . with
feeling” (7:286),100 and temperament “has . . . to do . . . with the faculty
of desire” (7:286). Moreover, all of these natural variations “must . . . be
distinguished from . . . habitual disposition (incurred through habit)
because a habitual disposition is not founded upon any natural
predisposition but on mere occasional causes” (7:286). Beyond humans’
shared mental powers and the differences acquired through different
lives and experiences, there are also innate differences in the degrees to
which and ways in which mental powers can be exercised.
Talents, for Kant, always indicate an especially effective use of
one’s cognitive faculties. The talents Kant emphasizes in his
Anthropology are “wit . . ., sagacity, and originality of thought (genius)”
98
Kant’s lectures on anthropology show significant shifts in his conceptions of talents, natural aptitudes,
and temperament from his first interest in these topics (at least as early as 1764 in his Observations)
through the published Anthropology. With the exception of my discussion of his shift from preferring the
melancholic temperament to preferring the phlegmatic, I gloss over those changes here, focusing on
Anthropology.
99
There are important biological factors – such as temperament, sex, and race – that can have an influence
on how one’s character develops.
100
Kant’s discussions of natural aptitudes (Naturell) are extremely abbreviated, not only in his
Anthropology but throughout his corpus and even his anthropology lectures, and while Kant often
distinguishes natural aptitudes from talents and temperaments, he does not consistently do so, nor does he
always do so in the same way. Often, Kant refers to natural aptitudes as “powers of mind” (Gemütskräfte,
see e.g. 25:556), but in the Anthropology, this is narrowed to refer specifically to those natural tendencies
that have “to do with the feeling of pleasure or displeasure, as to how one human being is affected by
another (and in this natural aptitude can have something characteristic)” (7:286). With respect to both
talents and natural aptitudes, Kant’s emphasis is on the range of purely individual variation that is possible
when it comes to the degree to which and the ways in which our natural cognitive and affective powers can
be exercised.
138 (7:220). The first is an excellence of understanding, whereby one can
“assimilate heterogeneous representations that . . . lie far apart from
each other” (7:220) in a way that is entertaining and agreeable. Sagacity
is a “natural gift for judging in advance,” whereby one’s reflective
judgment is effective in “knowing how to search well” and “discover[ing]
things” (7:223). And genius is a talent “of imagination” (7:224) whereby
one can “invent” things. Within Kant’s anthropology, talents serve to
distinguish different sorts of people, and knowing what talents someone
has (or lacks) is essential to knowing how properly to educate them
(since talents themselves cannot be taught, but only cultivated). In
addition to helping distinguish between people for purely anthropological
purposes, however, Kant’s conception of talents plays important roles in
his moral philosophy and aesthetics. Within moral philosophy, Kant
argues that human beings have a special obligation to cultivate their
talents. Readers who focus exclusively on Kant’s moral writings might
read this to refer to a general obligation on the part of human beings to
improve themselves, when Kant’s argument is more specific and crucially
grants dignity (and even providential arrangement) to human diversity.
Because human beings have different talents, they require different sorts
of self-cultivation. These innate, biological-anthropological differences are
also important for aesthetics, where Kant argues that artistic “genius” –
that capacity for “giving the rule to art” and “producing that for which no
rule could be given” – is a “talent” and even a “natural predisposition”
(5:307, cf. 5:317-8). He thereby argues that where other
accomplishments must be ascribed to human beings themselves (8:19),
fine art is the work of Nature itself: “genius is the inborn predisposition .
. . through which nature gives the rule to art” (5:307).
II. Temperament
Amongst the natural variations that constitute “what nature makes
of the human being,” by far the most important is temperament. Whereas
talents and natural aptitudes are highly individual, Kant holds that one
can classify people into precisely four “temperaments.” Like talents and
natural aptitudes, temperaments do not refer to specific additional
powers or faculties, but to systematic ways in which humans’ powers
differ.
Kant’s discussion of the temperaments takes place in the context
of a long tradition of treating human beings as divisible into the four
categories of sanguine, choleric, melancholic, and phlegmatic. These
categories were originally developed within medicine by Hippocrates and
139 Galen, who referred to ways in which bodily “humors” (phlegm, yellow
and black bile, and blood) were mixed in the body. The idea was that
bodily health required perfect balance, and one’s “temperament” was the
particular way in which one’s humors were unbalanced (so, for instance,
too much blood made one sanguine; too much phlegm made one
phlegmatic). By the 18th century, the theory of temperaments had
become an important part of moral psychology, and 18th century
moralists and proto-psychologists used “temperaments” to classify
different moral characters. In line with this tradition, Kant distinguishes
temperaments in terms of the different tendencies of action and
motivation that can come to have moral (and, more generally, pragmatic)
importance.
Kant brackets medical and physiological conceptions of
temperament (see 7:286), while still acknowledging that “temperaments
which we attribute merely to the soul may well also have corporeal
factors in the human being, as covertly contributing causes” (7:286).
Kant divides the four temperaments into sanguine and melancholic
“temperaments of feeling” and choleric and phlegmatic “temperaments of
activity” (7:286-7, 289).101 The sanguine “is carefree and of good cheer”
and lives in the moment (7:288). The melancholic is serious, thoughtful,
and tends towards misanthropy (7:288). The choleric is “hot-tempered . . .
[and] rash [and] his ruling passion is ambition” (7:289). Just as the
sanguine feels quickly and easily but is also quickly distracted, so the
choleric acts quickly but is quickly appeased. As the sanguine is has an
excess of (cheerful) feeling, the choleric has an excess of activity. Finally,
the phlegmatic has “lack of emotion” and “the quality of not being moved
easily” (7:289-90).
Although generally dismissed today, Kant’s discussion of
temperament is important for several reasons. First, it is an important
part of completing Kant’s empirical anthropology. In the absence of some
accounts of temperaments, Kant might rightly be accused of failing to
recognize the important natural (even biological) differences between
human beings. Kant’s doctrine of temperaments, like more contemporary
psychological investigations and classifications of human psychological
variations, provides his universal and historical anthropology with a
necessary supplementary account of human difference. Moreover, as one
important commentator has noted, Kant’s account of human difference
helps flesh out his otherwise simplistic accounts of such things as
101
Although temperament is distinguished from natural aptitude in that it relates to the faculty of desire,
temperaments relate to the faculty of desire either by being directly active or by influencing feeling in a
way that is relevant to activity.
140 “unsocial sociability,” which we can now see “describes a more complex
set of interactions than the mere push and pull of misanthropic egoism
and philanthropy. The several vices which propel history . . . are
arguably attached in Kant’s mind to different kinds of people” (Larrimore
2001: 285). Temperamental differences affect how our inclinations and
even character develop and thus have profound impacts on how we
behave and relate to one another. Moreover, within the emerging
empirical-psychological discussions of the temperaments, Kant’s way of
defending temperaments makes use of (and thus partly helps justify)
other aspects of Kant’s empirical and even transcendental anthropology.
The neat classification of the four temperaments in terms of strength or
weakness of feeling and desire helps vindicate both the legitimacy of
temperament theory in terms of Kant’s innovative distinction between
feeling and desire, and the validity of that distinction in terms of its
ability to account for temperaments. And Kant’s treatment of the
phlegmatic, as we will see shortly, both supports and is supported by
Kant’s work on the nature of moral motivation.
Second, Kant’s account of temperaments is important as part of a
specifically pragmatic anthropology. I discuss pragmatic anthropology in
more detail in the next chapter, but here it is important to note that Kant
does not merely classify different temperaments. He also emphasizes
their characteristics in ways relevant to moral and practical assessments
and deliberations. For example, when Kant claims that the sanguine
person “makes promises in all honesty, but does not keep his word
because he has not reflected deeply enough beforehand” (7:288), his
advice not only provides needed warning to the sanguine about their own
morally pernicious tendencies but also helps others know how to deal
with sanguine companions and even how to properly evaluate the moral
status of the sanguine’s broken promises (as flightiness, not deception).
Similarly, when the melancholic is cautious about making promises
(7:288) and the phlegmatic “proceed[s] from principles” (7:290), Kant’s
ascription of these traits to temperament and not to “moral causes”
(7:288) or “wisdom” (7:290) is an important warning to all concerned not
to mistake mere temperament for genuine moral worth.102
102
In this context, Kant’s note at 15:758-65 on “mistakes” or “failings” (Fehler) associated with different
temperaments is an excellent example of working through the challenges that those with different
temperaments will particularly have to face in living and good and happy life. My reading of Kant here
differs importantly from that recently offered by Mark Larrimore. I disagree with Larrimore’s claims that a
phlegmatic temperament “is a duty” (Larrimore 2001: 284) and that phlegma should be identifies with
apathy. Phlegma is a temperament that is like apathy and that makes it particularly easy to develop true
moral character (which includes apathy), but I take Kant’s repeated claim that phlegma can do what
philosophy or wisdom does without real philosophy or wisdom to be an important warning to the
141 Third, Kant’s discussion of temperaments provides one of the best
examples of how developments in his transcendental anthropology
intersect with those in his empirical (and pragmatic) anthropology. The
dominant traditional view of temperaments portrayed sanguine and
choleric as healthy, phlegmatic and melancholic as inherently unhealthy
(Larrimore 2001: 264). Kant consistently resisted this tradition. In his
early writings, Kant emphasized, alongside a major counter-tradition in
German (especially Pietist) thought, the merits of the melancholic
temperament: “Genuine virtue from principles therefore has something
about it that seems to agree most with the melancholic frame of mind in
a moderate sense” (2:219). At the time that Kant wrote this, his moral
philosophy was largely informed by sentimentalist views that emphasized
depth of feeling as an important part of virtue. But as Kant’s moral
theory moved towards the importance of a purely rational moral principle
and a distinctive moral motive, and as his general empirical anthropology
came to emphasize the importance of “character” in human life, Kant’s
account of the temperaments shifted to privilege the phlegmatic over the
melancholic. In his early writings, Kant followed the traditional view that
the phlegmatic was hardly worth discussing (2:224). But by 1778, Kant
already associated the phlegmatic with “the philosopher” (25:1167) and
had developed an important distinction between what he would later call
“phlegma as weakness,” which is a mere “propensity to inactivity” and
“phlegma as strength,” or “apathy,” which is a “quality of not being
moved easily or rashly” and associated with acting “from principles and
not from instinct” (7:290).
Finally, Kant’s discussion of temperament provides an important
“hinge” (Larrimore 2001:270) between Kant’s general and universal
anthropology and his discussions of differences between human sexes,
nationalities (or ethnic groups), and races. Especially in his early works,
Kant associates different sexes, nationalities, or races with different
temperaments, and he uses claims about the latter to explicate his
claims about the former. Given the offensive nature of Kant’s views about
sex and race, this calls for thinking about what, if anything,
phlegmatic. Whereas a sanguine person who lives life according to principles can and should regard that as
a moral accomplishment, the phlegmatic one should not. Instead, the phlegmatic person should be grateful
to nature or God for that temperament, but work all the harder to ensure that her principled action flows
from a steady moral character and not merely a fortunate temperament. I also see no reason to think that,
for Kant, one can change one’s temperament, though one can certainly learn not to manifest its (negative)
characteristics. Unlike character as such, temperament is, after all, something that “nature makes of the
human being,” not something that “the human being makes of himself.” (This is not to say that one’s
temperament cannot change – Kant associates different temperaments with different ages (see 25:820) –
but only that one’s temperament at a give time is something that arises naturally, not through one’s own
effort or decision.)
142 distinguishes Kant’s practice of subdividing people according to
“temperament” – shared, for example, by those who favor psychological
personality tests as a way of improving interpersonal relationships – and
his practice of subdividing people according to sex and race. Given that
for Kant temperaments are as much a matter of what “nature makes of
the human being” as sex or race, why is one sort of distinction offensive
while the other might seem at worst merely naïve? Or put another way,
given the dangers of distinguishing on the basis of race and sex, might it
not be appropriate to be concerned about any simplistic attempts to
classify different sorts of people?
III. Differences between the Sexes103
Kant’s discussion of temperament marks the start of his attempt to
classify human beings not only in terms of universally-shared
characteristics or individual variations but in terms of generic types of
human. But throughout his anthropological writings, beginning from his
very early Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime
(arguably his first foray into anthropology) and continuing through his
published Anthropology, Kant follows his discussion of human
temperaments with an account of the difference between men and
women, a discussion, that is, of “The Character of the Sexes” (7:303).
Consistently, and in perfect conformity to feminist characterizations of
Western discourse as fundamentally patriarchal, Kant’s discussion of
differences between men and women focuses exclusively on the unique
character of women. Kant takes men to be paradigmatic of human beings
in general, such that a characterization of “the sexes” involves nothing
more than showing how the previous characterization of human beings
in general must be modified for the “special case” of women.
Kant’s Observations, his earliest (1764) and most popular
(including amongst women!) anthropological discussion of the sexes,
includes both perfect sound-bites of Kantian misogyny – “A woman who
has a head full of Greek . . . might as well have a beard” (2:229) and
apparent mantras of egalitarianism – “the fair sex has just as much
understanding as the male” (2:229). The core of Kant’s account of the
sexes in Observations is that women are primarily beautiful, while men
are primarily sublime:
103
Throughout his discussion of differences between men and women, Kant conflates what we would now
call sex-differences and gender-differences. He also assumes heterosexuality throughout his discussions of
relations between sexes.
143 it is not to be understood that woman is lacking noble [sublime]
qualities or that the male sex must entirely forego beauties; rather
one expects that each sex will unite both, but in such a way that in a
woman all other merits should only be united so as to emphasize the
character of the beautiful, which is the proper point of reference,
while by contrast among the male qualities the sublime should
clearly stand out as the criterion of his kind (2:228).
Kant’s distinction is both descriptive – women are generally more
characterized by the beautiful and men by the sublime – and normative:
“To this [distinction] must refer all judgments of these two sexes, those of
praise as well as those of blame” (2:228) such that “what is most
important is that the man become more perfect as a man and the woman
as a woman” (2:242-3).
Unless one keeps both the descriptive and normative dimensions of
Kant’s distinction in mind, Kant’s account might seem to preclude virtue
in women. Kant says both “It is difficult for me to believe that the fair sex
is capable of principles” (2:232, see too 27:49), and “true virtue can only
be grafted upon principles” (2:217). This might require, as Jean Rumsey
claims, that “women . . . are in Kant’s view less than . . . full moral
agents.”104 But such attention to the merely descriptive aspect of Kant’s
distinction misses Kant’s insistence in Observations that women are
capable of virtue, but “The virtue of the woman is a beautiful virtue”
(2:231, see too 27:49-50). Following through on his sexual distinction,
Kant insists that women are capable of distinctively feminine virtue. And
whereas the principles of which women are incapable “are also extremely
rare among the male sex” (2:232), the “love [of] what is good” that serves
as the foundation of beautiful virtue is grounded in “goodly and
benevolent sentiments” that “providence has implanted . . . in [woman’s]
bosom” (2:232). The impossibility of fulfilling male virtue is actually a
moral advantage; whereas few men will attain sublime virtue, women are
well equipped for beautiful virtue.
By the time of Kant’s Anthropology,105 however, Kant’s thought
underwent several changes that affect his discussion of women. Some of
these reflect Kant’s increasing interest in courtship and marriage. So, for
104
Jean Rumsey, “Re-Visions of Agency in Kant’s Moral Theory,” in Feminist Interpretations of Immanuel
Kant (Ed. Robin May Schott), University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997, p. 131.
105
Many of the additions are already reflected in Remarks written in 1764-6 in Kant’s personal copy of his
Observations. The mid 1760’s, when Kant was personally deciding whether or not to marry (he eventually
decided against it) and reading the works of Rousseau (who’s Emile and Julie extensively discuss
differences between the sexes) seem to have been the period in which Kant did the most reflection on the
differences between men and women, and during which he formed most of his views on this matter.
144 example, Kant’s personal notes and lectures in anthropology increasing
emphasize that it is “an essential condition of nature, that woman must
be sought” (25:708), so that “the woman refuses, the man woos; her
surrender is a favor” (7:306). This characterization of “natural” courtship
practices contributes to Kant’s attention to a womanly “art of appearing”
or “art of illusion” (20:61, 69, 121, 140). Since women in fact want (and
need) men as much as men do women, their refusal is a ruse, a way of
attracting men, and this art of illusion continues throughout marriage as
a way to “govern . . . men and use them for their own purposes” (7:304).
The woman “acquires confidence early in her ability to please” (7:306),
especially through presenting charming appearances, and for this
reason, women care much more about appearances than men (25:720).
More important than these details of his account, though, Kant
reconceived of the difference between the sexes in terms of an overall
natural teleology. From his earliest discussions of women, Kant had
referred to their “innate” characteristics (2:229) and insisted that women
not only are but ought to be different from men (2:229-30). But his later
anthropology takes this further. First, Kant clarifies the extent to which
these differences are natural. He recognizes that there are substantial
differences between 18th century European relations between the sexes
and those in what Kant calls “uncivilized conditions.” In such conditions,
Kant argues, one cannot see any major differences between men and
women, except that men are somewhat physically stronger (and more
“courageous”). But, Kant claims, this greater sameness between men and
women is hardly a boon to women, who finds themselves, without
distinctively feminine sources of strength, in conditions of “domestic
animal[s]” (7:304). Consistent with his account of predispositions in
general, Kant sees feminine character traits as propensities that require
the right conditions to flourish: “culture does not introduce these
feminine qualities, it only allows them to develop and become
recognizable under favorable conditions” (7:303). Kant also offers specific
arguments against those who “dispute this [account of sex differences] in
the way one disputes something from the speaker’s lectern [to show that
they are not inherent to] nature and [they] believe it to be a matter of
fashion” (25:709). Kant appeals to “universal and constant” facts about
the sexes, including not only that women bear children while men to not,
but even that for humans as well as “animals . . ., one sees the female is
the refusing, but the male the courting party” (25:709). From such
universal characteristics, Kant argues, the further characteristics of
human females – their abilities to please through illusion, a desire to
dominate men through charm, etc – can be explained.
145 The most important part of Kant’s account of natural differences
between men and women is his treatment of “nature’s end in establishing
womankind” (7:305). There are two main natural purposes for women’s
distinctive characteristics: the preservation of the species [and] the
cultivation and refinement of society (7:305-6).106 Given that “nature
entrusted to woman’s womb its dearest pledge, namely, the species, in
the fetus,” women’s “fear of physical danger” is an important insurance
towards her preservation (7:306). Combining this physical “weakness”
with an ability to “demand male protection” ensures that the fetus (and
thus the species) will be threatened neither by excessive boldness on the
part of the woman nor physical dangers (against which the man will
protect her). The second great end of nature is the cultivation of society:
“nature wanted to instill the finer feelings that belong to culture –
namely, . . . sociability and propriety” (7:306). As we saw in the previous
chapter, the development of culture is the great natural end for human
106
There is a third, more immediate, purpose, but Kant does not discuss this as a purpose of nature. In the
immediate domestic sphere, women’s capacity for illusion and for “mastering [man’s] desire for her”
(7:303) ensures a level of stability and equality within marriage.
Two persons convening at random is insufficient for the unity and indissolubility of a union; one
partner must yield to the other, and, in turn, one must be superior to the other in some way, in order to
be able to rule over or govern him. For in the equality of claims of two people who cannot do without
each other, self-love produces nothing but squabbling. (7:303)
While Kant’s approach to marriage can seem extremely patriarchal (as we will see shortly), this passage
suggests something more complicated. For Kant, a lasting relationship between two people, especially
when sexual, is unsustainable without some sort of hierarchy. But Kant suggests that apparent hierarchies
are not (and should not be) entirely what they seem. Whereas the claim that “one partner must yield” and
another “be superior” might easily be taken to justify male superiority within the marriage union, Kant in
fact uses it to argue for the claim that “each partner must be superior in a different way” (7:303). The man
is superior in obvious ways, through “physical power and courage” and – in society – through formal
political rights. But Kant suggests that the real superiority is in the hands of the woman. Through her
charms, “domestic warfare which she conducts with her tongue,” and carefully used “tears of exasperation”
(7:304), she is able to govern and control the men who, it turns out, only seem to rule over her. Woman’s
art of appearances thus serves the purpose of balancing out men’s greater strength and thereby promoting
equality within marriage (and, more generally, within male-female relationships).
Kant even worries that in his age, women have actually gone beyond equality and exercise
superiority over men. He contrasts the state of polygamy, where men exercise undue control over women,
the civil condition of marital equality, and the state of luxury. In the last, “gallantry has become the fashion
and jealousy ridiculous. . . , [so] the feminine character reveals itself: by extending favors toward men,
woman lays claim to freedom and, at the same time, to the conquest of the entire male sex” (7:304-5). The
new polygamy of the “modern” (18th century) age, Kant suggests, is one within which “the time of the
debaucheries of men has ended and that of women has begun” (20:86).
146 beings as a species. There Kant emphasized unsocial sociability as the
driving force behind this development. Here he highlights that unsocial
sociability has a gendered structure. Men and women are attracted into
society with one another but manifest their superiority in different ways.
In particular, women’s power over men depends upon increasingly polite
and refined social interactions; her direct power is exercised through
“modesty and eloquence in speech and expression” (7:306). In order to
gain equality, women become adept at social interaction. But as women
become more capable of coaxing men, they “claim . . . gentle and
courteous treatment by the male,” who finds himself “fettered . . .
through his own magnanimity, and led by her, if not to morality itself, to
that which is its cloak, moral decency” (7:306, see too 2:241). The
apparent weakness and timidity of women ends up becoming one of the
driving forces behind cultural and even proto-moral progress in the
human species.
Unfortunately, Kant’s increased interest in women as a driving
force behind progress in history, even to the point of helping develop a
moral decency “which is the preparation for morality” (7:306), was
accompanied by profound changes in his overall moral theory, changes
that effectively precluded women from being capable of virtue. Whereas
the Kantian ethics of Observations emphasizes the importance of
“beautiful” or “adopted” virtues even for men and devotes significant
attention to spelling out the details of “the virtue of women” (2:231),
Kant’s mature moral theory not only does not include, but even seems to
preclude, anything that could genuinely be called feminine virtue. Kant’s
shift from an empirical and sentimentalist moral theory in the 1760s that
allowed different sorts of moral worth based on different aesthetic
feelings to a more rigorous rationalist morals in his Groundwork and
later works that emphasizes a “good will” as the only thing “good without
limitation” (4:393) precludes taking seriously as “virtue” anything that
does not involve acting out of respect for a pure moral law. Thus when he
refers to “feminine virtue” (7:307) in his Anthropology, the claim seems to
be a mere remnant of an earlier view, a remnant that no longer makes
sense in the context of Kant’s mature moral theory.
At the same time, unfortunately, Kant’s anthropological
characterization of women as incapable of male virtue (which becomes
the only real virtue) is unchanged. The early claim that “It is difficult for
me to believe that the fair sex is capable of principles” (2:232)107
blossoms into a more technical (and more problematic) claim that certain
107
Kant immediately adds, “and I hope not to give offense by this,” in keeping with the gallant tone of
Observations.
147 “feminine principle[s are] hard to unite with a character in the narrow
sense of the term.”108 This “narrow sense” of character is the capacity to
act on consistent principles of one’s own, a capacity that not only “has
an inner worth” of its own (7:293) but is also a necessary condition of a
good will (which makes the moral law its principle).109 Given that
woman’s distinctive art is an art of appearing, it is perhaps unsurprising
that character, which depends upon “not dissembling” (7:294), is
unavailable to them. And given that women naturally focus on “pleasing
others” (7:305), it is unsurprising that the self-governance required by
the moral law is particularly out of character. Perhaps most striking is
the subtle shift in terminology in Kant’s description of married life. In
Observations, Kant suggests that “In marital life the united pair should
[be] . . . animated and ruled by the understanding of the man and the
taste of the wife” (2:242).110 In the context of an ethic that defines virtue
as “the feeling of the beauty and dignity of human nature” (2:217), the
cooperation of taste and judgment seems perfectly poised to constitute
the “single moral person” (2:242) that Kant things a good marriage
should involve; the woman’s taste can heighten the man’s feeling for
human beauty, and the man’s understanding can heighten her feeling for
human dignity. But in Anthropology, written almost 35 years later, Kant
makes essentially the same point about mutual governance within
marriage, but in terms with a strikingly different moral resonance: “Who,
then, should have supreme command in the household? . . . .the woman
should dominate and the man should govern, for inclination dominates
and understanding governs” (7:309). Not only has an emphasis on unity
hardened into a description of mutual command, but more importantly,
the woman’s role is no longer that of “taste” but that of “inclination.”
While taste is part of virtue in Kant’s early ethics and a human
characteristic that Kant continues to value throughout his life,
“inclinations” in Kant’s mature moral philosophy lead one morally astray:
“they are always burdensome to a rational being, and though he cannot
lay them aside, they wrest from him the wish to be rid of them”
(5:118).111 Not only does Kant’s mature moral philosophy make it
108
Pauline Kleingeld, in Kleingeld 1993, has pointed out that Kant denies that women have “courage”
(7:303), which Kant claims is essential for virtue. This consideration seems less important to me than his
points about character. I see no evidence that the courage that men have and women lack is the same
courage needed for moral worth. Kant links “courage” with “physical power” and seems to have in mind
pragmatic boldness.
109
See Rumsey 1989 and Frierson 2006.
110
Kant adds, in striking contrast to Anthropology, that “In such a relationship a struggle for precedence is
ridiculous” (2:242).
111
To be fair, by the time that Kant wrote Anthropology, he had written his Religion, within which
inclinations are subsumed under one or another predispositions to good. But Kant’s association of women
with inclination dates back to his anthropology lectures of the 1770s and 1780s (see e.g. 25:718).
148 impossible for women to have a good will, but Kant even shifts in
describing their non-moral advantages from the positively-connoting
“taste” to the negatively-suggestive “inclination.”
In view of his apparent indifference to treating women as incapable
of moral worth, it is perhaps unsurprising that when Kant turns to the
details of his moral and especially political theory, he does not accord
women rights equal to those of men. Within his political theory, women
show up in two important contexts: citizenship and marriage. With
respect to citizenship, Kant defines citizens as “the members of a society
who are united for giving law” and insists on three essential
attributes of a citizen . . .: [1] lawful freedom, the attribute of obeying
no other law than that to which he gives his consent; [2] civil
equality, that of not recognizing among the people any superior with
the moral capacity to bind him as a matter of right in a way that he
could not in turn bind the other; and, [3] the attribute of civil
independence, of owing his existence and preservation to his own
rights and powers . . . (6:314)
Kant puts “all women” into the category of “passive citizens” or “mere
associates” of the state, people who are not “fit to vote” but nonetheless
have “freedom and equality as human beings” (6:314-5, cf. 8:295). And
whereas Kant states as a general rule that the laws of a society must be
such that “anyone can work his way of from this passive condition to an
active [citizenship]” (6:315), his insistence that all women are passive
implies that he excludes them from this condition. For Kant, women
cannot vote and must remain forever dependent upon their husbands for
representation in the public realm.
In Anthropology, Kant adds two important nuances to this account.
First, he makes clear that while “woman regardless of age is declared to
be immature in civil matters,” this is a specifically civil declaration; in
fact, a wife is, if anything, “over-mature” in her ability to “represent both
herself and her husband.” But “just as it does not belong to women to go
to war, so women cannot personally defend their rights and pursue civil
affairs by themselves.” Second, Kant suggests that women do in fact
defend their rights and pursue civil affairs indirectly, since “this legal
immaturity with respect to public transactions makes women all the
more powerful in respect to domestic welfare; because here the right of
the weaker enters in, which the male sex by its nature already feels
called on to respect and defend” (7:209). Kant’s view seems to be that
women are excluded from public politics not because of a genuine
incapacity, but in order to empower them at home, where they can
149 control their husbands and thereby ensure that husbands take care of
the family’s public affairs.
Kant’s political philosophy discusses marital rights in the general
context of property rights, in a section illuminatingly entitled “on rights
to persons akin to rights to things” (6:277). There are three ways to
acquire “a person akin to a thing,” when “a man acquires a wife; a couple
acquires children; and a family acquires servants” (6:227). Of these three,
Kant insists that both children and servants are acquired only for a
specified period of time, after which they must be granted complete
freedom from their parents/masters (6:281, 283). Only women are
capable of being “acquired” for life.
To be fair, Kant’s account of the husband’s ownership right over
the wife is carefully described not as a right to a person as a thing, which
would blatantly contradict the obligation to respect all others as an end
and not a mere means, but only as a right akin to rights to things. In
fact, Kant’s discussion of the marriage right is one of the clearest places
where he articulated the view that women, despite whatever limitations
they may have anthropologically, are nonetheless ends in themselves
who have a “duty . . . to the humanity in [their] own person[s]” (6:280). It
even follows from this, for Kant, that marriage rights – unlike rights over
children and servants – must include entire reciprocity and “equality of
possession” (6:278), such that just as the husband entirely owns the
wife, so the wife in turn entirely owns the husband.
There is only one condition under which [it] is possible [to make
oneself into a thing without compromising one’s own humanity]: that
while one person is acquired by the other . . ., the one who is
acquired acquires the other in turn; for in this way each reclaims
itself and restores its personality. (6:278).
Thereby Kant rules out polygamy, concubinage, prostitution, and
“morganatic marriage” (whereby the husband withholds property or titles
from the wife); and he even insists upon “equality in their possession of
material goods” (6:278). Consistent with accounts of differences between
sexes in Anthropology and elsewhere, Kant does not think that husband
and wife play identical roles within marriage. In the Metaphysics of
Morals, where legal rights are at stake, Kant insists that the husband “is
to be [the wife’s] master,” which “cannot be regarded as conflicting with
the natural equality of the couple if this dominance is based only on the
natural superiority of the husband to his wife in his capacity to promote
the common interest of the household” (6:279, see too 7:304). Consistent
with his view that women hold power primarily through charming
150 manipulation of their husbands, Kant insists that the law recognize the
husband as head of household, while the wife – through her relational
adeptness – “dominates” the husband through his own will.
In the end, Kant’s account of the difference between the sexes is
disturbing. Most blatantly, Kant was on the “wrong side” of the most
important issues of the day, such as women’s education and citizenship.
And while he “gallantly”112 praises women’s distinctive charms, his
overall account sees them primarily as means to the civil and moral
development of men. Even Kant’s explicit endorsements of women’s
equality (or superiority) fit within an overall attempt to defend and
entrench patriarchal political structures. Saying that women have soft
power that flourishes in contexts where they lack explicit and formal
power is an excellent way to justify denying them political equality. And
drawing attention to women’s ability to control men through charm is a
good way of discounting the role of rational argument and dialogue at the
level of intellectual equals. This discounting can have profound effects
not only within marriages – where husbands will expect wives to be
charming rather than wise – but also in the education of girls, which
education would, for Kant, properly emphasize learning social graces
rather than intellectual pursuits (including not only abstract
metaphysics but also disciplines that involve more obvious uses of
power, like physics, engineering, and politics).113
Simply accepting Kant’s views about women is unacceptable not
only because they conflict with contemporary assumptions, but also
because they conflict with Kant’s own transcendental anthropology.114
Through all the particular anti-feminist and misogynistic claims in
Kant’s eventual account of women’s nature, it is the inability for women
in their own right to have the unconditional worth of a good will that is
the most morally and philosophically problematic. Moral responsibility,
worthiness to be considered an end-in-oneself, and the capacity for a
good will are inextricably connected in Kant’s transcendental
anthropology. Kant explicitly claims that women must be treated as
ends-in-themselves (6:278, 280). And there is no evidence that he denies
them moral responsibility. So Kant needs to provide an account of how
112
A term that Kant constantly uses to describe his own accounts of women. See, e.g., 7:310.
One odd and striking feature of many of Kant’s descriptions of women’s education is the extent to
which his accounts of the proper topics of learning for women match almost exactly his account of his own
goals for pragmatic anthropology. In the actual practice of seeking to understand human beings
pragmatically, Kant embodies his own highest ideals of womanly philosophy.
114
The rest of this discussion in this section focus on this general problem for his views. For some specific
treatments of his accounts of women and marriage or women’s citizenship, see Denis 2007, Mendus 1992,
and Shell 1996.
113
151 women can be capable of moral worth. And doing this will require
substantial revisions in his anthropology.
*
*
*
Today, there are two major and opposing responses to Kant’s
characterization of women. The dominant response among those
sympathetic to Kant “is to say that Kant’s views on women are mistaken,
that one should instead concentrate on his more important philosophical
achievements, and that one can simply leave his theory about the sexes
behind” (Kleingeld 1993:140). This response involves rejecting Kant’s
anthropological characterization of women and extending his
descriptions of transcendental and even empirical anthropology to
include women as well as men. Within the context of such an approach,
one would affirm – with Kant – that character and rationality are crucial
to virtue, but add – against Kant – that women are no less capable of
these traits than men. A second response, dominant amongst feminist
critics of thinkers like Kant, is to argue that Kant’s philosophy as a whole
reflects a masculinist bias. Such critics typically agree with Kant’s
general anthropological claim that there are important differences
between men and women, but reject his identification of what is
universal and normative for “human beings” with what is universal and
normative for men. Carol Gilligan, for example, suggests – with Kant –
that for women “morality is conceived in interpersonal terms and
goodness is equated with . . . pleasing others” rather than in an
“understanding of rights and rules” (Gilligan 1982:2).115 Like the Kant of
Observations, however, Gilligan takes the “different voice” women bring
to moral deliberation to be legitimate and needed to balance masculine
emphasis on rule-following and personal autonomy (Gilligan 1982, see
too Noddings 1984). While Gilligan focuses on differences in moral
perspectives, other feminist thinkers have made similar points about
Kant’s transcendental anthropology more generally. His emphasis on
reason and understanding over sensibility has been taken to reflect a
115
Importantly, Gilligan rejects the view that this difference is either universal or essential:
The different voice I describe is characterized not by gender but theme. Its association with women is
an empirical observation . . . But this association is not absolute, and the contrasts between male and
female voices are presented here to highlight a distinction . . . rather than to represent a generalization
about either sex . . . No claims are made about the origins of the differences described or their
distribution in the wider population, across cultures, or through time. Clearly, these differences arise
in a social context where factors of social status and power combine with reproductive biology to
shape the experiences of males and females and the relations between the sexes. (p. 2)
(For a more essentialist account of gender differences that shares many claims in common with both
Gilligan and Kant (though situated in a psychoanalytic framework), see Chodorow 1974.)
152 masculinist bias in epistemology, one that puts “the Enlightenment
conception of a universal, rational subject” above “feminist notions that
the self is embedded in social relations, that the self is embodied, and is
thus historically specific and partial” (Schott 1997:8).
This divided response to Kant’s thought highlights in contemporary
form the problem that arises within Kant’s own anthropology.
Philosophers who find Kant’s transcendental anthropology convincing
have sought to jettison the empirical-anthropological accounts of women
than make them seem ill-suited for fulfilling the requirements of that
transcendental anthropology. But philosophers and empirical
psychologists who study sex and gender often end up supporting, if not
Kant’s specific claims, at least accounts of gender differences that raise
similar philosophical problems for a broadly Kantian account of moral
and epistemic norms. What seemed to be a tension internal to Kant, one
that he lamely resolved by simply settling into misogyny and ignoring the
problems this raised for his transcendental anthropology, appears as a
real problem for anyone who finds plausible both Kant’s arguments for
universal norms governing thought, choice, and feeling and the
importance of empirical sensitivity to human differences in thinking
about how those norms play out in the real human world.116
One important way to deal with the tension – for the present day,
even if not to salvage Kant’s own thinking – would be through more
careful and fine-grained approaches to both transcendental and
empirical anthropology. These might find that women and men are not
different in ways that have moral relevance. Even if, say, morality
requires acting on principles and women tend to be more situational, this
does not necessarily mean that they lack what is necessary for morality.
Morality might also require situational sensitivity,117 and women might
116
Incidentally, this problem is more serious, and less easily resolved, that the problem that Gilligan
emphasizes in her critique of Kohlberg. Gilligan is a psychologist writing in response to Kohlberg’s (and
others’) theories of human development, which used empirical studies of human beings from childhood to
adulthood to develop scales for measuring such things as moral and emotional maturity. In a context where
the basis for the dominant normative claims about what human beings ought to be is largely driven by a
description of how “eighty-four boys . . . develop[ed] . . . over twenty years” (18), Gilligan’s observations
that girls and women develop differently is a serious ground for calling into question the normative claims
themselves. But Kant does not defend his normative claims on the basis of observing the actual
development of human beings. Instead, he defends them from-within, as conditions of the possibility of any
legitimate claims to knowledge or moral responsibility or aesthetic experience. Thus empirical evidence
showing that one sex fails to meet these standards provides no ground for rejecting them.
117
Barbara Herman has recently argued that Kant’s moral theory depends at least as much upon a
situational sensitivity that is highly emotional as it does upon the categorical imperative itself. See Herman
1993.
153 also be capable of morally principled action, even if not in the same way
or to the same degree as men.
Another middle-ground would accept both Kant’s philosophical
defense of norms that seem more masculine than feminine and empirical
evidence of differences between sexes, but reject the teleological
essentialism underlying Kant’s explanation of those differences.118 As
Carol Gilligan emphasizes, “differences arise in a social context where
factors of social status and power combine with reproductive biology to
shape the experiences of males and females and the relations between
the sexes” (Gilligan 1984:2). Kant himself recognizes that the sex
differences he discusses arise only in particular social and political
contexts (7:304) and his discussion of women’s civil inequality (6:314,
7:204) remains at least open to the idea that women’s civil immaturity is
socially-created rather than natural. Differences between men and
women that inhibit women from fully realizing Kantian ideals of
autonomy may be due to unjust social conditions that can and should be
remedied. This approach could give rise to an increased attention to the
social and political reforms that could create a world within which
women would have as good a chance as men at measuring up to
universally human moral (and other) norms. Kant, unfortunately,
rejected this middle-ground in both his anthropology – where he insists
that differences between men and women are natural and not merely
social (e.g. 25:709) – and in his politics – where his explanation of the
passive citizenship of “all women” is combined with both complacency
and an account of marriage that seems to reinforce this civil inequality.
Finally, even if it does turn out that there are essential differences
between men and women and that these differences make it considerably
more difficult for women to attain to a good will, one might still – and
Kant certainly should – insist that it is possible for women to have
unconditional moral worth. Modifying Kant’s claim from Religion,119 we
might say “In spite of [one’s sex], the command that we ought to become
better human beings still resounds unabated in our souls; consequently,
we must also be capable of it” (6:45). In this context, the difference
between men and women would be akin to differences between
temperaments, not a denial of the possibility of virtue for women, but a
detailed attention to the fact that women will face greater and different
118
The recent emphasis on distinguishing “sex” and “gender” obviously fits into this general approach.
Insofar as one’s gender can be distinguished from one’s biological sex, one need not identify biological sex
(male/female) with the characteristics associated with particular genders (masculine/feminine), and one can
largely ascribe gender characteristics to social factors.
119
See chapter three, p. xxx.
154 challenges in their progress towards virtue than men. One might even
recast the differences between the sexes in terms of different
manifestations of radical evil. Whereas men’s radical evil typically
manifests itself in an unsocial sociability rooted in overwhelming love of
honor that gives rise to passions of jealousy and rivalry, women’s radical
evil might more typically manifest itself in a desire to please that
encourages duplicity and sacrificing principle for the sake of relationship.
The claims about women that seem to preclude her from having true
virtue are certainly no more extreme than Kant’s claims about radical
evil in human nature in general; Kant just lacks an account of the
emergence of women from their particular weaknesses. Again, however,
Kant did not seem to have seen the difference between the sexes in these
terms. Despite the change in his moral theory that made “feminine
virtues” mere illusions of virtue, Kant never gave up the idea that women
ought to seek these virtues rather than the unconditional good will to
which men should aspire.
In the end, Kant’s treatment of women, in the context of his
anthropology as a whole, raises problems and tensions that continue
even today to affect thinking about relations between the sexes, and
between empirical and transcendental philosophy. But Kant not only
rejects the most natural ways of dealing with these problems, but his
infatuation with the “charming difference that nature sought to establish
between the two human sexes” (2:228) seems to have made him blindly
and complacently unaware of them.
IV. Racial and ethnic differences
Kant’s account of sex differences is not the only part of his
anthropology that is offensive and problematic for his philosophy.
Another important aspect of Kant’s account of human beings is his
theory of racial and national character. It is important to distinguish
three separate aspects of Kant’s account, especially with respect to racial
difference. First, Kant makes statements about other races that are, from
our contemporary standpoint, outrageously racist. Second, Kant
develops a complicated theory of race, one that played a role in the
development of scientific racism in the 19th century and thereby
continues to affect the way races are conceived today. Finally, Kant’s
moral and political theory at times specifically addresses the
relationships between peoples of different racial and ethnic groups.
Precisely how these different elements of his views fit together is not
always clear; and at least the first, and probably the second, share with
155 Kant’s views on women both immediate offensiveness and serious
tension with his transcendental philosophy.
Throughout this section, I focus on racial rather than ethnic (or
what Kant calls “national”) differences.120 Kant was (one of) the first
thinker(s) to develop a scientific concept of “race,” and many of his most
outrageous comments about other peoples are comments about nonEuropean races. But it is important to note that with the exception of a
series of articles published during the 1780s, Kant was much more
interested in differences amongst European peoples than in differences
between Europeans and non-Europeans. His published Anthropology
includes a major section on differences amongst European nations but
only two short paragraphs on the character of the races, and even his
Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime devotes only a
“quick look” at “other parts of the world” (2:252) after offering a
substantial discussion of differences between European people groups
(French, Spanish, English, etc.) (2:243-52). The emphasis of this section
on different races is due both to the presence of a systematic race-theory
in Kant’s own writings and to the importance of “race” today. For Kant,
however, differences amongst Europeans were at least as important as
differences between Europeans and others.121
a) Kant’s descriptions of other races
Kant’s most disgraceful (published) claims about races are found
in his Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime. After
describing a conversation about the nature of women between an African
carpenter and a European missionary, Kant writes of the African’s
comments,
There might be something here worth considering, except for the fact
that this scoundrel was completely black from head to foot, a distinct
proof that what he said was stupid. (2:254-5)
120
I also do not discuss Kant’s important comments about Jews (see especially R 6:125ff.); some, but not
all, of the present discussion is relevant to assessing these comments. While his views have been seen as
important precursors of later German anti-Semitism, they would take the present discussion too far afield
because Kant sees the Jews primarily through a cultural and religious rather than racial lens.
121
Whether Kant would extend this interest in ethnic as opposed to racial differences to other races is not
clear. He often distinguishes different ethnic groups within non-European races (see, e.g., 2:252), but he
also seems to think that a “definite national character” is an accomplishment that depends upon a level of
civilization of which non-European races seem incapable (see, e.g., 7:319).
156 Kant’s general characterization of Black Africans in Observations, though
painfully offensive, is also worth quoting:
The Negroes of Africa have by nature no feeling that rises above the
ridiculous. Mr. Hume challenges anyone to adduce a single example
where a Negro has demonstrated talents, and asserts that among the
hundreds of thousands of blacks who have been transported
elsewhere from their countries, although very many of them have
been set free, nevertheless not a single one has ever be found who
has accomplished something great in art or science or shown any
other praiseworthy quality, while among the whites there are always
those who rise up from the lowest rabble and through extraordinary
gifts earn respect in the world. So essential is the difference between
these two human kinds, and it seems to be just as great with regard
to the capacities of mind as it is with respect to color. The religion of
fetishes which is widespread among them is perhaps a sort of
idolatry, which sinks so deeply into the ridiculous as ever seems to be
possible for human nature. A bird's feather, a cow's horn, a shell, or
any other common thing, as soon as it is consecrated with some
words, is an object of veneration and of invocation in swearing oaths.
The blacks are very vain, but in the Negro’s way, and so talkative that
they must be driven apart from each other by blows. (2:253)
This text does not represent the limit of Kant’s offensive comments. In
notes from his lecture course on Anthropology, Kant claims, in terms
reminiscent of his comments about women:
If we compare the character of the Oriental nations with the
character of the Europeans, we here thus find an essential difference,
which among all the governments and variations has nevertheless
remained in the case of the Oriental nations. A capacity to act in
accordance with concepts and principles is required for character. All
Oriental nations are completely incapable of judgment in accordance
with concepts. It is a big difference to judge a matter according to
shape, appearance, and intuition, and to judge [it] according to
concepts. All Oriental nations are not in the position to explain a
single property of morality or of justice through concepts; rather all
their morals are based on appearance. (25:655)
And in his Physical Geography,122 Kant offers a sort of summary of his
views of the different races of the world:
122
Kant taught a course in Physical Geography for decades (more than any other single course), and, like
his lectures on anthropology, student transcripts of these lectures were circulated during Kant’s days. Until
157 Humanity is at its greatest perfection in the race of the whites. The
yellow Indians do have a meager talent. The Negroes are far below
them and at the lowest point are a part of the American peoples.
(Physical Geography, 9:316, see too 25:843,123 1187-8)
These comments offer but a sample of the dismissive and demeaning
views about non-Europeans scattered throughout Kant’s writings and
lectures. Now Kant is not always entirely dismissive of other races. In
Observations, in sharp contrast to his Physical Geography, Kant has
some admiration for the “sublime cast of mind” of the “savages . . . of
North America.”
Lycurgus probably gave laws to such savages, and if a law-giver were
to arise among the six [Native American] nations, one would see a
Spartan republic arise in the new world; just as the undertaking of
the Argonauts is little different from the military expeditions of these
Indians, and Jason has nothing over Attakakullakulla except the
honor of a Greek name. (2:253-4, though cf. 25:1187)
And elsewhere Kant says that “the Hindus . . . have a strong degree of
composure, . . . they all look like philosophers, . . . [and] they acquire
culture in the highest degree” (25:1187). On the whole, however, Kant’s
informal “observations” about other races reflect the prejudices of an
European satisfied with the superiority of his own race and ready to
believe the worst and most degrading claims about other races.
*
*
*
To those who know Kant through his moral philosophy or the
universal claims of his transcendental and empirical anthropology, these
deeply disdainful comments about other races are disturbing to say the
least. How should we respond to comments that seem so out of line with
the respect for humanity that Kant emphasizes elsewhere in his work?
recently, the main form in which these lectures have been available to Kant scholars has been in an edition
put together by Kant’s student Friedrich Theodor Rink, likely based on notes from two different courses
and included in volume 9 of Kant’s works. Volume 26 of Kant’s works (published partly in 2009 and
partly forthcoming) will include many more versions of student notes from Kant’s Physical Geography
course.
123
The remarks at 25:843, while not wholly reliable because based on lecture notes, are perhaps the most
disturbing. There Kant not only sets up an implicit hierarchy of races, but adds that “Negros are not capable
of any further civilization . . . The Indians and Chinese seem to be static in perfection, for their history
books show that they do not know more now than they have long known.” (25:843). For both Africans and
Asians, Kant alludes to character traits that are not merely physical (civilization and learning) and suggests
not only that these races are inferior to whites, but that they cannot ever improve.
158 Unlike Kant’s comments about sex, where many continue to argue
that there are important differences between men and women that may
be relevant to moral or epistemic issues, the notion that there are serious
innate differences between races that would inhibit members of a
particular race from being able to satisfy the demands of Kant’s
transcendental anthropology can hardly be taken seriously. To those who
know Toni Morrison, Jacob Lawrence, Benjamin Banneker, or Wangari
Maathai, Kant’s reference to Hume’s claim that “not a single [African] has
ever be found who has accomplished something great in art or science”
would display little more than laughable ignorance if it were not so
appalling (2:253). With respect race, the issue is not whether to accept
Kant’s racial distinctions and adjust his transcendental philosophy or
vice versa. No serious thinker today can affirm Kant’s racial
observations. But two issues remain: first, whether Kant’s views on nonwhite races taint the rest of his philosophy such that his claims about,
say, moral norms or cultural progress must be abandoned because they
are inextricably linked with racism, and second, how Kant – that
champion of universal human dignity – could espouse views that seem to
deny that dignity to most of the world.
One response to the first issue involves simply dismissing or
ignoring Kant’s racially offensive comments. While there are glimmers of
Kant’s views of other races in his more well-known writings – the most
famous being his reference in Groundwork to “the South Sea Islanders . .
. [who] let talents rust and are concerned with devoting life merely to
idleness, amusement, [and] procreation” (4:423) – by and large Kant’s
best read texts give little explicit indication of his racial views. It seems
easy to excise these offensive texts from Kant’s corpus, ignore them, and
focus on the parts of Kant’s thought that can and should be candidates
for serious consideration today. This strategy is far and away the
dominant way of dealing with Kant’s claims about races and has
important advantages, but it is not without its dangers.
The advantages should be clear. Kant’s philosophy has had
profound impacts on metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, aesthetics,
philosophy of religion, political theory and so on. Kant’s moral
philosophy, in particular, continues to play important roles in
safeguarding human rights and individual autonomy. Throwing out
Kant’s insights in these areas because of his personal views about other
races is a waste. Moreover, Kant himself provides an important
justification for leaving his racially offensive comments behind and
focusing on the rest of his anthropology. For Kant, transcendental
anthropology (epistemology, ethics, and even aesthetics) must be
developed a priori; empirical insights – including observations about
159 human differences – are relevant only later, in thinking about how to
apply a priori norms to empirically-situated human beings. Given Kant’s
own discipline in isolating his transcendental philosophy from his
empirical observations, one seems justified in ignoring the latter and
reaping the insights of the former, especially with empirical claims so
clearly false.
That said, simply ignoring Kant’s comments on race brings
important dangers. One danger is that one risks misunderstanding those
parts of Kant that one chooses to accept. Kant’s apparently off-handed
reference to the South Sea Islanders, for example, actually involves him
taking an important stand in contemporary debates about the moral
status of so-called “primitive” peoples. Most travelers’ accounts,
especially of Tahiti (rediscovered by Europeans in 1767), were both
“morally provocative” – contrasting Europeans morals with those of the
native – and “complimentary,” in that travelers to these places typically
presented the lives of at least the Tahitians (and often other “savages” as
well) as idyllic not only in terms of pleasures but also of morals (Wilson
1998: 317). Kant’s insistence that the cultivation of one’s perfections
(including non-moral talents) is a duty is an important part of his moral
philosophy, one for which Kant offers an apparently universal
justification. But in the context of Kant’s claims about other races, this
claim can be situated into a general Kantian defense of the superiority of
the ambitiously progressive historical self-conception of a European
comparing himself to the rest of the world. In itself, this added insight
does not give a reason to reject Kant’s claim that humans ought to
cultivate their talents. But it does force one to look more carefully at the
justification and implications of that claim.124 Precisely how to
understand claims that might otherwise seem to be universal, especially
when these arise in Kant’s transcendental anthropology, cannot be easily
settled simply by pointing to Kant’s views about races. But paying
attention to these views can force more careful attention to nuances in
Kant’s philosophical views.
This point highlights other risks of simply dismissing Kant’s views
on race. Kant’s claims about other races at least seem to conflict with
124
For another example, when Kant claims in the Critique of Judgment that human beings seek systematic
interconnections amongst empirical objects and the laws that govern them, he might seem to mean this as a
universal claim about all human beings. But Kant’s views about other races (e.g. about “Oriental nations”)
suggests that it might simply be a claim about the human species as a whole. Kant may not be committed to
the view that each human being seeks systematic interconnection, but only that human beings as a group
seek this, and within that group, that white Europeans lead the way.
160 other aspects of Kant’s anthropology. At the very least, they raise
questions about how Kant could have reconciled his universal
anthropology with a view that “Negroes” are irredeemably stupid and
“Orientals” incapable of concepts. Trying to figure out how Kant could
have held together what seem to be such disparate views can open up
new insights into the meaning, limits, and dangers of what might
otherwise seem benign aspects of his philosophy.125 Alternatively,
showing precisely the way in which, say, Kant’s moral theory conflicts
with these claims can reveal that moral theory as an important resource
for overcoming racism today.126 Finally, failing to pay attention to Kant’s
negative views on race can mark a missed opportunity to more fully
understand the limits of philosophy itself. Investigating how Kant, who
claims, “I would feel by far less useful than the common laborer if I did
not believe that [my philosophy] could impart a value to all others in
order to establish the rights of humanity” (20:44), could hold such
offensive views about other races can help reveal some of the causes that
continue to prolong racism today.
Despite the dangers of simply ignoring Kant’s racially offensive
comments, however, dismissing Kant’s whole philosophy as tainted by
racism is even more dangerous. For one thing, Kant’s transcendental
anthropology has played an extremely important role in helping
philosophers – and our society as a whole – come to see racism as
unacceptable. Kant’s moral philosophy, with its emphasis on the need to
respect the infinite worth of each and every human being, is still one of
the most powerful philosophical tools for combating racism. And as we
will see in chapter nine, even Kant’s epistemological claim that our world
is constructed in terms of a priori categories we impose on it has helped
cultivate an awareness of the extent to which nonuniversal categories of
thought can also shape our experiences, an awareness crucial for crosscultural understanding. And although Kant’s interest in transforming the
study of other cultures into a serious academic discipline was tainted by
how he wanted to do that, his conviction that being an educated world
citizen requires understanding not only universal characteristics of
human beings but also human differences remains an important insight
today. Finally, a considerable amount of Kant’s philosophy, at least as
that philosophy has been taken up and influences philosophers today,
can be freed of Kant’s racist views. The mere fact that most readers of
Kant – including those whose interpretations are most influential – are
virtually (and often completely) unaware of his views on races shows that
those views can, at least to a considerable degree, be understood and
125
126
See Eze 1994, Larrimore 1999, and Louden 2000.
See Boxill and Hill 2001, Louden 2000.
161 appreciated independently. As philosophers and scholars continue to
explore the implications and impact of Kant’s racial views on his
philosophy as a whole, some interpretations of Kant will have to change,
and some aspects of his views that might have seemed plausible will now
raise more suspicion. But there is at present no reason to think that his
philosophy as a whole will need to be dismissed simply because most of
his claims about other races must be.
When we turn to how Kant could have held these views, the
obvious response – simply ascribing Kant’s racial stereotypes to his
eighteenth-century background – is not entirely satisfying. On the one
hand, his racist views are largely informed by popular prejudices of
Kant’s time. The contexts in which Kant’s comments occur are almost
entirely contexts in which Kant is deliberately seeking to write (or teach)
in ways that will be “popular,” “entertaining” for his readers and students
(10:146). Observations, in which his most outrageous claims occur, was
Kant’s most popular book during his lifetime and was written in part to
attract students to his lectures. Because negative attitudes towards nonwhite racial groups were widely shared amongst the public at large in the
eighteenth century, Kant’s demeaning comments would likely have
enhanced his works’ popularity. His working-class background may have
encouraged him to draw divisions between people that would put himself
and the upper class students that he needed to attract to his lectures on
the same side. Being a relatively poor intellectual who never went more
than 90 miles from home, Kant was limited in his data about other races
to accounts written by merchants, explorers, and missionaries. In fact,
Kant’s courses in Physical Geography and Anthropology were, at least in
part, designed “to make a more certain knowledge of believable travel
accounts and to make this into a legitimate course of study.”127 Thus
Kant was, to a considerable degree, limited by the biases and prejudices
of the travel accounts to which he had access and the culture of which
he was a part.
On the other hand, however, it is also clear that eighteenthcentury thinking about non-white people was not uniformly negative.
Kant’s empirical sources were often much more generous in their
observations than Kant, being written by travelers influenced by a moral
ideal of simplicity that seemed well-exhibited in the exotic peoples they
observed (Wilson 1998). Among the most important alternative
theoretical ways of thinking about races were those of Kant’s own
student Herder, who, drawing from similar travel logs and empirical
sources, developed a much less patronizing view of non-European
127
Wilson 2006: 3.
162 nations, and Georg Forster, who not only published travel accounts of
his own that emphasized much more positive views of non-Europeans
but also specifically criticized Kant’s own race theory as being
insufficiently egalitarian in 1786. In both cases, Kant fought against
more generous portrayals of other races. In his review of Herder’s Ideas,
Kant even wrote:
[F]rom a multiplicity of descriptions of countries one can prove, if one
wants to, that Americans, Tibetans, and other genuine Mongolian
peoples have no beard, but also, if it suits you better, that all of them
are by nature bearded . . .; that Americans and Negroes are each a
race, sunk beneath the remaining of the human species in their
mental predispositions, but on the other side by just as apparent
records that as regards their natural predispositions, they are to be
estimated equal to every other inhabitant of the world; so it remains
to the choice of the philosopher whether he wants to assume
differences in nature or wants to just everything in accordance with
the principle “Everything is as it is with us.” (8:62)
This self-awareness about the process of picking and choosing amidst
empirical data shows how Kant could – even with his sources and his
cultural baggage – have developed a different view of non-white races.
And Kant should have seen the inconsistency of his dismissal of other
races with his own personal and philosophical trajectory: growing up in a
working class family, rising into the ranks of the intelligentsia, and then
recognizing on reading Rousseau that intellectuals are “far less useful
than the common laborer” except insofar as they defend “the rights of
humanity” (20:44). In the end, while one can point to reasons for Kant’s
demeaning views of other races in his cultural context, Kant’s own words
require him to acknowledge “the choice of the philosopher.” And while
one might understand this choice in terms of pleasing the crowd
(especially given the public purpose of his Observations)128 or even in
terms simply of making his best attempt at getting things right (given the
128
One might also see Kant not as endorsing but merely exploiting the racially demeaning views of his
times. Kant’s lower class background may have provided an incentive to embrace these demeaning views
to deflect class-based prejudices of his contemporaries. Moreover, by portraying Europeans as superior by
virtue of their ability to think in terms of concepts, to govern their lives on the basis of principles, and so
on, Kant exploits his readers’ (and listeners’) prejudices to exhort them to personal moral reform. Not only
are the norms of Kant’s transcendental anthropology the routes to autonomy and the fulfillment of one’s
vocation as a human being, but they are also the ways to distinguish oneself as a European from the savage
Americans, stupid Negroes, and fantastical Orientals. If one assumes that one’s readers and listeners
already have a sense of white superiority, associating that superiority with the authentic norms of human
autonomy is a way to inspire his readers to pursue these norms. In that sense, Kant masterfully uses the
rhetorical strategy whereby his readers mock and deride attributes of others, only to find that they need to
overcome those same attributes in themselves.
163 pedagogical purpose of his physical geography and anthropology
lectures), one must also admit that Kant, despite his acuity in some
areas of philosophy, was neither sufficiently thoughtful nor sufficiently
courageous in thinking about other races. Whatever the explanation,
Kant’s ability to combine a transcendental anthropology that emphasizes
universality with utterly dismissive claims about most of humanity is an
important lesson in the limits of merely philosophical insight.
b) Kant’s Race Theory
Kant’s most extreme claims about race come in early or informal
works, largely disconnected from any formal theory about races. But over
a decade after the publication of Observations, Kant wrote an essay
entitled “Of the difference races of human beings” that marked the
beginning of a series of papers in which Kant “invented the concept of
race” (Bernasconi 2001:11) or at least became “a leading proponent of
the concept of race at a time when its scientific status was still far from
secure” (Bernasconi 2002: 146). Kant’s racially offensive but informal
remarks bear a greater superficial similarity to present-day racism. But
his less immediately offensive theory of race arguably played a more
significant role in actually creating the conditions for present-day racism
by giving “the concept [of race] sufficient definition for subsequent users
to believe that they were addressing something whose scientific status
could at least be debated” (Bernasconi 2001: 11). As one commentator
puts it, “Once Kant’s role in constructing a rigorous concept of race is
established, it is relatively easy to give Kant a place in the history of
racism” (Bernasconi 2002: 146), a place he would not warrant merely for
his offensive comments (comments that played little role in the
development of racism and that were common at the time).
In one important respect, Kant’s theory of race was deeply antiracist, in that Kant was a staunch defender of “monogenesis” – the view
that all human beings are a single species derived from a common
ancestor – during a period in which polygenesis – the view that, for
instance, black Africans and white Europeans are actually different
species – was gaining prominence as Europeans increasingly interacted
with different groups. The different behavior and physical appearance of
distant peoples challenged the limits of the European imagination to the
point that postulating that different peoples were different species
seemed a natural response to the discomforting possibility that “we” and
“they” were the same sort of being. At the same time, the basic categories
of biological science were in flux, so there was no universally accepted
164 criterion for determining commonality of species. Neither “common
descent” nor taxonomic similarity provided clear bases for determining
whether different human populations were descended from common
ancestors and/or sufficiently similar to be grouped together. The
heritability of racial characteristics even after members of different
members were transplanted to new climates – i.e., the fact the Europeans
and their children did not become dark-skinned when living in Africa –
even seemed to suggest polygenesis.
In response to the growing interest in polygenesis, Kant sought a
scientific account of the human species that would reconcile
monogenesis with European’s desire to distinguish between people with
recognizable and heritable differences.129 The essence of Kant’s account
is to distinguish concepts of “species” and “race” and to provide clear
criteria for each. With respect to “species,” Kant adopts from his
contemporary Buffon what has come to be the standard account in
contemporary biology130: “animals that produce fertile young with one
another (whatever difference in shape there may be) still belong to one
and the same physical species” (2:429, see too 8:165-9). Kant
immediately applies this to the human case: “According to this concept,
all human beings on the wide earth belong to one and the same natural
species because they consistently beget fertile children with one another”
(2:430). Because being the same species does not necessarily imply
common ancestry, Kant makes his affirmation of (and justification for)
monogenesis explicit: “ [H]uman beings belong not merely to one and the
same species, but also to one family, [since otherwise] many local
creations [of members of the same species] would have to be assumed –
an opinion which needlessly multiplies the number of causes” (2:430).
129
It is not entirely clear why Kant was motivated to defend monogenesis. He may have had religious
motivations, a desire to ensure that biology is reconcilable with the Biblical account of creation, but given
Kant’s willingness in other areas to interpret the Bible to fit “within the boundaries of mere reason,” this
reason seems unlikely. Another theoretical possibility would be a resistance to the prejudice and oppression
that were often justified on the basis of polygenesis. But although (as we will see below) Kant was
vehemently opposed to the dominant forms of explicit racial oppression in his day, this justification seems
unlikely given the racial views discussed in the previous subsection. Most likely, Kant’s reason for
defending monogenesis is just what he claimed it to be, that polygenesis unnecessarily multiplies scientific
hypothesis (see 2:430). That is, Kant seems to have had a basically scientific motivation for developing his
view of different races. At least one other plausible and likely cause, suggested by Bernasconi, is that this
problem in biology – how to reconcile variation with monogenesis – simply gave Kant a good opportunity
to show the power of his philosophy of biology to deliver concrete results to a real problem facing the
scientific world.
130
There is considerable debate about and nuance within this present-day biological species concept, but
the concept developed by Buffon and Kant provides the core of the most prevalent contemporary versions
of it.
165 Having settled the issue in favor of monogenesis, Kant needs to
explain heritable diversity between different human groups, and he does
so with his concept of a race, defined as follows:
Among . . . the hereditary differences of animals which belong to a
single [species], those which persistently preserve themselves in all
transplantings (transpositions to other regions) over prolonged
generations among themselves and which also always beget halfbreed young in the mixing with other variations of the same [species]
are called races. (2:430)
In order to distinguish racial characteristics from differences due merely
to environmental conditions, Kant insists that racial differences must
persist over many generations even after the relevant “race” is
transplanted to a different place. Racial differences must also blend when
members of different races interbreed, which allows Kant to distinguish
such differences from what he calls difference in “strain” (2:430) and
thereby avoid calling different white European peoples different “races.”
In this way, Negroes and whites, while not different kinds of human
beings . . ., are still two different races because each of the two
perpetuates itself in all regions and both necessarily beget . . . blends
(mulattoes) with one another. By contrast, blondes and brunettes are
not difference races of whites, because a blond man can have entirely
blond children with a brunette woman. (2:431)
As this example suggests, Kant goes on to argue that skin color “is
especially suited” for dividing the races, since “no other characteristic
property is necessarily hereditary . . . [and] in the mixing of [peoples with
different skin colors] the character of each one is unfailingly hereditary”
(8:94-5). Thus Kant divides the human species into “four classificatory
differences . . . with respect to skin color . . .[:] the whites, the yellow
Indians, the Negroes, and the copper-red Americans” (8:93).131
For Kant, however, merely defining the concept of race and
classifying human beings is insufficient. Kant also aims to show how the
concept of race can be illuminated by his overall philosophy of biology,
and in particular by the role of natural teleology in empirical
anthropology. Thus Kant uses his account of natural predispositions in
131
Strikingly, Kant says – within a single page – both that “how much the natural skin color of the Kaffirs
differs from that of the Negroes . . . will not be decisively settled for a long time” and that “I assume that
there are no more hereditary ethnic characters . . . than the above four” (8:93-4). Over the course of his
writings on race, Kant never changes his definition of race, focus on skin color, or insistence that there are
only four races; but he changes his account of which four races are irreducible (cf., e.g. 2:432, 8:93).
166 order to explain both how and why human beings became differentiated
into different races. Starting with the purpose of racial differentiation,
Kant claims, “The human species was destined for all climates and for
every soil; consequently, various germs and natural predispositions had
to lie ready in him to be on occasion either unfolded or restrained”
(2:435, see too 8:168). The idea is that different racial characteristics are
well-suited for different climates. Given Nature’s end – for humans to
settle the entire globe – she endowed human beings with a variety of
predispositions that could develop differently in accordance with different
local conditions “so that he would become suited to his place” (2:435).
For Kant, however, variability with local conditions is importantly not
merely an ability to adapt; it has a hereditary component:
Once a race . . . had established itself . . . this race could not be
transformed into another one through any influences of the climate.
For only the [original representatives of the species] can [develop]132
into a race; however, once a race has taken root and suffocated the
other germs, it resists all transformation just because the character
of the race has then become prevailing in the generative power.
(2:442, see too 8:166, 172)
What begins as a mere lack of expression of certain natural “germs” (akin
to predispositions) becomes, over time, a “suffocation” of those germs. It
is unclear whether Kant intends to say that the germs literally die out, or
– more likely – that a propensity for them not to express themselves
becomes hereditary. In either case, individual adaptations to climate
become fixed characteristics. And this, too, has a natural purpose, so
that human beings, “over the course of generations . . . appear to be . . .
made for that place” in which they reside (2:435). Nature intends not
only for human beings to spread all over the globe, but also for humans
to fit well wherever they find themselves to be. Kant thus charts a middle
path between those who claim that human beings are biologically
distinct and those that claim that differences are environmental.
Differences between human beings are caused by environmental factors,
but at least some of these differences – notably skin color – can become
hereditary.
In many respects, Kant’s formal theory of race is much less
problematic than his informal negative comments about various races.
132
Kant uses the technical term “degenerate” here. In 18th century biology, the term “degeneration” was
used in virtually the way that we use the term “evolve” today, and it lacked many of the negative
connotations that we associate with the term today.
167 With rare exceptions, Kant’s race essays refrain from describing moral or
intellectual qualities as hereditary, and the claim that skin color is
necessarily hereditary is not, in itself, particularly offensive. Arguably,
Kant’s account of race is even an important step towards a broadly
Darwinian account of the possibility of environmentally-caused
hereditable changes in given populations. But Kant’s race theory raises
three new problems for assessing Kant’s philosophy as a whole. First,
given how Kant situates his race theory in the context of the stagnation
of various natural predispositions, his race theory raises the stakes of his
racially disparaging comments. If other races have literally lost the
capacity for moral or intellectual advancement, this poses problems for
Kant’s moral theory and philosophy of history that are similar to those
raised in the context of the sexes (where women seemed incapable of
moral worth). Second, whatever its relationship to his moral theory,
Kant’s race theory seems deeply intertwined with the account of natural
teleology in his Critique of Judgment, which provides the capstone of his
transcendental anthropology as a whole. Even if Kant’s transcendental
anthropology could be isolated from Kant’s informal comments about
races, it seems harder to isolate his race theory. Finally, even if Kant’s
race theory is not as immediately offensive as the comments discussed in
the last section, by contributing to the development of a scientific, skincolor-based conception of race, Kant arguably played a real historical role
in the development of modern racism.
With respect to the first issue, Kant’s works provide mixed
evidence about the extent to which he conceived of moral and intellectual
attributes as irremediably fixed in races. In Observations, the early essay
with Kant’s most atrocious claims about races, Kant adds a crucial
footnote to the title of the section in which he discusses different
races133:
My intention is not at all to portray the characters of the peoples in
detail; rather I will only outline some features that express the feeling
of the sublime and the beautiful in them. One can readily guess that
only a tolerable level of accuracy can be demanded in such a
depiction, that its prototypes stand out in the large crowds of those
who make claim to a finer feeling, and that no nation is lacking in
casts of mind which unite the foremost predominant qualities of this
kind. For this reason the criticism that might occasionally be cast on
133
Because this section focuses on “The Character of the Nations,” including non-European races as an
afterthought, the footnotes might be restricted to Europeans. But they show a way that Kant could reconcile
claims about races with his universalist moral theory.
168 a people can offend no one, as it is like a ball that one can always hit
to his neighbor. (2:243n)
Later, Kant reiterates,
It is hardly necessary for me to repeat my previous apology here. In
each people the finest portion contains praiseworthy characters of all
sorts, and whoever is affected by one or another criticism will, if he is
fine enough, understand it to his advantage, which lies in leaving
everyone else to his fate but making an exception of himself. (2:245n)
At least in Observations, Kant sees differences between people groups
like those between temperaments, as natural advantages or
disadvantages that can be overcome through making an exception of
oneself. Readers should take negative characterizations of their nation or
race as exhortations to moral strength rather than signs of inextricable
inferiority. Moreover, although Kant refers to differences between
Europeans and Africans as “essential” (2:253) and seems fixed even upon
change of conditions, his early comments on racial differences stick to
the level of “observations.” Kant even claims,
I will not investigate here whether these national differences are
contingent and depend upon the times and the type of government,
or whether they are connected with a certain necessity with the
climate. (2:243n)
And even when Kant develops his formal race theory, in which he argues
for essential and hereditary racial characteristics, he insists that “no
characteristic property other [than skin color] is necessarily hereditary”
(8: 94). And in an anthropology lecture delivered the same year that Kant
published his “Of the different races of human beings,” he uses Indians
as examples to show that all human being have the same underlying
“germs.”
Who has seen a savage Indian or Greenlander, should he indeed
believe that there is a germ innate to this same [being], to become
just such a man in accordance with Parisian fashion, as another
[would become]? He has, however, the same germs as a civilized
human being, only they are not yet developed. (25:694)
In these and other passages, Kant seems to endorse the view that
whatever moral and intellectual differences there are between races can,
to some extent, be overcome.
169 On the other hand, Kant’s comments about other races often imply
a heritable and unchangeable moral and intellectual inferiority of some
races to others. Kant’s rankings of various races (see, e.g., 2:441), and
his claim in Observations that the differences between Africans and
Europeans are “essential” and “just as great with regard to the capacities
of mind as it is with respect to color” (2:253) imply as much. And
although his formal race essays emphasize skin color, the last of these
essays describes Native Americans as “incapable of any culture” (8:176,
emphasis added, cf. 10:239), and the first ascribes to them a “halfextinguishes life power” while describing Africans as “lazy, soft, and
trifling” (2:438). Perhaps the most systematic-sounding claim comes in a
footnote of Kant’s last race essay. Here, in the context of a discussion of
whether African slaves could be used as free laborers, Kant writes:
Should one not conclude . . . that in addition to the faculty to work,
there is also an immediate drive to activity (especially to the
sustained activity that one calls industry), which . . . is especially
interwoven with certain natural predispositions; and that Indians as
well as Negroes do not bring any more of this impetus into other
climates and pass it on to their offspring than was needed for their
preservation in their old motherland . . . [where t]he far lesser needs .
. . demand no greater predispositions to activity. (8:174n)
Strictly speaking, Kant does not claim that Negroes or Indians are
incapable of activity or industry, but he does suggest a biological basis
for the “laziness” ascribed to them in earlier essays, which brings
motivational characteristics into the realm of biologically fixed racial
differences. In the end, Kant does not strictly commit himself to race
differences with moral implications as profound as those of sex, but even
insofar as he approaches these sorts of views, Kant’s moral philosophy
and philosophy of history give decisive reasons to favor treating Kant’s
characterizations of various races in just the way that Kant suggests in
Observations, as a catalogue of traits to which individual members of
those races can and should make exceptions of themselves. Even this
way of reading Kant is hardly without its dangers. Members of racial
groups who are classified as having particular defects can come either to
be demoralized through Kant’s theory or to overcompensate, trying to
“prove themselves” in ways that go far beyond the actual demands of
moral and cultural life. Even interpreted in the most generous way,
Kant’s race theory brings problems, and taken too far, it could license
the worst racist abuses, as Kant’s seeming support of slavery in the
footnote above might forebode.
170 On the second issue – the relationship between Kant’s race theory
and his Critique of Judgment – it would be nice to say, as we did with
Kant’s informal observations about race, that one can insulate his
Critical philosophy from his race theory. In fact, however, as Robert
Bernasconi has rightly pointed out, “Kant’s understanding of race is at
stake in the discussion of teleology in the Critique of Judgment”
(Bernasconi 2002:147, see too Bernasconi 2001). But the relationship
between race theory, teleology, and the central aspects of Kant’s Critical
philosophy (and with it, his transcendental anthropology), is not as
problematic as some commentators (e.g. Eze 1994) have suggested
because it tends to be unidirectional. Race theory supports for Kant’s
philosophy of biology primarily by showing a particularly interesting way
in which it can be applied, but the general points that Kant makes use of
in his race theory – such as the distinction between natural history and
mere description of nature (2:434n, 8:153f) or the legitimacy of
teleological principles in biology (8:157-84) – are, as Kant recognizes,
compatible with different specific empirical accounts depending upon the
empirical details to which they are applied. Where Kant’s race theories go
astray is not at the level of these general methodological principles but in
the specific and misguided application of them. Thus while problems
with the accounts of judgment and teleology in the Critique of Judgment
could undermine Kant’s race theory, abandoning his race theory
altogether, if done for empirical and not methodological reasons, would
not jeopardize his Critique at all.134 Kant’s more general philosophy of
biology does not preclude scientific racism, which may be an indictment
of a sort, but it also does not imply Kant’s theory of race.
The final issue – the role of Kant in the development of modern
racism – is in some respects the most complicated. Kant’s race theory,
with its defense of monogenesis and emphasis on physical rather than
moral or intellectual characteristics, is the sort of theory that one would
expect a thoughtful, cosmopolitan humanitarian to develop in the 18th
century. As a way of making sense of the confusing array of
anthropological discoveries faced by Europeans coming into greater
contact with the rest of the world, Kant’s race theory might have seemed
to be extremely well suited to his moral ideals. All human beings are a
single species and hence – one would think – equally worthy of respect
and capable of the highest human ideals. But there are real, hereditary,
134
Similarly, Kant’s theory of race could prove an important supplement to Kant’s moral philosophy. It
might affect how one applied moral principle to other races (though see next section), or – more likely – it
might affect the sorts of moral education we apply to different races. In either case, changes to Kant’s race
theory could affect the application of his moral theory, but need not pose problems for the core of that
moral theory.
171 biological differences between people that manifest in their physical
appearance. So far, so good.
But Kant’s race theory did not in fact limit itself to physical
characteristics. We have already seen this in Kant’s own life, where he
combined a scientific account of race with intensely negative
characterization of non-European races. But the same held true for those
who appropriated the concept of race as a scientific concept in the 19th
and 20th centuries. Given the role that “scientific racism” came to play in
the entrenchment of racist ideology (especially in Europe and the
Americas),135 Kant’s role in making this science possible implicates him
in those racist ideologies, even if only indirectly. Kant’s concept of race
was not, of course, the most important influence on racism (even
scientific racism) in the 20th century; Darwin’s account was more
important. And if Kant’s personal views were different, his overall place
in the history of racism might well be that of the well-intentioned but
naïve humanitarian attempting to combat proto-racist tendencies
through science, whose science ended up working to promote racism.
But given Kant’s personal views about race and the fact that his race
theory did in fact end up playing a real role in the development of what
has come to be modern-day racism, Kant must – unfortunately – be given
a prominent a place in the history of racism, as he has in the histories of
human rights, aesthetics, theology, and other fields where his impact has
been more positive.
c) Political issues: Slavery and colonialism
When Kant turns from descriptions of different races to
prescriptions for how to deal with members of other races, the merits of
his moral philosophy overwhelm the offense of his empirical
anthropology. The two most important issues facing Europeans in their
interactions with other races were the closely connected issues of
colonialism and race-based slavery. And Kant’s later political writings
involve detailed and impassioned rejections of both. With respect to
slavery, Kant’s published writings are clear and direct.136 He refers to
135
See especially Gould 1981.
Kant’s unpublished writings are less clear about the issue of slavery. In notes written during the 1780s,
Kant seems to accept the notion that “Americans and negroes cannot govern themselves. Thus [they] are
good only as slaves” (15:878). Strictly speaking, these comments need not morally justify chattel slavery,
but they seem at least in tension with Kant’s later works. On the other side, Kant’s notes for his Perpetual
Peace include condemnations of slavery – especially the enslavements of non-whites by whites – that are
136
172 West Indian (or “Sugar Islands”) slavery as “the cruelest and most
calculated slavery” (8:359) and insists in his Metaphysics of Morals not
only that no one may sell himself into slavery (6:270) but also that any
relationship between master and servant can be “at most only for an
unspecified time, within which one party may give the other notice” and
“children . . . are at all times free” (6:283). Whatever forms of indentured
servitude might be allowed, the chattel slavery associated with the slave
trade and European (especially British) colonialism are excluded. With
respect to colonialism in general, Kant is even more eloquent:
If one compares with [the duty to universal hospitality] the
inhospitable behavior of civilized, especially commercial, states in our
part of the world, the injustice they show in visiting foreign lands and
people (which with them is tantamount to conquering them) goes to
horrifying lengths. When American, the negro countries, the Spice
Islands, the Cape, and so forth were discovered, they were, to them,
countries belonging to no one, since they counted the inhabitants as
nothing. In the East Indies (Hindustan), they brought in foreign
soldiers under the pretext of merely proposing to set up trading
posts, but [brought] with them the oppression of the inhabitants,
incitement of the various Indian states to widespread wars, famine,
rebellions, treachery, and the whole litany of troubles that oppress
the human race. (8:358-9)137
Kant not only vehemently rejects the practice of “counting [non-white
peoples] as nothing,” but he shows a surprisingly degree of insight into
the deceptive justifications for standard practices of European
colonialism, even emphasizing that his “right to hospitality – that is, the
even more impassioned and detailed than those in his published writings. Pauline Kleingeld summarizes
some of these:
[Kant] sharply criticizes ‘the civilized countries bordering the seas’, whom he accuses of recognizing
no normative constraints in their behaviour towards people on other continents and of regarding the
‘possessions and even the person of the stranger as a loot given to them by Nature’. Kant censures the
slave trade (‘trade in Negroes’), not as an excessive form of an otherwise acceptable institution, but as
in itself a ‘violation’ of the cosmopolitan right of blacks (23:174). Similarly, he criticizes the fact that
the inhabitants of America were . . . ‘displaced or enslaved’ soon after Europeans reached the
continent (23:173-4). (Kleingeld 2007: 15).
The combination of these comments lends credence to the view (noted below) that Kant changes his views
on race in the 1790s.
137
Kant’s quotation goes on to refer to the wisdom of the “great empire” of China, as well as Japan, in
limiting access of Europeans to their lands (8:359).
173 authorization of the foreign newcomer – does not extend beyond the
condition which makes it possible to seek commerce with the old
inhabitants” (8:358), drawing attention to the practice of using trade to
control other peoples. In his Metaphysics of Morals, Kant returns to the
issue of colonialism, now connecting it with the same end of Nature that
played such an important role in his race theory, the spreading of human
beings across the globe. Kant claims that “all nations stand originally in
a community of land” but emphasizes that this does not give anyone the
right to possess any land they find. Instead, Kant emphasizes the right of
first possession (6:263) and specifically applies this to the case of “newly
discovered lands”:
If the settlement [of these lands] is made so far from where [the local]
people reside that there is no encroachment on anyone’s use of his
land, the right to settle is not open to doubt. But if these people are
shepherds or hunters (like the Hottentots, the Tungusi, or most of
the American Indian nations) who depend for their sustenance on
great open regions, this settlement may not take place by force but
only by contract, and indeed by a contract that does not take
advantage of the ignorance of those inhabitants with respect to
ceding their lands. This is true despite . . . it [being] to the world’s
advantage . . . [A]ll these supposedly good intentions cannot wash
away the stain of injustice in the means used for them. (6:353)
Again, Kant not only rejects the practice of seizing land in the “New”
World, but specifically addresses two of the main ways in which this
practice is justified, through appeals to the greater good (e.g., that
American Indian land can be better used for farming than for hunting)
and through spurious “contracts” whereby natives are robbed of their
land by virtue of not fully understanding the costs and benefits at stake.
Despite whatever personal views he may hold about the capacities of
non-white peoples, Kant has no tolerance for failing to afford them the
rights consistent with the humanity that we all share in common, and he
eloquently defends those rights against encroaching colonial practices of
Europeans.
There are at least two important ways of reading Kant’s moral and
political stances towards other races, both of which at least partially
redeem Kant as a thinker about race. First, one might rightly point out
that Kant’s moral theory emphasizes the importance of respect for the
humanity of others, where humanity primarily involves the mere capacity
for choice. Just as Kant insists that a person’s (radical) evil does not
174 justify denying them respect, so he should equally insist that whatever
differences there are between Europeans and non-Europeans, as long as
non-Europeans are human beings with a capacity for choice, they must
be respected. In that sense, Kant’s moral arguments against slavery and
colonialism are not only consistent with his overall moral theory but
show the power of that moral theory even in the face of extreme personal
prejudice. Second, one might find in Kant’s political writings some hint
that Kant’s views on other races changed in response to criticisms by
Forster, Herder, and others (see Kleingeld 2007). The comments in which
Kant is disparaging of other races gradually cease after 1792, such that
Kant’s Anthropology (published in 1798), while in other respects following
the general outline of his Observations, refrains from making any
mention of his views on race, instead referring readers to a text by
another author. This has led at least one scholar to argue that “Kant
changed and improved his position[on race] during the 1790s” (Kleingeld
2007:3).
Neither of these ways of reading Kant’s later work justifies the
racially offensive comments found elsewhere. The fact that in his later
years Kant did not use negative characterizations of other races to justify
slavery or colonialism does not take away the real harm of depicting
them as naturally inferior to whites, and Kant was well aware of the
damage to one’s personhood that comes from damaging the way that one
is perceived in the eyes of others. Even changing his views eventually
does not justify Kant’s holding them for as long as he did. But just as
Kant’s other writings on race show the limits of Kant’s moral philosophy,
these later texts show some of its power. At the very least, the emphasis
on universal human dignity in his moral philosophy helped prevent Kant
from drawing the worst practical implications of his early views on other
races. At best, his philosophy may have even helped him see the errors of
those views.
V. Conclusion
Kant’s transcendental and even empirical anthropology has often
been criticized for being excessively universal, for painting all humans
with the same brush and ignoring the differences between them, for
being insufficiently attentive to the idiosyncratic, masculine, or European
perspective from which Kant writes. Kant himself was deeply attuned to
these concerns. Even before he started developing an a priori
transcendental anthropology, Kant insisted on teaching a course in
physical geography to “make good [his students] lack of experience” and
175 equip them to function in the world. An important part of this course was
exposing his students to the variety of manners and types of people in
the world, and from his early Observations to his eventually courses (and
book) in anthropology, Kant expanded this part of his geography course
to included detailed accounts of human difference so his students could
act and judge well in a diverse human world.
In broad outline, this attention to human difference as an
important part of being an active world citizen is an admirable aspect of
Kant’s overall anthropology, something that should make that
anthropology more appealing today. But the details of Kant’s accounts of
diversity reveal a darker side to attending to human difference. Kant’s
resources for understanding human difference were limited. He never
married and his primary knowledge of women was through formal dinner
parties and English novels. He never traveled, so his primary knowledge
of non-Europeans (and even most Europeans) was from books written by
others. Kant made the most of books, voraciously reading travel logs,
novels, scientific and medical treatises, and other accounts of human
difference. But even with this background, Kant recognized that
ultimately “the choice of the philosopher” plays a significant role in how
such data is interpreted. And Kant’s choices, with respect to both women
and non-Europeans, were generally reprehensible. What could have been
a significant improvement to Kant’s anthropology now serves as a
warning about the dangers of supplementing a transcendental
anthropology with an empirical one, and especially of supplementing a
universal anthropology with an account of diversity. Despite its errors
and dangers, however, Kant’s account of human diversity is an
important part of his overall account of human beings, and his insistence
that human difference as well as human similarity is an important part
of what makes us who we are is an insistence that continues to resonate
today (as we will see especially in chapter nine).
176 CHAPTER 5: PRAGMATIC ANTHROPOLOGY
The previous four chapters examined Kant’s transcendental
and empirical anthropologies, his normative and descriptive accounts of
human life from-within and from-without, as these “anthropologies” are
expressed in various written works and unpublished lectures composed
by Kant over his lifetime. At the end of his life, however, when Kant came
to write the only published work he entitled Anthropology, this book was
neither a Transcendental Anthropology nor an Empirical Anthropology.
Instead, Kant wrote Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. And
throughout his life, Kant taught “Anthropology” courses that cannot be
described as either transcendental or empirical. Instead, what Kant
sought to do, throughout his life and especially in Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View, was to develop a new approach to thinking
about human beings, one that combined theoretical insight into human
nature with humans’ fundamental practical concerns, and one that
avoided stale, metaphysical debates about such things as the
relationship between mind and body, while providing a useful,
philosophically sophisticated, systematic answer to the question “What is
the human being?” In his “pragmatic” anthropology, Kant pulls together
his transcendental and empirical anthropologies into a coherent whole
that can help his readers actually “properly fulfill [our] station in
creation” (20:41). Pragmatic anthropology thus marks a sort of
culmination of Kant’s anthropology. While not the arena within which
Kant answers all the questions of philosophy, it is where he most fully
combines philosophical insights with empirical-psychological
observations of human beings in order to improve humans’ cognition,
feelings, and actions.
Kant does, of course, discuss “anthropology” in his previous
published works, most famously in his Groundwork and Metaphysics of
Morals. In the first, he explains that “ethics” will have an “empirical part”
called “practical anthropology,” which will help him “distinguish in what
cases [moral laws] are applicable and . . . provide them with access to the
will of the human being” (4:388-9) and “would deal . . . with the
subjective conditions in human nature that help or hinder in fulfilling
the laws of a metaphysics of morals” (6:217). Moreover, as we saw in
chapter three, Kant’s discussion of humans’ radical evil requires some
explanation for how one can work to undo and arm oneself against selfwrought evil tendencies, an explanation that one would expect from his
moral anthropology. One might think, then, that Kant’s Anthropology
from a Pragmatic Point of View would provide the much-needed
supplement for his pure moral philosophy.
177 In fact, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View does provide
this supplement, but the text also goes much further than a merely
moral anthropology. From Kant’s transcendental anthropology, one
might think that Kant cares only about those aspects of human nature
that are subject to a priori normative principles. And while his empirical
anthropology shows his interest in investigating a much broader range of
human action, one might be left with the impression that anything that
does not ultimately serve moral, epistemic, or aesthetic ends is, for Kant,
a flaw in human nature. Kant’s pragmatic anthropology alleviates these
concerns by showing Kant’s interest in helping humans become better at
all of those aspects of human life that make it worth living. As he
explained in an early (1773) letter to a former student, his course in
anthropology will “disclose the basis of . . . everything that pertains to
the practical” (10:146, see too 16:804).
This general understanding of pragmatic as practical shows up
early in Kant’s published Anthropology. Kant distinguishes his
“pragmatic” anthropology from a “physiological” one on the grounds that
whereas the latter emphasizes “what nature makes of the human being,”
pragmatic anthropology attends to “what he as a free-acting being makes
. . . or can and should make of himself” (7:119). More specifically, while
the physiological anthropologist looks at the neurophysical bases of
mental powers, “he must admit that in this play of his representations he
is a mere observer and must let nature run its course, for he does not
understand how to put [these neurophysical bases] to use for his
purposes” (7:119). In contrast, the pragmatic anthropologist focuses on
that “knowledge of the human being” that is useful for, say, improving
memory; this anthropologist “uses perceptions concerning what has been
found to hinder or stimulate memory in order to enlarge it or make it
agile” (7:119).
Kant’s particular example of memory is important for clarifying
what exactly is meant when Kant refers to the subject matter of
pragmatic anthropology as something that “concerns . . . the
investigation of what he as a free-acting being makes of himself, or can
and should make of himself.” In particular, Kant does not imply here
that pragmatic anthropology takes the free subject of transcendental
anthropology as its primary topic of investigation. In the rest of Kant’s
Anthropology, not only through his stated methodology (7:120-22) but in
his actual practice, the information about human beings that makes up
the content of pragmatic anthropology is empirical. In an important
sense, then, pragmatic anthropology has no distinctive content of its
own. Elsewhere, Kant even denies a distinctive content to “practical
psychology” – using the term psychology here to refer to what he
178 elsewhere calls anthropology – saying instead that all of its principles are
mere “scholia” of empirical “knowledge of [human] nature” (20:199).
Pragmatic anthropology is concerned with free-acting human beings in
that it is addressed to human agents who can make use of empirical
knowledge for accomplishing their (freely-chosen) goals.
When one asks where the ends served by pragmatic anthropology
arise, one must look to transcendental anthropology in the broadest
sense. It is only from-within the standpoints of thinking, feeling, and
willing that one comes to discover – at least in outline – what the human
being should make of himself. As freely-acting beings, human beings find
themselves with two main orienting principles of volition: happiness and
duty. And from the start, Kant recognized that these orienting principles
require considerable empirical knowledge for their application.
Happiness is “such an indeterminate concept that although every human
being wishes to attain this, he can still never say determinately and
consistently with himself what he really wishes and wills” (4:418) and
even moral laws require “a judgment sharpened by experience . . . to
distinguish in what cases they are applicable and . . . to provide them
with access to the will of the human being” (4:389). Kant’s pragmatic
anthropology thus fills in the empirical knowledge of human nature that
is required in order to discern not only the means for pursuing one’s
ends but even what ends Kant thinks free but finite human agents
should devote attention towards. Of these, of course, the only end that is
“good without limitation” (4:393) is the good will, so I begin my
discussion of Kant’s pragmatic anthropology with more specifically moral
anthropology.
1. Moral Anthropology
For Kant, “moral anthropology” provides a necessary empirical
supplement to his “pure” moral philosophy, rooted in his transcendental
anthropology of desire. Precisely what moral anthropology contributes is
disputed, however, and even seems to shift between Kant’s earlier and
later works in moral philosophy.138 In particular, we can distinguish two
different senses in which empirical anthropology might help supplement
a pure moral philosophy. First, and most obviously, we might need what
Kant, in Groundwork, refers to as a “judgment sharpened by experience .
. . in order to distinguish in what cases [moral principles] are applicable”
(4:389). Even for generating relatively specific principles from the
138
By “earlier” and “later” here I refer to Kant’s Groundwork (1785) and Metaphysics of Morals (1797). In
Kant’s earliest works in moral philosophy, such as his Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and
Sublime, there is no distinction between (empirical) anthropology and (pure) moral philosophy.
179 categorical imperative itself, we might need to include various sorts of
empirical information about human beings. For example, the obligation
not to make false promises only applies to beings like ourselves, not, for
instance, to the extra-terrestrials that Kant imagines in his anthropology,
“rational beings on some other planet who could not think in any other
way but aloud” (7:332). We might also use empirical facts about the
human desires to specify and apply our general obligation to promote the
happiness of others, and we can use facts about the limits of human
capabilities to set proper boundaries and conditions for a wide variety of
human interactions. As we will see at the end of the next section, Kant
does see pragmatic anthropology as playing a very important role in this
sort of application of moral principles to human life. But this role is not,
at least not in his most developed accounts of morality, the role that he
ascribes to “moral anthropology” strictly speaking.
Instead, “moral anthropology” is concerned with a second way of
putting empirical anthropology to use for moral philosophy: “Moral
anthropology . . . deal[s] with the subjective conditions in human nature
that help or hinder in fulfilling the laws of a metaphysics of morals. It . . .
deal[s] with the development, spreading, and strengthening of moral
principles” (6:217). As Kant explained in lectures in both ethics and
anthropology, empirical insight is needed to “make human beings ready
to follow [moral laws]” (27: 244) and even to “give duties the power of
inclinations” (25:1437, cf. 25:471-2, 734-5). The general idea here is that
one can use empirical knowledge about how human volition actually
works in order to help human beings – both oneself and others – act on
the basis of the moral law.
This task of putting empirical knowledge to use for moral
improvement is particularly important, for Kant, because of the problem
of radical evil diagnosed in chapter three. There we saw that human
beings have a self-wrought propensity to evil by virtue of which we not
only perform evil acts but also cultivate in ourselves a tendency to do
more and more evil. In response to the problem that human evil poses for
his moral philosophy in that it seems to make a good will impossible for
human beings, Kant proposes both a theological solution – God’s grace –
and a set of practical solutions. In chapter three, we emphasized two
aspects of Kant’s practical solution, his emphasis on human historicity
and on the ethical community. But both of these aspects are
supplemented by Kant’s emphasis on moral anthropology. Given our
radical evil, the best that human beings can do with respect to morality
is to “remain forever armed for battle,” “under the leadership of the good
principle, against the attacks of the evil principle” that is in him (6:93).
But this involves an unending effort to strengthen this good principle and
180 weaken the good principle in one’s empirical character, an effort that can
only be facilitated through empirical, anthropological knowledge of how
human volition actually works.
For that reason, Kant develops a moral anthropology, an
application of his empirical anthropology to the specific problem of how
to cultivate virtue in human agents. His answers to this question stretch
over several his works. Throughout his works in moral philosophy, Kant
emphasizes the practical-pedagogical importance of presenting the moral
law in all its purity (e.g. 4:390, 5: 156), and not only offers a “moral
catechism” (6:480) in his Metaphysics of Morals, but – much more
powerfully – sketches a model of how to use stories of moral heroes to
bring a “ten-year old boy . . . from approval to admiration, from that to
amazement, and finally to a lively wish that he himself could be such a
[virtuous] man” (5:155-6). Kant’s lectures on pedagogy include a long
discussion of how to cultivate, from infancy to adulthood, the moderation
and self-discipline that will provide a foundation for moral virtue. Kant
uses, for example, his empirical claims about the nature of habitformation and the role of inclinations in moral temptation to argue in
these lectures that “the child should be prevented from getting
accustomed to anything; he must not develop habits” (9:463). And Kant’s
lectures on ethics include attention to how “a person may be compelled
to duty by others” (27:521) through the careful articulation of one’s
moral responsibilities. Unsurprisingly, then, Kant’s Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View includes substantial attention to empirical
features of human beings that are particularly salient for the cultivation
of moral virtue and even ends with an impassioned reiteration of the
moral vocation of human beings as an historical and social species (see
7:330-3). Four particular examples from this work are particularly
important: politeness as an aid to virtue, passions and affects as
hindrances to virtue, character as a necessary ground for virtue, and
understanding diversity to cultivate morals properly.
Kant discusses politeness primarily in two contexts, in his
Metaphysics of Morals where he insists on a “duty to oneself as well as to
others” to engage in polite society (6:473), and in his Anthropology and
related lectures, where politeness shows up as an example of a
“permissible moral illusion” (7:151, cf. 25:502-505, 1455). In both
contexts, Kant’s emphasis is on the moral-anthropological importance of
politeness, that is, on the way in which it either strengthens or weakens
commitment to the moral law. Against philosophers like Hume and
Smith, Kant emphasizes how politeness is significantly different in kind
from truly moral action; it is a “mere external . . . which give[s] a
beautiful illusion [merely] resembling virtue” (6:473). But against
181 Rousseau, Kant insists that this merely external show of virtue can, over
time, “promote a virtuous disposition” (6:474). In his Metaphysics of
Morals, Kant’s account of precisely how politeness does this is absent,
but his Anthropology makes use of empirical facts about human beings –
such as the “tendency to willingly allow himself to be deceived” that
“nature wisely implanted” in human beings – to show how engaging in
shows of virtue can, over time, help a person combat the evil principle
within them and cultivate genuine virtue.139
While politeness is an aid to moral character, passions and affects
are the prime examples of moral hindrances in Kant’s Anthropology. As
we saw in the last chapter, Kant treats affects and passions as
“illness[es] of mind” (7:251), and both represent degrees of emotional
agitation that rise to the level where one is incapable of reflecting on
one’s goals. Both affects and passions preclude acting from a good will,
since the reflection necessary to be motivated by the moral law is absent,
but the way in which they preclude the good will is different. Affects are
an extreme and passing form of weak or frail will, where one is simply
overcome by feeling and engages in no reflection at all. Sudden rage or
shock fall into this category. Fortunately, affects are passing, and one
afflicted by affect can, during cool, calm hours, take steps to prevent
further outbursts. Those afflicted by passions akin to depraved wills but
focused, not on their own happiness overall, but solely on a single end.
Vengeful hatred and the lust for power are among the passions. Kant
uses his taxonomy of mental faculties – especially the distinction
between feeling and desire – and his overall empirical account of human
action to explain not only the difference between these mental illness but
also why passions are not only “incurable because the sick person does
not want to be cured” (7:266) but also, and in contrast to affects,
“properly evil” (6:408).
Throughout his lectures and in his published Anthropology, Kant
follows his discussion of affects and passions with an account of
“character” that pulls together his empirical treatment of character with
his moral philosophy. Character – the tendency to act in accordance with
consistent principles – is the surest antidote to passions, affects, and
even the ordinary human emotional fluctuations that can be so
problematic to moral life. Thus Kant’s Anthropology emphasizes the
importance of character for living a good life. Here it is important to recall
that Kant’s empirical psychology emphasizes “character” as the proper
expression of the higher faculty of desire, but also notes that most
individuals have a “bad” or “flawed” character that fails to fully regulate
139
For a detailed discussion of politeness in Kant, see Frierson 2005.
182 itself by consistent principles. Moreover, recall that radical evil in Kant’s
Religion is not diabolical – a rebelling against morality as such – nor even
primarily depraved – a consistent preferring of happiness to morality –
but rather an impurity or frailness that manifests itself in a tendency to
give in to sufficiently strong temptations. For Kant, character – the
“property of the will by which the subject binds himself to definite
practical principles” (7:292) – is necessary in order to have a will that is
stably and purely bound to the moral law as its principle. Thus Kant’s
Anthropology devotes considerable attention to cataloging measures that
one can take to cultivate genuine character.140
In the course of his discussions of individual character – the sort
so prominent in his empirical theory of the higher faculty of desire – Kant
also discusses other sorts of “character,” including the character of
different nations and races, and various “influences on character,”
including temperament. In other words, Kant’s moral anthropology,
especially when it comes to the matter of character, absorbs his interest
in diversity. And in this context, his treatments of diversity take on a
special sort of moral importance. In particular, Kant often emphasizes
human differences as a way of highlighting the very different sorts of
“struggles against the evil principle” that different people will have. In
describing the sanguine as “not . . . evil . . . but . . . a sinner hard to
convert [because] he regrets . . . much but quickly forgets this regret”
(7:288) or the phlegmatic as one who “proceeds from principles” even
when lacking “wisdom” (7:290), Kant highlights different emphases for
moral cultivation in these two sorts of people. And Kant’s claims that
French “vivacity is not sufficiently kept in check by considered
principles” (7:313) or that Germans “have a tendency to imitation . . .[,] a
140
Of course, nothing in Kant’s anthropology dictates empirical causes of a good will since a good will
cannot be empirically caused. But Kant does lay out empirical causes of and practical advice for cultivating
character, he highlights particular moral challenges that will be faced by those of varying temperaments
and national origin, and he describes the resources for progress in the species as a whole. Because all of
these considerations are empirical, they cannot ultimately determine whether one’s free, noumenal choice is
for good or evil. But a person who recognizes radical evil and earnestly seeks every resource to combat the
“evil principle” within her knows that merely choosing rightly in a particular case is insufficient for moral
progress. For radically evil human beings, virtue requires taking one’s life as a whole to be a battlefield
between one’s evil tendencies to self-deceptive moral complacency and one’s moral struggle to revolt
against those tendencies. Knowing that one’s friendliness or even principled actions are merely matters of
temperament can help one focus on those areas of life that require greater moral attention (being more
principled if one is naturally sanguine, or being less imitative if one is naturally phlegmatic). And given
how lack of character leads to moral failings, knowledge of how to cultivate character, properly used, can
arm one against the evils of frailty and impurity of will. Even if moral anthropology does not teach one
how to effect a noumenal revolution against radical evil in one’s will, it gives one the tools to effectively
live out that revolution in a life of constant progress towards greater and greater conformity to the demands
of the moral law. (For more discussion of these points, see Frierson 2003.)
183 mania for punctiliousness and . . . a need for methodical division . . .
[that] reveals the limitation of [their] innate talent” (7:318-9) show that
these two nations face different challenges in the cultivation of (moral)
character (7:293). Kant’s pragmatic attention to empirical differences
between human being often focuses on just those “subjective conditions”
relevant for moral anthropology.
2. Pragmatic Anthropology
Pragmatic anthropology is not limited to merely moral anthropology
but encompasses “everything that pertains to the practical” (10:146).141
And while Kant’s emphasis on the good will in his moral writings might
lead some to think that, for Kant, there is little more to life than doing
one’s duty, in fact Kant is adamant that human lives, to be really good
lives, must include not only duty but also happiness and the increasing
perfection of the whole range of predispositions with which nature has
gifted us. Strikingly, in fact, while moral anthropology is an important
part of Kant’s pragmatic anthropology, Kant consistently downplays the
moral importance of his anthropological claims. In the passage where
Kant describes, for example, the ways an inclination like idleness morally
corrupts by making one think that “when one does nothing at all . . . he
can do nothing evil” (7:152), his emphasis is on the fact that this idleness
is the cause of “boredom,” a feeling of extreme dissatisfaction with
oneself and one’s life (7:151). Similarly, politeness is important not
merely for moral ends but for the sheer pleasure of polite company.
Affects and passions are dangerous, and character beneficial, not merely
for virtue but for happiness as well. Kant even discusses how an “evil
character” can inspire “admiration” (7:293) and his main examples of the
dangers of affects and passions involve the ways in which these prevent
people from reflecting on “sum of all feelings of pleasure” (7:254) or the
“sum of all inclinations” (7:265). And Kant’s account of diverse national
characters is oriented towards discerning “what each can expect from the
other and how each could use the other to his own advantage” (7:312).
Anthropology is full of applications of Kant’s empirical anthropology
towards helping human beings cultivate skills and capacities or become
happier through better knowledge of human nature (both one’s own and
those of others). For the purpose of this chapter, four examples of this
141
In his writings on moral philosophy, Kant even associates the “pragmatic” with guidelines aimed solely
towards happiness (see 4:416-7), but we have already seen that “pragmatic anthropology” includes
specifically moral anthropology as well as advice that is more “pragmatic” in this narrower, hedonic sense.
184 non-moral “pragmatic” anthropology suffice: memory, distraction, “the
highest physical pleasure,” and “the highest ethico-physical good.”
Kant’s discussions of memory and distraction highlight the
application of empirical anthropology to the perfection of capacities that
are neither moral nor an obvious part of human happiness.142 With
respect to memory, Kant objects to those who propose “impressing
certain ideas on the memory by association with correlative ideas that in
themselves . . . have no relationship at all with each other” on the
grounds that “in order to grasp something in the memory more easily, we
inconvenience it with still more correlative ideas,” which “is absurd”
(7:183). Instead, Kant suggests, “Judicious memorizing is nothing other
than memorizing, in thought, a table of the divisions of a system (for
example, that of Linnaeus) where, if one should forget something, one
can find it again through the enumeration of the parts that one has
retained” (7:184). Kant adds, of course, various further mnemonic
“tricks” such as “maxims in verse, since the rhythm has a regular
syllabic stress that is a great advantage to the mechanism of memory”
(7:184). Distraction, which Kant warns can lead to “forgetfulness” (7:185)
or even “dementia” (7:207) if overused, can be effectively used as a sort of
cleansing agent for the mind:
[O]ne can also distract oneself, that is, create a diversion for one’s
involuntary reproductive power of imagination, as, for example, when
the clergyman has delivered his memorized sermon and wants to
prevent it from echoing in his head afterwards. This is a necessary
and in part artificial precautionary procedure for our mental health.
Continuous reflection on one and the same object leaves behind it a
reverberation, so to speak (as when one and the very same piece of
dance music that went on for a long time is still hummed by those
returning from a festivity, or when children repeat incessantly one
and the same of their kind of bon mot, especially when it has a
rhythmic sound). Such a reverberation . . . molests the mind, and it
can only be stopped by distraction and by applying attention to other
objects; for example, reading newspapers. (7:207)
142
These examples also elegantly show the interplay of empirical-causal description with
pragmatic purposes. In the case of distraction, for instance, Kant assumes that people are
free in the sense that he directs this advice to someone who he takes to be capable of
acting upon it. But the advice is based on a picture of human cognition that is determinist
in the sense that it traces the causes of various changes in one’s cognitions, from the way
in which continuous reflection on a single object causes “reverberation” to the ways that
one can undo this reverberation by, for instance, reading newspapers.
185 While both good memory and the “mental health” referred to here may be
helpful for happiness and/or virtue, Kant’s emphases in these passages
is on putting empirical knowledge of human beings to use for the
“pragmatic” purpose of perfecting cognitive powers as such, regardless of
any moral or hedonic purposes to which these might be put.
From his long and detailed “pragmatic” discussion of cognitive
faculty (which takes up more than half of his published Anthropology),
Kant turns to the faculties of feeling and desire, and there devotes
attention to “pragmatic” advice about how to make human beings happy.
Those familiar with Kant’s moral philosophy may recall his periodic
despair about the possibility of “imperative of prudence” even “presenting
actions . . . as practically necessary,” even merely necessary for
happiness (4:418, cf. 5:36).
[T]he concept of happiness is such an indeterminate concept that,
although every human being wishes to attain this, he can still never
say determinately and consistently with himself what he really wishes
and wills. The cause of this is that all of the elements that belong to
happiness are without exception empirical, that is, they must be
borrowed from experience . . . Now it is impossible for the most
insightful . . . finite being to frame for himself a determinate concept
of what he really wills here. If he wills riches, how much anxiety,
envy, and intrigue might he not bring upon himself . . . If he wills a
great deal of cognition and insight, that might become only an eye all
the more acute to show him . . . ills that are now concealed . . . If he
wills a long life, who will guarantee him that it would not be a long
misery? (4:418)
One might not expect a philosopher who so rails against the possibility of
framing a determinate concept of happiness to offer empirically-rooted
rules of prudence, but Kant does just this. His Anthropology lays out a
general discussion of the nature of pleasure and pain, noting in
particular that given the particular “animal life” that humans share,
“pain must always precede every enjoyment” and “no enjoyment can
immediately follow another” (7:231).143 And Kant gives detailed analyses
of inclinations, not primarily to show their moral dangers but to reveal
how they are often self-defeating even from the standpoint of human
happiness. Following Rousseau, Kant emphasizes that imagination and
reason give humans capacities to generate desires that do not contribute
143
For a detailed discussion of the shifts in Kant’s views that led him to these claims, see Shell 2003.
186 to lasting happiness. Even while discussing the cognitive faculty, Kant
emphasizes implications of cognitive powers for happiness. For example,
after distinguishing “attention” from “abstraction,” Kant notes, “Many
human beings are unhappy because they cannot abstract. The suitor
could make a good marriage if only he could overlook a wart on his
beloved’s face, or a gap between her teeth . . . But this faculty of
abstraction is a strength of mind that can only be acquired through
practice” (7:131-2). Kant not only diagnoses a source of unhappiness but
suggests a means for cultivating the cognitive power to have a happier
life. The peak of his emphasis on happiness comes, however, at the of the
first part of his Anthropology, where Kant offers specific accounts of “the
highest physical good” and “the highest moral-physical good,” both of
which, despite their use of the terms “good” and “moral,” are suggestions
for how to best be happy given our human nature.
The “highest physical good” is that “greatest sensuous enjoyment .
. . not accompanied by any admixture of loathing at all” found in “resting
after work” (7:276). Kant identifies psychological features of human
beings that interfere with this enjoyment, especially “laziness” (“the
propensity to rest without having first worked” (7:276)) and he uses his
account to explain phenomena as diverse as the appeal of “a game,”
which is “the best distraction and relaxation after a long intellectual
exertion,” the tendency of “a love story [to] always end with the wedding,”
and the fact that “boredom will often affect us in such a manner that we
feel driven to so something harmful to ourselves rather than nothing at
all” (7:232-3). The “highest moral-physical good” is the way to unify “good
living with virtue in social intercourse,” and it is found, for Kant, in “a
good meal in good company” (7:277-8). Kant spends five full pages
(7:277-82) detailing the importance of such dinner parties and how they
should be conducted, including advice about the number of guests (ten),
the order of conversation (first narration, then arguing, and finally
jesting), and even the proper roles of “small . . . attacks on the [female]
sex” (acceptable as long as they are “not shameful”) and dinner music
(“the most tasteless absurdity that revelry ever contrived”).144 Such
dinner parties please by virtue of humans’ innate sociability, and they
even channel our unsociability into conversation and “dispute . . . which
stirs up the appetite” but which, because it avoids excessive seriousness,
is consistent with “mutual respect and benevolence” (7:280-1). Unlike
vain luxury and chasing after superiority over others, “the art of good
living” is a skillfulness of choice in social enjoyment, which . . . mak[es]
pleasure mutually beneficial, and is calculated to last” (7:250). The end
144
For a detailed discussion of Kant’s account of dinner parties, see Cohen 2008.
187 result is social enjoyment consisting of a “stimulating play of thoughts”
that “promotes sociability” and thereby “dresses virtue to advantage”
(7:279-82). While seemingly “insignificant . . . compare[d] to pure moral
laws,” the graces of “social good living” are not only enjoyable in
themselves but also serve virtue by preventing it from becoming distorted
into a cold “mortification of the flesh” (7:282), and the social interactions
of a well-run dinner party help pave the way for polite and enjoyable
moral exhortations amongst members of an ethical commonwealth. In
the end, while the specifics of these discussions is important, far more
important is the way that Anthropology enriches the austere conception
of human life one might find in Kant’s transcendental anthropology with
details that are neither moral, nor epistemic, nor aesthetic.
But why does Kant devote so much attention to how human beings
can improve non-moral capacities and become happier? In part, one
might appeal to moral incentives even here. As we noted at the beginning
of the last section, one way in which one might use empirical
anthropology is to specific the duties required by pure moral philosophy.
And Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals explains that there are two “ends that
are also duties . . .[:] one’s own perfection and the happiness of others”
(6:386). Learning what makes people genuinely happy and what best
facilitates the perfection of all “his natural powers . . . of spirit, mind, and
body” (6:444) specifies, in empirically-informed and concrete ways, what
one ought to do to work towards these two obligatory ends.
But Kant also emphasizes that human beings “unavoidably want”
their own happiness (6:386, cf. 4:418, 5:25), and in Religion, Kant
ascribes humans’ pursuit of happiness to “predispositions to animality . .
. [and] humanity” that are, ultimately, parts of our more general
“predisposition to good” (6:26). Even the perfection of our capacities – on
which the majority of Anthropology focuses – is for Kant “a pragmatic
purpose” (6:444) required because “these capacities “serve [one] and are
given . . . for all sorts of possible purposes” (4:423). In contrast not only
to monkish moralists who decry base animal desires for food and sex but
even to moralists like Rousseau who decry the social inclinations that
come from comparing ourselves with others, Kant endorses as good a
wide range of human inclinations – for food, sex, social life, fine wine,
good conversation, and so on. While not “good without limitation” (4:
393), these other important even if “limited” goods in human life should
be pursued as well as possible. So an important part of pragmatic
anthropology is discerning, through careful empirical investigation, what
sorts of activities best satisfy and delight human beings over the long
term. The despair over rules of prudence that Kant seemed to express in
his Groundwork is mitigated by a very serious effort throughout his
188 Anthropology to provide, practical advice that is as effective as any
empirical investigation can be at providing for improvement and personal
as well as social well-being.
3. Empirical, transcendental, and pragmatic anthropology
So far, this chapter has focused on various details of Kant’s
pragmatic anthropology, but it is finally time to ask how Kant saw his
pragmatic anthropology in relation to his empirical and transcendental
anthropologies. In other words, it is time to answer Kant’s question –
“What is the human being?” in an integrated way. As we have seen in
this book, throughout his life Kant distinguished what I have called
“transcendental” from “empirical” anthropology, particularly insisting
that the latter not corrupt the former. For Kant, it is essential to work
out normative demands a priori and from-within and to keep this
investigation distinct from empirical claims about human beings. But
Kant’s pragmatic anthropology brings the two sorts of investigation
together, which might seem to undermine both projects since it risks
undermining empirical investigation with normative prejudices and
corrupting transcendental theorizing with empirical description. Kant’s
explanations of what pragmatic anthropology consists in seem to
exacerbate this tension. Kant refers to it as at once “knowledge of the
world” that can even be broadened by “travel” (7:119-20) and “the
investigation of what [the human being] as a free-acting being makes of
himself, or can and should make of himself (7:119), seemingly pulling
together empirical and transcendental anthropology in the most
incoherent of ways. In fact, however, Kant’s pragmatic anthropology
offers a coherent and plausible model for how empirical and
transcendental anthropologies should be integrated, and thus a model
for what a complete “doctrine of the knowledge of the human being”
(7:119) might look like.
Kant’s claim that pragmatic anthropology attends to “what [the
human being] as a free-acting being makes . . . or can and should make
of himself” (7:119) comes in the context of his distinction between his
own “pragmatic” anthropology from the “physiological” anthropology of
his contemporary Ernst Platner. A merely physiological anthropology
emphasizes “what nature makes of the human being” by examining
neurophysiological bases of mental powers, so it “must admit that in this
play of his representations he is a mere observer and must let nature run
its course, for he does not understand how to put [these
neurophysiological bases] to use for his purposes” (7:119). In contrast,
189 the pragmatic anthropologist focuses on “knowledge of the human being”
with “the goal of applying this acquired knowledge . . . to . . . the human
being because the human being is his own final end” (7:119). Similarly,
in a handwritten personal note, Kant describes his approach to
anthropology saying, “the historical kind of teaching is pragmatic, when
it . . . is not merely for the school, but also for the world or ethics” (16:
804). And in his lectures, he emphasizes that “anthropology is . . .
indispensable and manages great uses” (25:1437). The general point of
all these remarks is that Kant’s anthropology is meant to be pragmatic in
the sense of practical rather than theoretical, something that not only
gives knowledge about human beings, but that gives knowledge that one
can put to use.
Importantly, Kant’s claim that pragmatic anthropology “concerns .
. . the investigation of what he as a free-acting being makes of himself, or
can and should make of himself” should not be taken to imply that
pragmatic anthropology takes the free subject of transcendental
anthropology as its primary topic of investigation. In the rest of Kant’s
Anthropology, not only through his stated methodology (7:120-22) but in
his actual practice, the information about human beings that makes up
the content of pragmatic anthropology is empirical.145 In an important
sense, then, pragmatic anthropology has no distinctive content of its
own. Elsewhere, Kant even seems to deny the possibility of distinctively
pragmatic anthropology at all:
[Although one might offer] practical precepts, which concern the
voluntary production of a certain state of mind in us (e.g. that of the
stimulation or restraint of the imagination . . .)[, t]here is no practical
[anthropology]146 as a special part of the philosophy of human
nature. For the principles of the possibility of its state by means of
art must be borrowed from those of the possibility of our
determinations from the constitution of our nature and, although the
former consist of practical propositions, still they do not constitute a
practical part of empirical psychology, because they do not have any
special principles, but merely belong among its scholia. In general,
145
For a detailed defense of this claim, see Frierson 2003. It is worth noting, of course, that even Kant’s
empirical accounts of human beings treat them as free beings in the sense that humans have a faculty of
desire capable of acting for the sake of ends and a higher faculty of desire capable of acting from
principles. Consistent with his empirical anthropology, Kant’s pragmatic anthropology treats human beings
as “free” in that sense (cf. Cohen 2009). But what makes the anthropology pragmatic is not the way
humans are treated teleologically-biologically rather than mechanically, but the fact that Kant emphasizes
those aspects of human nature that free human beings can use.
146
Although he says “psychology” here, his use of the term psychology in this context corresponds to what
I have been calling “empirical anthropology.”
190 practical propositions . . . always belong to the knowledge of nature
and to the theoretical part of philosophy. (20:199)
The denial in passage of a distinctive, practical anthropology might seem
to preclude any Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View at all. But in
fact, the passage merely clarifies the logical status of such anthropology.
Technically, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View is a subset of
Kant’s empirical anthropology, a series of “scholia” that apply that
empirical anthropology to specific human ends. But precisely because
pragmatic anthropology is oriented towards ends, it refrains from
discussing merely theoretical aspects of human nature, claims about
human beings that cannot be put to any use.
In what sense, then, is pragmatic anthropology concerned with a
free-acting human being? Put simply, pragmatic anthropology is
knowledge of human beings addressed to human agents who can make
use of such knowledge for accomplishing their (freely-chosen) goals. Kant
uses the case of memory to explain that what makes an anthropologist
pragmatic is that he “uses perceptions concerning what has been found
to hinder or stimulate memory in order to enlarge it or make it agile”
rather than dwelling over purely theoretical claims about memory that
are “a pure waste of time” (7:119). And so when he turns to discuss
memory in detail in Anthropology, Kant uses his empirical anthropology
to discern the best mnemonic strategies, rather than merely explaining
the “nature” of memory as such. This strategy is even clearer in the
discussion of distraction cited in the previous section. Recall that Kant
recommends distracting oneself to avoid reverberation in imagination
(7:207). Throughout his discussion, Kant assumes that people are free in
the sense that he directs this advice to someone capable of acting upon
it. But the advice is based on a picture of human cognition that is
strongly determinist in that it traces causes of changes in cognitions,
from the way continuous reflection on a single object causes
“reverberation” to the ways that one can undo this reverberation by, for
instance, reading newspapers. Similarly, Kant’s accounts of how
politeness cultivates good character, the nature of affects and passions,
and even the general role of character in action are all empiricalanthropological claims, but ones that can be put to use. Kant addresses
free agents, teaching empirical facts about human nature in order to
show what free human beings can make of themselves, and how.
But pragmatic anthropology is not merely empirical anthropology
that can be put to use. Kant also, implicitly if not explicitly, recommends
how one should put one’s empirical knowledge to use. Pragmatic
anthropology teaches both what human beings can make of themselves
191 and what they should make of themselves. And these norms cannot be
justified merely empirically but depend upon the from-within perspective
that is the focus of Kant’s transcendental anthropology. The molestation
of mind that calls for distraction appears only from-within, in one’s
response to one’s cognitive state. And Kant’s discussion of cognition even
ends with a series of “unalterable commands” that “lead to wisdom,”
including the need “to think for oneself” and “Always to think
consistently” (7:228) and with an exhortation, fundamental to the
autonomy at the core of Kant’s transcendental anthropology, to “exit
from his self-incurred immaturity,” to “venture to advance, though still
shakily, with his own feet on the ground of experience” (7:229). By
providing free human thinkers with empirical knowledge about how
cognition works, Kant can cultivate the autonomy of thought that is a
normative requirement of thinking, evident from-within. Similarly, as we
saw in section one above, Kant’s pragmatic anthropology puts empirical
anthropology to use to cultivate good character in human beings. By
understanding the aspects of our natures that tempt and lead us astray
and by understanding how to cultivate character, we can better engage
in the struggle towards the good will that Kant’s transcendental
anthropology of desire shows, from-within, to be the only thing good
without limitation. Pragmatic anthropology thus unifies transcendental
with empirical anthropology; transcendental analysis provides the a
priori normative principles for our human powers, and empirical
anthropology shows how to cultivate powers that conform to those
norms.
One aspect of Kant’s pragmatic anthropology, however, goes
beyond the mere application of empirically-given means to
transcendentally-given ends. Kant’s discussions of happiness, which play
a particularly important role in his “pragmatic” anthropology, make use
of empirical anthropology to specify the best ends for human beings.
Happiness is a universal end, one that we can observe all humans
seeking and that we can discover, from-within, to be a naturally
necessary end for ourselves. But happiness is “such an indeterminate
concept” (4:418) that it requires empirical content to be action-guiding at
all. Whereas there can be a priori cognitive and moral principles, the best
that humans can do regarding the pursuit of happiness is to carefully
study, through introspection as well as the investigation of others, what
actually gives us the most pleasure over the long term.147 In that sense,
the pursuit of happiness is the special domain of pragmatic
anthropology, the domain within which pragmatic anthropology specifies
147
This should not be taken to deny that there can be an a priori investigation of pleasure, as chapter one
makes clear. But this investigation only focuses on aesthetic – that is, non-action-guiding – pleasure.
192 not only means but also – because “happiness” is so indeterminate – the
true nature of the end itself. Thus it is no surprise that Kant often uses
the term “pragmatic” to refer specifically to what is to one’s own
advantage, what is conducive to one’s own happiness (see, e.g., 4:416).
There is one further important aspect of Kant’s “pragmatic”
anthropology that has not yet received sufficient attention. So far, this
chapter focused on the importance of pragmatic anthropology for
fostering one’s own capacities, happiness, and virtue. But for Kant, one
of the primary reasons for developing a pragmatic anthropology is to
learn how others respond to various empirical conditions in order to
appropriately navigate within a world defined largely by other people.
Thus Kant claims “all pragmatic instruction is instruction in prudence
[Klugheits Lehren]” (25:471, see too 25:1436), in Groundwork, identifies
“prudence” and “worldly wisdom” with “the skill of someone in
influencing others so as to use them for his own purposes” (4: 416n.),
and in Anthropology itself, defines the “pragmatic predisposition” as the
ability “to use other human beings skillfully for his purposes” (7:322).
Thus in laying out characteristics of different nationalities, Kant claims,
“In an anthropology from a pragmatic point of view, . . . the only thing
that matters to us is to present the character of [each] . . . in some
examples, and, as far as possible, systematically; which makes it
possible to judge what each can expect from the other and how each
could use the other to his own advantage. (7:312, emphasis added). By
understanding human nature, one not only knows how to influence
oneself in order to improve memory, attain happiness, or cultivate
character; one also knows or can quickly assess the strengths and
weaknesses of others in order to influence their development and
behavior.
This way of approaching others can sound sinister when Kant
speaks of “using” others “to one’s own advantage,” but Kant’s point is
more benign, and, properly understood, even an affirmation of human
dignity. The fact is that human beings have various psychological
characteristics that affect how we respond to each other. Regardless of
how free one might be from-within, there are empirically-knowable
tendencies in human nature that enable prediction of how different
people respond to situations of various kinds. One might put this
knowledge to use to manipulate others as mere means to one’s ends. But
one might also put this knowledge to use in order to best achieve one’s
ends without treating others as mere means. If I know that the sanguine
“attributes a great importance to each thing for the moment, and the
next moment may not give it another thought” (7:287-8) while the
melancholy “finds cause for concern everywhere” (7:288), I know to treat
193 social commitments with these two types of people differently. If I have
agreed to go to a movie with someone but feel like going to a concert
instead, I will suggest this change to my sanguine friends (who are likely
to be thrilled by my spontaneity, and in any case will tell me if they still
want to go to the movie) but not to my melancholic ones (who are likely
to silently take offense while reluctantly granting assent to the change of
plans). Knowing how others are affected by empirical conditions can
make me more respectful of their humanity, rather than less. Thus Kant
says to his students,
We must trouble ourselves to shape the ways of thinking and powers
of those with whom we have to act, so that we are neither too hard
nor too offensive. So we are taught anthropology, which shows us
how we can use people for our ends. (25:1436)
One uses anthropological knowledge, rather than manipulation or force,
in order to accomplish one’s ends in relation to others while still avoiding
“offense” against their humanity.
Even this level of interest in others, of course, might still focus
merely on not offending others while pursuing “one’s own advantage.”
But Kant makes clear throughout his lectures on anthropology, and at
the end of his published Anthropology, that his ambitions with respect to
others are even higher. In one lecture, Kant laments that “the reason
that morals and preaching that are full of admonitions . . . have little
effect is the lack of knowledge of man” (25:471-72, cf. 27:358). In
another, he explains:
Anthropology is . . . indispensable and manages great uses.
1. In pedagogy.
2. With respect to the influence that we can have on others.
Especially commanders, who with a proper knowledge of man can get
total opposites to work [together], which otherwise can be set right
only through violence.
3. With respect to the influences on morals and religion, that through
this knowledge one can give these duties the power of inclinations.
(25: 1437)
And Kant’s published Anthropology ends with an inspiring allusion back
to the discussion of radical evil and the ethical commonwealth that Kant
discussed in his Religion:
194 [Anthropology] presents the human species not as evil, but as a
species of rational beings that strives among obstacles to rise out of
evil in constant progress toward the good. In this its volition is
generally good, but achievement is difficult because one cannot
expect to reach the goal by the free agreement of individuals, but only
by a progressive organization of citizens of the earth into and toward
the species as a system that is cosmopolitically united. (7:333)
These three passages suggest a crucial moral function of pragmatic
anthropology. Learning how other people are affected by empirical
influences is crucial for “morals and preaching,” “education . . . [and]
influences on morals,” and ultimately “a progressive organization of
citizens are earth.” In these ways, we can see pragmatic anthropology as
the science needed in order to actively promote an ethical commonwealth
on earth. Thus it is unsurprising that at the outset of Kant’s
Anthropology, he distinguishes several forms of “egoism” wherein one
treats oneself as the ultimate authority in matters of truth, taste, or
morals as hindrances to human excellence in these areas, and exhorts
his readers to “the way of thinking in which one is not concerned with
oneself as the whole world, but rather regards and conducts oneself as a
mere citizen of the world” (7:130).
4. Conclusion
In the end, Kant’s Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
does, in a sense, provide his answer to the question “What is the human
being?” For Kant, the question is a pressing practical one, a question
about humans’ place in the universe, about who we are but also,
crucially, about what we can and should make of ourselves. Many
aspects of Kant’s answer to this question come in his transcendental
anthropology. There he lays out the norms that should govern our
cognition, feelings, and volitions; he shows the conditions of possibility of
being bound by these norms; and he develops his metaphysical account
of humans’ free and finite natures. Many aspects of Kant’s answer show
up in his empirical anthropology, where he provides detailed descriptions
of how human beings actually think, feel, and choose. But Kant’s
pragmatic anthropology provides Kant’s way of integrating these other
two sets of answers into a science that would help human beings better
satisfy norms of cognition, feeling, and volition and live happier, more
virtuous, and more beneficially-social lives.
195 This model of pragmatic anthropology helps complete Kant’s
accounts of human evil and human history, showing what we can do
here and now, given the natures that we actually have, to make our
world a better place. Moreover, as Kant’s anthropology makes clear,
human beings get into moral trouble both by prioritizing non-moral
incentives over moral ones, and simply by being inconsistent, foolish,
excessively passionate, and inept. The second problem can rise to the
level of a genuinely moral problem, especially given our evil tendency to
cultivate ineptness to excuse our failings. But it is also just a problem for
living good lives. And Kant’s pragmatic anthropology provides numerous
specific suggestions for overcoming the general problems that make us
both vicious and miserable. This approach also puts Kant’s accounts of
diversity in a new light, showing how they are meant to provide tools to
improve humanity in all its forms, rather than excuses for dismissing or
exploiting others.
This model of pragmatic anthropology also provides a useful model
for how philosophical investigation of human nature might interact with
human sciences today. While I discuss this in more detail in succeeding
chapters, Kant’s general model is to use transcendental philosophy to
articulate and provide conditions of possibility for the norms governing
human life and to use the findings of empirical sciences both to show the
best ways of cultivating human beings who can achieve those norms and
to discern and specify the one human end that is genuinely empirical:
our pursuit of happiness. In the end, the answer to the question “What is
the human being?” will be provided by philosophical accounts of the
from-within, norm-governed perspectives of free and finite beings like us
engaged in thinking, feeling, and choosing, along with empirical-scientific
accounts of the characteristics and causal laws governing homo sapiens,
combined into pragmatic knowledge that helps us become betterfunctioning, happier, more virtuous citizens of the world.
196 Chapter 6: The Immediate Reception of Kant’s Anthropology
Kant had high hopes for his philosophy of the human being. He
claimed that his Critiques, especially the Critique of Pure Reason,
“completely specified [reason’s] questions according to principles, and,
after discovering the point where reason has misunderstood itself, . . .
resolved them to reason’s complete satisfaction” (Axii). He wrote of his
course in anthropology that he would make this “very pleasant empirical
study” into “a proper academic discipline” that could, “distinct from all
other learning, . . . be called knowledge of the world” (10:146). Kant’s
account of God, immortality, and human evil would, he hoped, put
religion “within the boundaries of reason alone.” But while Kant did
inaugurate a Copernican turn in philosophy, this turn did not take the
form he expected. At almost every step of the way, its reception was
disrupted in unanticipated ways. While Kant had hoped and expected
that his transcendental philosophy would be sympathetically reviewed by
prominent rationalist philosophers such as Moses Mendelssohn, the first
reviews of the Critique of Pure Reason were dominated by empiricists
and highly negative. Before discussion of Kant’s philosophy could reach
its natural conclusion, it was overtaken by a controversy about Lessing
that displaced the Critique’s detailed nuances in favor its “spirit.” In this
context, a young upstart philosopher named Karl Leonhard Reinhold
(1757-1823) emerged as the spokesman and heir of Kant’s philosophy –
this even while Kant was still publishing major works of his own.
Through Reinhold’s influence, the reception of Kant’s philosophy was
driven along two radically different lines. German Romantics reacted
against Reinhold’s attempt to transform Kant’s Critical philosophy into a
foundationalist metaphysics by emphasizing inscrutability and
particularity in a way that privileged artistic expression over
philosophical system-building. German Idealists – Fichte, Schelling, and
Hegel – took almost the opposite approach, building massive
philosophical systems to fill Kant’s gaps and correct his errors.
Meanwhile Kant’s empirical and pragmatic anthropology was largely
ignored. By the time Kant published his Anthropology from a Pragmatic
Point of View in 1798, the work barely attracted attention from a
philosophical community that was preoccupied with the latest works by
Reinhold, Fichte, and the early German Romantics.148 By the time Kant
died six years later, Schelling and Hegel were emerging as the most
148
In 1798, the year Kant published his Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, Reinhold published
his Fundamental Concepts and Principles of Ethics, Fichte published An Attempt at a New Presentation of
the Wissenschaftslehre, the Early Romantic Journal The Athenaeum was founded, and Schelling published
On the World Soul.
197 important philosophers in Germany, and while both were heavily
influenced by Reinhold and Fichte, they largely left Kant’s own
philosophy behind.
I. Early Reception and the Emergence of German Idealism
After Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason was published in 1781, its
first review (by Johann Feder and Christian Garve, in 1782) suggested
that Kant was merely a new Berkeley who “transforms the world and
ourselves into representations” (Sassen 2000:53).149 Succeeding years
brought a vibrant debate about Kant’s philosophy, mostly characterized
by empiricist criticisms of his philosophy and more-or-less Kantian
responses to those criticisms. There were five key criticisms articulated
during these early years. First, empiricists argued that Kant’s
Copernican turn implies an unacceptable Subjectivism, reducing all of
our knowledge to mere knowledge of our own representations and
precluding any real connection to an objective world. As one reviewer put
it, Kantian sensibility “does not present the objective world at all” but is
“like a glass whose exterior has an entirely foreign painting glued to it”
(Pistorius 1786:115, in Sassen 2000: 101). Second, they argued that
Kant has a Self-Reference Problem. If all that one knows is how things
appear, and especially if self-knowledge is only knowledge of oneself as
appearance, then “according to the author’s system, appearance [cannot]
be possible at all [since] that through which all appearing becomes
possible (which must, accordingly, be presupposed prior to all
appearances . . .) is supposed to be appearance” (Pistorius 1786:93, in
Sassen 2000: 94). Put another way, the conditions of possibility of
experience, and especially the transcendentally unified “I” that is the
subject of experience, cannot themselves be mere appearances. So Kant
must be able to know something that goes beyond mere appearances,
since he makes claims about the “I” that experiences those appearances.
Third, empiricists raised the problem of the Neglected Alternative. Even if
Kant can show that human beings necessarily impose sensory and
cognitive structures on our experience of the world, nothing prevents the
world itself from conforming to these categories. In fact, it seems
reasonable to think that human beings have the cognitive capacities that
we do precisely because these conform to the way that the world actually
is. Fourth, empiricists raised a Problem of Affection. As F. H. Jacobi put
it, “without the presupposition [of things in themselves], I could not find
149
George Berkeley (1685-1753) was an Irish philosopher whose “idealism” advocated the view that “to be
is to be perceived,” that is, that only perceptions (and perceivers) are real.
198 my way into the system, whereas with it I could not stay there” (Sassen
2000: 173). Kant’s account of sensibility as a passive faculty seems to
depend upon things-in-themselves affecting sensibility, but Kant’s
limitations on knowledge make it “if not altogether impossible, at least
quite difficult, to think things in themselves as the possible foundation or
substratum of appearances” (Pistorius 1786:108, in Sassen 2000: 100).
For Kant, the category of causation seems applicable only to appearances
and thus not at all to the relationship between things-in-themselves and
the sensibility that these things supposedly affect. Finally, more
linguistically- and historically-inclined empiricists such as Hamann and
Herder suggested that rather than Kant’s Copernican turn, something
more like a Linguistic Turn was needed. Hamann critiques the “purism of
pure reason,” Kant’s attempt to free reason from “tradition and custom”
and from “language, the only, first, and last organon and criterion of
reason” (Hamann 1800, in Schmidt 1996:155). He suggests that “space
and time have made themselves universal and necessary” through the
importance of “sounds and letters,” the “true aesthetic elements of
human knowledge” that have their roots in “the oldest language . . .
music, and . . . the oldest writing . . . painting and drawing” (Hamann
1800, in Schmidt 1996:156-7). Rather than space and time being
fundamental a priori structures of human cognition, they reflect only the
most general elements of human language. Hamann mocks the “Homer
of pure reason” (Kant) as having “dreamed that the universal character of
a philosophical language . . . is already found” (Hamann 1800, in
Schmidt 1996:158).
These criticisms highlight several features of the early reception of
Kant’s transcendental anthropology. First, reviews focused on the
epistemic and metaphysical implications of Kant’s view, remaining
faithful to the sense in which Kant’s first Critique emphasized the
conditions of human knowing. Second and most importantly, these early
reviews refused to endorse Kant’s Copernican turn. Rather than seeing
the world of experience as largely a product of the particular structures
of human cognitive powers, early reviews of Kant’s work insisted that
cognition reflects rather than constructs the world it experiences.
Because of this refusal to accept Kant’s Copernican turn, early reviews
largely failed to grasp the force of Kant’s transcendental anthropology.
The Self-Reference Problem, the Problem of Affection, and arguably even
the Linguistic Turn all arise from trying to make Kant’s transcendental
anthropology explanatory in the way that an empirical anthropology
would be. Having portrayed human cognition as ultimately responsive to
experience, the empiricist reviewers read Kant’s transcendental
199 anthropology as confused empirical psychology. Finally, early reviews
reflect readers’ general confusion about most details of Kant’s
arguments; they typically focus on overarching themes of Kant’s work,
and insofar as they enter into details, do so primarily in the context of
the relatively straightforward accounts of sensibility rather than the very
complicated transcendental deduction of the categories of the
understanding.
After the first reviews of his Critique, Kant tried to correct
misunderstandings and defend his transcendental anthropology, most
notably through his publication of a simplified version of the main
results of the Critique – his Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics
(1783) – and his revision of the Critique itself (which aimed especially to
distinguish his view from Berkeley’s). But as Kant continued to develop
his philosophy into ethics, aesthetics, and other areas, the work of
defending and clarifying his first Critique largely fell to others.
Moreover, in 1785, after largely unfavorable initial reviews, an
event transformed German intellectual life and contributed to a more
favorable reception of Kant’s philosophy. The event hardly seems
remarkable: within a month, two biographies of Gotthold Ephraim
Lessing, who had died a few years earlier, were published. Lessing had
been the leading light of the German enlightenment for decades. (Kant
had written, just a few years before publishing the Critique, “I am
uncomfortable that you praise me as comparable to Lessing. For in fact I
have not yet accomplished anything to deserve such comparison”
(10:198).) The biographies were written by Moses Mendelssohn, another
leading Enlightenment philosopher, and F.H. Jacobi, a long-standing
critic of thoroughgoing Enlightenment rationalism. Both had known
Lessing, and Jacobi had visited him during his final days. During those
conversations, Jacobi reports that Lessing confessed, “There is no other
philosophy than that of Spinoza” and that he adhered to the philosophy
of “One and all.”150 In late 18th century Germany, “Spinoza” was a trope
for materialism, fatalism, and atheism; Spinoza’s deterministic
pantheism – the view that everything is God and everything about God is
necessary – was seen undermining both religion (since a philosophy in
which God is identical to the world is no different from atheism) and
morals (since if everything is necessary, then there is no room for moral
responsibility). If Lessing, the best proponent of Enlightenment
rationalism, had found that all philosophy ends in Spinozism, one
seemed forced to choose between being rational and being moralreligious. Given this choice, Jacobi argued, one ought to subordinate
150
See Lessing 2005: 241-56, especially p. 244.
200 reason to a “mortal leap” of faith. Mendelssohn, partly to save Lessing’s
reputation but primarily to vindicate Enlightenment rationalism, sought
to show that reason need not require abandoning morals and religion.
The “Pantheism Controversy” that started with a dispute about Lessing
soon became a wide-ranging debate about the prospects for
Enlightenment rationalism in Germany.
The result of this apparently biographical dispute was that in
1785, German intellectual life became preoccupied with the issue of how
(and whether) to reconcile faith and reason. And into that context came a
new young philosopher and defender of Kant: Karl Leonhard Reinhold
(1757-1823). In a series of “Letters on the Kantian Philosophy” published
in 1786-7, Reinhold argued that Kant’s philosophy successfully solved
this problem by negotiating a middle ground between “naturalists” who
claim too much for reason and “supernaturalists” who allow too little.
Reinhold, anticipating points that Kant made explicit in later works,
suggested that even while justifying the possibility of a priori knowledge
of objects of possible experience, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason
precludes rational knowledge of the all-important topics of religion: God
and immortality. But in contrast to those like Jacobi who insist upon a
“mortal leap,” Kant “found the true ground of conviction in a faith
commanded by reason” (Reinhold 2006: 21). What’s more, by placing the
ground for religious conviction in a “moral ground of cognition” (Reinhold
2006: 44), Kant protects against both amoral Spinozism and the moralreligious fanaticism that can come from non-rational religious faith.
Kant’s distinction between theoretical and practical reason – or between
the transcendental anthropologies of cognition and desire – provided a
form of non-Spinozist rationalism to meet the needs of the age.
Reinhold’s Letters had three main effects on the reception of Kant’s
philosophy. First, they solidified Kant’s status as the main philosopher to
be reckoned with over the next thirty years. Kant’s work had been widely
if critically reviewed, but the difficulty of its prose and the complexity of
its arguments had prevented the widespread interest in Kant that came
with Reinhold’s accessible and popular Letters. Second, because he
situated Kant in the context of the Pantheism Controversy, Reinhold
explicitly bracketed “the depths of speculation from which Kant has
unearthed so many previously undiscovered treasures of the human
spirit” in favor of “extracting the principle results of the Critique of
Reason” (Reinhold 2006: 16). Thus Reinhold suggested that “his readers
postpone their judgment on its internal grounds” (Reinhold 2006: 50n),
and it is not until his last letter that Reinhold even begins to lay out
some of the complicated transcendental anthropology of cognition that
underlies Kant’s insistence upon rational faith (see Reinhold
201 2006:104ff.). While Kant’s overall conclusions were seen as central to
philosophy for the next several decades, the particular arguments used
to establish those conclusions were largely left behind. Finally, the fact
that Kant became popular through Reinhold quickly established
Reinhold himself as a force to be reckoned with in German philosophy.
Reinhold was given a Professorship at Jena within a year of publishing
the Letters, and he quickly became seen – much to Kant’s chagrin – as
the defender of Kantian philosophy. Unfortunately for Kant, the third of
these effects was to be the most lasting. Even as the tide turned from the
practical and religious concerns of the 1780’s back towards more
systematic issues, philosophers increasingly turned to Reinhold rather
than to Kant. By 1794, Fichte could write that “in the opinion of a
majority of the admirers of the Kantian philosophy, Reinhold is the
author who has either already succeeded in establishing philosophy as a
science or else has best [i.e., better than Kant!] prepared the way for
such success” (Review of Aenesiemus 4, in Fichte 1993: 60).
While his early defense of Kant focused on the results of Kant’s
philosophy for the Pantheism Controversy, Reinhold quickly turned to
fleshing out the “internal grounds” for Kant’s transcendental
anthropology in way that – he claimed – would be faithful to the “spirit”
of Kant without becoming “slave to the letter” of Kant (Foundation 97, in
diGiovanni 1985: 79). But Reinhold came to this project with
commitments that were at odds with Kant’s philosophy of the human
being, which led to several revisions of Kant’s transcendental
anthropology: a shift towards foundationalism, a return to quasiLeibnizian reductionism about mental states, a new kind of
systematicity, and a non-anthropological approach to transcendental
philosophy. First, Reinhold was a foundationalist in a way that Kant
never was. Reinhold spends the decade after publishing the remarks in
search of the “one absolutely fundamental explanation” that could
irrefutably ground results he endorsed from Kant’s Critique. Shortly after
publishing his Letters on the Kantian Philosophy, Reinhold set to work
on Concerning the Foundation of Elementary-Philosophy (1789), followed
shortly thereafter by On the Foundation of Philosophical Knowledge,
together with some comments concerning the Theory of the Faculty of
Representation (1791) and Concerning the Foundations of Philosophical
Knowledge, of Metaphysics, Morality, Moral Religion, and the Doctrine of
Taste (1794). Whereas Kant sought to lay out transcendental conditions
of possibility of various commonsense commitments (e.g., to empirical
knowledge and moral responsibility), Reinhold aimed to lay indubitable
foundations for philosophy in a basic starting point. As the subtitle of his
1791 text suggests, Reinhold located this foundation in the “faculty of
202 representation,” the definition of which he “does not pull out of thin air”
but “ground[s] upon a principle which is determined through itself” (R81,
in diGiovanni 1985: 71-2). This “principle” is “the principle of
consciousness,” which is itself nothing more than “the exposition of the
immediate expression of the self-explanatory actual fact of
consciousness” (R103-4, diG 81). For Reinhold, this fact is “the only
thing about whose actuality all philosophers agree . . . No idealist, no
solipsist, no dogmatic skeptic, can deny its being” (R 190, cf. diGiovanni
1985:107-8).
Reinhold’s foundationalism contributed to a second key difference
from Kant, a subtle rejection of Kant’s multi-faculty approach to the
human mind in favor of reductionism about human mental states.151 In
chapter three, we saw how Kant’s empirical psychology argued against
attempts of Leibniz and Wolff to reduce all mental powers to a single
power of representation. Similarly, in his transcendental anthropology,
Kant carefully distinguished between the a priori structure governing
different ways of approaching the world: as an object of knowledge, a
sphere for human action, or a purposive locus of beauty and order. In his
attempt to develop a systematic philosophy built on a single, solid
foundation, however, Reinhold returned to the traditional Leibnizian
strategy of reducing different mental powers to variations of a single
power:
[T]he science of the a priori form of representing through sensibility,
understanding, and reason; on this form depends the form of
knowledge, as well as that of desire. In a word, it would be the
science of the entire faculty of representation as such (R 71,
diGiovanni 1985: 67)
[T]he two particular parts of the Philosophy of the Elements, the
theoretical and the practical, of the sciences of the faculties of
cognition and desire respectively, are subordinate to one common
fundamental science” (Foundation 127, diGiovanni 1985: 91)
Reinhold’s foundationalist objection to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason –
that “the science of the faculty of cognition would have to be preceded by
another that establishes its foundation” (R71, diGiovanni 1985: 67) –
applies just as well to Kant’s other Critiques. And Reinhold’s
supplementation of Kant’s specific Critiques with a foundation in
151
Admittedly, Reinhold did point out that different powers “express particular kinds of consciousness”
that are irreducible to each other and that have “specific properties,” but his focus ends up being on the
“principle of consciousness in general” that “expresses what is present in every consciousness”
(Foundation 106, diGiovanni 1985:82, cf. diGiovanni 1985: 69, 70)
203 consciousness provides not only an indubitable ground for knowledge
about our more specific mental faculties, but a ground that unifies these
diverse faculties into merely different “specifications” of a single
underlying faculty.152
Third, Reinhold’s Leibnizian reductionism about human mental
states combined with his strong foundationalism gave Reinhold’s
philosophical anthropology a much more systematic character than
Kant’s own. Kant’s anthropology is pervaded with distinctions, between
transcendental and empirical perspectives; between cognition, feeling,
and desire; between sensibility and the undboth erstanding. Reinhold’s
comprehensive foundationalism results in a “scientific form” with a new
“systematic character”, a “thoroughgoing interconnection of . . . material
. . . under one principle” (R 109-10, diGiovanni 1985: 84). Where Kant
sought a taxonomically exhaustive system laying out conditions of
possibility of various different human faculties, Reinhold seeks the unity
of all sciences under the single foundational principle of consciousness.
Finally, Reinhold’s emphasis on consciousness as the ground of a
whole transcendental system displaced the uniquely human character of
Kant’s own transcendental philosophy. For Kant, the world appears as it
does because of distinctively human features of cognition, especially the
spatial-temporal structure of our sensibility. By contrast, by emphasizing
the power of representation, Reinhold sought transcendental conditions
of possibility of any world that could be represented by any being,
human or otherwise, deriving even space and time not from the
particular form of human intuition but from the nature of representation
as such.
Reinhold’s attempt to provide a unified, systematic grounding for
what he took to be a broadly Kantian transcendental anthropology did
not silence Kant’s critics, of course, and in 1792, G.E. Schultze (17611833), a little known philosophy professor, wrote a work entitled
Aenesidemus, Or Concerning the Foundations of The Philosophy of the
Elements issued by Prof. Reinhold in Jena, Together with a Defense of
Skepticism Against the Pretensions of the Critique of Pure Reason. The
work defensed a broadly Humean skepticism and rejected Reinhold’s
philosophy and the foundationalism that had become the dominant
152
Reinhold even takes this unifying further, suggesting that his Philosophy of Elements will ground both
sensible and supersensible objects: “the Philosophy of the Elements must lay down the principles not just
for the metaphysics of nature, but for general metaphysics as well – qua metaphysics of knowable objects,
but no less qua metaphysics of those supra-sensible objects that are present only to thought” (Foundation
121, diGiovanni 1985:89).
204 interpretation of Kant’s own transcendental anthropology. Its impact was
immediate and profound, marking the end of Reinhold’s dominance as
preeminent defender of Kant. While Reinhold himself quickly faded from
the scene after the publication of this criticism of his views, however,
Aenesidimus did more to promote than to undermine the foundationalist,
reductionist, and systematic direction in which Reinhold took Kant.
In his Review of Aenesidemus (1794)¸ J. G. Fichte (1762-1814)
simultaneously named Reinhold as the primary defender of Kantian
philosophy and usurped that role.153 For Fichte, Schultze’s skepticism
showed “the precariousness of the position where [philosophical reason]
has for the moment come to rest” (diGiovanni 1985: 137). Aenesidemus
“concedes . . . that philosophy has so far lacked a supreme, universally
valid principle, and that it will be able to elevate itself to the rank of a
science only upon the establishment of some such principle” (diGiovanni
1985:138, emphasis added). But Fichte argues, against both Reinhold
and Schultze, that this principle need not be based on the power of
representation. Fichte thus accepts Reinhold’s foundationalism while
denying his specific foundation. Moreover, unlike Kant, for whom the
attempt to find a common root to the diverse powers of the soul is
mistaken and ultimately futile, Fichte seeks “yet a higher concept than
that of representation” (diGiovanni 1985: 138). The general reductionist
trajectory begun by Reinhold is extended by Fichte and, in varying ways,
becomes the guiding thread of German Idealism, which would dominate
the appropriation of Kant for the next 30 years.
The key to Fichte’s shift away from Reinhold is his move from a
“fact [Tatsache] of consciousness” to an original act [Tathandlung], to
start not from some dogmatic assertion but from a “highest act,” which
Fichte identifies with an “act of self-positing” (Fichte 1993:126). As Fichte
explains, “the heart of my system is the proposition, ‘The I simply posits
itself’” (Fichte 1993:398).154 The self-positing of the I, a self-positing of
which one becomes aware only through an “intellectual intuition” of one’s
own activity, precedes any distinction between subject and object, or
between oneself and others. This importantly differentiates Fichte’s
foundationalism from previous foundationalisms, including Reinhold’s.
Whereas Reinhold followed Descartes and others in seeking a
substantive foundation, Fichte’s grounding act provides a “practical”
153
Like Reinhold and the German Romantics, Fichte takes himself to be adhering to the spirit of Kant –
“my system is none other than the Kantian system” – even if not the letter – “it proceeds in a manner that is
entirely independent of Kant’s presentation” (Fichte 1994: 4).
154
See Beiser 2002 for discussion of the ongoing scholarly debate about whether this I should be
understood subjectively (as an individual I) or as an absolute I distinct from any individual.
205 foundation for his philosophy. Fichte takes self-positing as a starting
point and shows how it requires positing a “not-I.” In later works, Fichte
takes the requirement to posit not-I further, arguing that positing oneself
as a free being requires positing a not-I that can issue an invitation
(Aufforderung) to activity, and to play this role, the not-I must be free
and rational. Thus the I’s self-positing requires positing other free and
rational beings, and from this deduction of intersubjectivity, Fichte
derives a whole moral and political theory (see his 1796-7 Foundations of
Natural Right and 1798 System of Ethics). An indubitable foundation in
the self-positing of the I provides the basis for a systematic philosophy
that not only responds to skeptical concerns regarding theoretical
knowledge but also grounds a detailed practical philosophy.
Some further points are worth noting in connection with Fichte’s
relation to Kant’s transcendental anthropology. First, like Kant, Fichte
emphasizes human freedom. An early letter shows Fichte’s admiration
for Kant – and rejection of Spinozism – springing precisely from this
emphasis on freedom:
The influence that this [Kant’s] philosophy, especially its moral part
(though this is unintelligible apart from the Critique of Pure Reason),
exercises upon one’s entire way of thinking is unbelievable – as is the
revolution that has occurred in my own way of thinking in particular.
. . I now believe wholeheartedly in human freedom and realize full
well that duty, virtue, and morality are all possible only if freedom is
presupposed. I realized this truth very well before . . . but I felt that
the entire sequence of my inferences forced me to reject morality . . .
If I have time and leisure, I will devote them . . . entirely to the
Kantian philosophy. (Fichte 1993: 360).
The “I” that posits itself is free, and its positing is free self-positing. Even
the restraints imposed upon the I by the not-I and other free beings must
be seen, from the perspective of the I itself, as self-imposed restraints:
“the not-I which is supposed to determine the intellect is itself
determined by the I – though in this case the I would be considered not
as the representing I, but rather as an I which possesses absolute
causality” (Fichte 1993: 134). However, Fichte’s admiration for Kantian
freedom does not extend to the metaphysical framework that, for Kant,
made such freedom possible. Fichte vehemently rejects the doctrine of
the thing-in-itself, describing it as “a pure invention which possesses no
reality whatsoever” (Fichte 1994: 13), a “piece of whimsy, a pipe dream, a
nonthought” (Fichte 1993: 71). Rather than taking “representation” to be
primitive and getting trapped by Jacobi’s (and Pistorius’) Affection
Problem, Fichte takes Idealism to its limit and denies the need to think of
206 anything beyond what is posited by an Absolute I (which itself is merely
something self-posited, rather than some existent but unknowable
thing). Finally, Fichte – like Reinhold – shifts from a specifically
anthropological idealism (which argues from the nature of human
cognition to a metaphysics of human experience) to an “absolute”
idealism that abstracts from anything distinctively human. Whether one
interprets Fichte’s “I” as the I of a single individual or an absolute I that
stands apart from any particular thinker, the starting point of Fichte’s
philosophy is not distinctively human. The “I = I” that marks the
beginning of the Wissenschaftslehre is, even more than Reinhold’s
“principle of consciousness,” a universal, non-anthropological starting
point.
By 1800, Kant no longer had control over his own philosophy. His
pragmatic and empirical anthropology were largely ignored, and his
transcendental anthropology was subjected to vehement criticisms from
empiricists, skeptics, and even rationalists. More importantly, Kant’s
“defenders” largely left Kant behind, and the world looked not to Kant,
but to Reinhold and then Fichte for the comprehensive vision that could
resolve the conflicts Jacobi had highlighted between a rational
understanding of the world and the freedom necessary for moral
responsibility. German Idealism, as it emerged through the work of
Reinhold and Fichte, would replace Kant’s anthropological philosophy
(with its sensitivity to the diversity of human faculties, the irreducible
perspectives that human beings take on the world, and the inherent
limitations of these perspectives), with foundationalist, systematic
philosophies that sought to find a single absolute and fundamental fact,
act, or standpoint from which everything important about the world
could be completely understood.
II. Early German Romanticism
The foundationalist, systematic approach of Reinhold and Fichte
was not universally accepted as the best way to carry on the “spirit” of
Kant’s philosophy. Especially in the context of Hamann and Herder’s
critiques of supposedly purely-rational system-building, another group of
thinkers – so-called German Romantics – promoted an appropriation of
Kant that deemphasized reason and system. Like Reinhold (and Fichte),
these thinkers saw themselves as following Kant, but German Romantics
focused on a very different Kant. Three central themes characterize the
207 reception of Kant’s anthropology within Early German Romanticism: an
attempt to bridge the gap between nature and freedom (and therefore
between duty and inclination), an interest in individuality rather than
universality, and a focus on the implications of the inscrutable thing-initself for the limits of philosophy.
The Romantic interest in bridging the divide between duty and
inclination that Kant seemed to assume in his moral philosophy begins
with Kant’s own insistence in his Critique of Judgment and pragmatic
anthropology that there must be a way of bringing together nature and
freedom, what we will do and what we ought to do. Drawing on Kant’s
claim in the Critique of Judgment that the feeling for the beautiful
provides a link between nature and freedom, many Romantics
emphasized the formative function of art in bridging what Kant’s
anthropology had seemed to present an intractable divides. The most
important early attempt is found in Friedrich Schiller (1759-1805), who
famously offers this witty poetic criticism of Kant’s divide between duty
and inclination:
Scruples of Conscience
I gladly serve my friends, yet I do it by inclination
And so it often vexes me, that I am not virtuous
Decision
There is no other advice, you must seek to despise them,
And thereby do with abhorrence what duty bids you. (Schiller and
Goethe 1796: poems 388-9)
But Schiller’s more important contribution to the Romantic reception of
Kant’s conception of human nature came through his On the Aesthetic
Education of Man, where Schiller seeks, like Reinhold, to develop a
philosophy that is true to the “spirit of the Kantian system” even if not to
the “letter of it” (Schiller 1967: 87n2).155 There Schiller argues,
If we are to be able to count on man’s moral behavior . . . as we do on
natural effects, it will itself have to be nature, and he will have to be
led by his very impulses to the kind of conduct which is bound to
proceed from a moral character. But the will of man stands
completely free between duty and inclination, and no physical
compulsion can, or should, encroach on this sovereign right of his
personality. If, then, man is to retain his power of choice and yet, at
155
With respect to Kant’s anthropology in general, Schiller is actually remarkably sensitive the spirit of
Kant’s whole anthropology (not merely the transcendental part of it), following Kant in insisting upon
distinctions between different powers of soul, developing a philosophy of history with marked parallels to
Kant’s own, emphasizing the importance of pragmatic-moral anthropology, and even laying out some
similar details (e.g. an emphasis on aesthetic illusion) to Kant’s own.
208 the same time, be a reliable link in the chain of causality, this can
only be brought about through both these motive forces, inclination
and duty, producing completely identical results in the world of
phenomena; through the content of his volition remaining the same
whatever the difference in form; that is to say, through impulse being
sufficiently in harmony with reason to qualify as universal legislator.
(Schiller 1967: 17).
Schiller uses Kant’s fundamental claim about human beings – that we
are both objects in an empirical world and free agents – to argue for a
new kind of philosophical task. If we are both free and empirical, then
virtue requires not only a strong will that can choose in accordance with
the moral law but a set of empirical incentives that will give rise to moral
actions as the expression of that will. For Kant, cognition of the moral
law appears in the empirical world as a predisposition to personality by
which the moral law itself overpowers “inclinations” rooted in the lower
faculty of desire. But Schiller’s essay “On Grace and Dignity” (1792),
objected that “in the moral philosophy of Kant, the idea of duty is
proposed with a harshness enough to ruffle the Graces, and one which
could easily tempt a feeble mind to seek for moral perfection in the
somber paths of an ascetic and monastic life” (Schiller 2006:148) By
contrast, Schiller aims for an ethics that would recognize and embrace
the whole of human nature: “By the fact that nature has made of him a
being at once both reasonable and sensuous, that is to say, a human
being, it has prescribed to him the obligation not to separate that which
she has united” (Schiller 2006: 147). For Schiller, the “will” that acts in
accordance with the moral law has no direct empirical correlate, so
bringing together nature and freedom requires developing inclinations
that will give rise to the actions duty requires. Thus Schiller sees the
unification of reason and sensibility, duty and inclination, as necessary
to bring Kant’s anthropology to completion. Violating the “letter” of Kant’s
moral theory by insisting that dutiful actions can and even should be
motivated by inclination (empirically) is necessary, Schiller thinks, to
preserve the spirit of Kant’s anthropological emphasis on both freedom
and nature. Even before Kant published his Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View (1798), Schiller’s On the Aesthetic Education of
Man (1794) puts at center stage what would become Kant’s pragmatic
anthropology, especially the issue of how to empirically effect moral
reform in human beings. Bridging the gap between nature and freedom is
an important part of the Romantic appropriation of Kant.
A second key theme within the Romantic appropriation of Kant is
the emphasis on human individuality. When Novalis (1772-1802) insists
that “the highest task of education is – to seize the mastery of one’s
209 transcendental self – to be at the same time the Self of one’s Self”
(Novalis 1797: 207), he does not have in mind Kant’s sort of autonomy as
governing oneself by means of a universal moral law, but instead an
embracing of “my own, true, innermost life” (Novalis 1797:206) which
differs wildly from one person to another. Friedrich Schlegel (1772-1829)
praises the one “who has his own religion, his own original way of
looking at infinity” (Schlegel 1800:261) and objects that “the Kantians’
conception of duty relates to . . . one’s calling . . . as the dried plant to
the fresh flower” (Schlegel 1800:262). For him, “Individuality is precisely
what is original and eternal in man; personality doesn’t matter so much.
To pursue the cultivation and development of this individuality as one’s
highest calling would be a godlike egoism” (Schlegel 1800:264).
Schleiermacher (1768-1834) – whose early years were spent in the
company of the German Romantics – adds, “What would be the point of
the uniform repetition of a highest ideal whereby human beings . . . are
all actually identical, the same formula [e.g., the categorical imperative]
being merely combined with other coefficients?” (Schleiermacher 2006:
39). True humanity and true freedom are found not in submission to any
universal law, even a supposedly self-legislated one, but in embracing
and cultivating one’s uniqueness.
Finally, a third key theme in the Romantic appropriation of Kant
was an emphasis on the unknowability of ultimate reality. Drawing from
Kant’s own insistence that the human mind constructs a comprehensible
reality but lacks cognitive access to things-in-themselves, Schlegel
rhetorically asks, “Isn’t this entire world constructed by the
understanding out of incomprehensibility or chaos?” (Bernstein 2003:
305). But unlike Kant, Romantics do not tidily set chaos to one side and
pursue what can be known. Schlegel rejects any philosophy that
“inhibits a leap into the suprasensory regions” (Bernstein 2003: 251) and
thereby also rejects any philosophy that purports to be complete,
systematic, comprehensible, or even consistent: “Philosophy is the real
homeland of irony, which one would like to define as logical beauty . . .
Irony is the form of paradox (Bernstein 2003: 241). And, put most
beautifully because most ironically, “It’s equally fatal for the mind to
have a system and to have none. It will simply have to decide to combine
the two” (Bernstein 2003: 247).
For many early Romantics, the emphasis on the incomprehensible
was linked with a rejection of the Fichtean pretension that the I – and
especially some primitive act of self-positing – can be original. Even if
self-positing first brings order to experience, Romantics refuse to reject
the Kantian notion that something precedes – not temporally but
logically or even ontologically – this order. Schlegel puts this in terms of
210 incomprehensibility or chaos. Hölderlin (1770-1843) describes it as
“Being,” a sort of primordial unity out of which subject and object emerge
(a unity that cannot therefore really be thought of as a unity of subject
and object, since this unity of already assumes the distinction that Being
precedes). Throughout, Romantics shift towards thinking about the world
that underlies the emergence of the I, not just the way that the I comes
back to the world. In an aphorism that sums up the anthropology of
many early Romantics, Schlegel writes, “The human being is Nature
creatively looking back at itself” (Schlegel 1800: 261). On the one hand,
this aphorism points out the distinctive importance of human beings; we
are the way the nature looks back at itself, and we are creative. On the
other hand, though, this aphorism shows a way in which Nature is
privileged. Rather than seeing Nature as primarily constructed by human
beings (as in Kant’s transcendental anthropology), Schlegel sees human
creativity itself as the expression of a spiritualized and creative Nature.
Permeating all three developments was an emphasis within early
German Romanticism on the importance of art and of feeling.156 Schiller
finds the bridge between nature and freedom in a purely aesthetic, free
activity. Schlegel insists that true art expresses the unique inner
character of the genius who creates it: “An artist is someone who carries
his center within himself” (Schlegel 1800: 263). And Hölderlin points to
art – notably tragedy – as revelatory of “the hidden ground of everything
in nature” (Bernstein 2003: 193). Precisely because art is not reducible to
the categories with which human beings structure the world into a
coherent whole, it is capable of mirroring the incomprehensibility of the
world: “a classical text [i.e., a poetic creation] must never be entirely
comprehensible” (Bernstein 2003: 239). Art represents the world from a
perspective, but a perspective that, precisely because it is not universalconceptual, leaves the incomprehensibility of the world open to further
interpretation. Art – including tragedy, poetry, music, etc – provides
glimpses of that Being that precedes all categories.
III. Late German Idealism
Fichte marks a high point of Early German Idealism, the pinnacle
of foundationalist and I-centered approaches to understanding humans’
place in the world. For Fichte, philosophy was capable of achieving a
156
In fact, Kant’s Critique of Judgment – as a transcendental anthropology of feeling that finds in beauty
and the sublime a unity between nature and freedom, a sort of individual freedom in the activity of the
genius, and a way of “feeling” the supersensible – could be seen as an early Romantic text, and early
Romantics drew heavily from that Critique.
211 scientific, systematic status through seeing all knowledge as following
from the conditions of self-positing of the “I.” Early German Romantics
resisted Fichte’s subjectivism,157 systematicity, and rejection of limits for
human knowledge. The next major stage of German Idealism was
dominated by two figures – Friedrich Schelling158 (1775-1854) and G. W.
F Hegel (1770-1831) – who were closely tied to German Romanticism.
Schelling, Hegel, and Hölderlin lived and studied together in Tübingen,
and all three worked together on an “Oldest System-Programme of
German Idealism,” which lays out a sort of program for “a new mythology
. . . of reason.” But while Schelling and Hegel shared some central
Romantic convictions, they fundamentally accepted the need for
systematic philosophy.
Among the most important problems facing the later German
Idealists was the problem of how to reconcile the empiricist and
especially Romantic recognition that humans’ interpretive activity is
something that emerges out of a pre-existing Nature or Being with the
insights of Kant’s properly transcendental anthropology. Two issues here
were particularly important. The first was how to preserve cognitive
access to the world. Unlike the Romantics, Schelling and especially Hegel
refused to accept the absolute incomprehensibility of ultimate reality.
Like Reinhold and Fichte, they sought some way of avoiding commitment
to an absolutely unknowable thing-in-itself. But this required responding
to Kant’s arguments that the Copernican turn that makes knowledge
possible also limits the scope of that knowledge. The second issue was
how to preserve the from-the-inside dimension of transcendental
anthropology while integrating human beings into a more comprehensive
natural whole.
Early Idealism and Romanticism provided some resources for
systematically integrating human beings into an absolute whole. Fichte’s
“Absolute I” provided one avenue. In Schelling’s hands, the “Absolute I”
was transformed into merely “the Absolute” as such. Hölderlin had
already suggested that “Being expresses the combination of subject of
object” and specifically directed this conception of Being against Fichte’s
“I=I” in which subject and object are united through combining what is
157
See Beiser 2002: 217ff. for discussion of the scholarly debate about whether the ascription of
subjectivism to Fichte is justified.
158
For the purposes of this brief summary, I focus on the early work of Schelling, ending in the early
1800s. Schelling is famous for constantly shifting philosophical views, but here I aim for a more-or-less
unified view of his early works. For discussions of Schelling’s whole corpus, see Bowie 1993, Snow 1996,
and White 1983.
212 already posited as separate. Schelling follows Hölderlin in arguing that
Fichte’s “I” must be conceived of as something that emerges from a more
basic “Absolute.” Whereas Fichte and Reinhold saw Kant’s philosophy of
freedom as a way to avoid a Spinozism that he saw as inimical to
morality and religion, Schelling made use of this same emphasis on
freedom to redeem Spinozism by showing how Being itself can ground
freedom. Schelling’s project has three parts, which we might see as the
stages towards fusing Fichte with Spinoza and thereby integrating a
transcendental and normative perspective into a Romantic conception of
human beings as emerging from Nature.
First, in his Naturphilosophie (Nature-Philosophy) of 1797,
Schelling sets out to transform Spinoza by developing what we might
think of as a transcendental cosmology. Rather than looking at the world
of appearance from the perspective of human experiencers, as in Kant’s
transcendental anthropology, Schelling attempts to think of the world of
appearances from the perspective of nature itself. Schelling thus seeks
to explain the world out of which human knowers could have emerged,
rather than simply the world known by human beings. Here the
question is not “what are the conditions in human nature that make it
possible to experience a world?” but “what are the conditions in Nature
that allow it to be the sort of thing that can be experienced?” Like
Spinoza, Schelling adopts a God-eye view on the world, seeing it as a
whole that manifests itself in different ways. But for Schelling, nature is
not a set of brute mechanical interactions. Drawing from the spirit
(though certainly not the letter!) of Kant’s Critique of Judgment,
Schelling sees nature as purposive, an “original productivity” (Bowie
2003:75). And just as Fichte argued that the I must limit itself in order to
become conscious of itself, Schelling argues that Nature must limit – or
“inhibit” – its own productivity in order to emerge from the realm of vital
forces to appear as an “object” for a human perceiver. In thinking of
Nature itself as an original productivity, Schelling transcends, from the
side of nature, the determinism that seemed to rule out freedom (and
with it morality). Whereas Fichte (and Kant) thought freedom could be
preserved only by prioritizing human activity, Schelling points out that
Nature itself can be conceived as a set of active forces. Rather than
protecting human freedom from Nature, Schelling argues that human
freedom emerges from freedom already in nature. In contrast both to
traditional compatibilisms (which change our concept of freedom so that
it fits with natural necessity) and to Kant (who posits nature and freedom
in separate realms), Schelling changes our concept of nature so that it
fits with our conception of freedom as something fundamentally active.
213 Second, in his System of Transcendental Idealism of 1800,
Schelling considers the problem of the relationship between nature and
freedom from a Fichtean (rather than Spinozist) starting point.
[I]n the fact of my knowing, objective and subjective are so united
that one cannot say which of the two has priority . . . [so] there are
two possibilities.
A. Either the objective is made primary, and the question is: how a
subjective is annexed thereto[?] . . .
B. [Or] the subjective is made primary, and the problem is: how an
objective supervenes, which coincides with it? (Schelling 1978:6-7)
Naturphilosophie addressed the first possibility, concluding that Nature
itself must have properties associated with subjectivity, in particular a
sort of spontaneity that comes to emerge in consciousness. System
addresses the second possibility. Starting from the perspective of the
knowing I, Schelling considers what is necessary in order for that I to
have knowledge of a world that is not itself a subjectivity. And his
central claim in System is the converse of the central claim in
Naturphilosophie. Just as Nature must be united with subjectivity and
thus must be spontaneous, so the free, spontaneous, and conscious “I”
must be united with Nature and thus grounded in unconscious
elements. Schelling thus posits “an identity of the nonconscious activity
that brought forth nature and the conscious activity expressed in willing”
and exhibits “this simultaneously conscious and nonconscious activity . .
. in consciousness itself” (Schelling 1978:12). In the process, Schelling
draws from Fichte’s argument that consciousness depends upon the notI and echoes Holderlin’s appeal to a Being more primordial than the
subject-object dichotomy to argue for a sort of incoherence in the very
categories in terms of which Kant cast his famous “Copernican turn”:
[T]he distinction between what comes from without and what comes
from within . . . stands in need of justification . . . But . . . I posit a
region of consciousness [really, unconsciousness] where this
separation does not exist, and where inner and outer worlds are
conceived as interfused. (Schelling 1978:74)
Like his Naturphilosophie, System aims to undermine the Kantian
distinction between nature and freedom, now by showing that freedom
itself has an unconscious, “natural,” dimension. And for Schelling –
arguably following the lead provided by Kant in his Critique of Judgment,
but certainly following the lead of Romantics like Schiller – the
unconscious dimension of human subjectivity has important
214 implications for the sort of “knowledge” that one can have of self and
nature. Since conscious knowing is only partial and derivative, access to
nature as well as oneself can only take place most fully in the context of
a process of awareness that combined conscious and unconscious
elements. This awareness takes place in art, in both “the artist . . . lost in
his work” (Schelling 1978:75) and those aesthetically reflecting on the
work of art:
The work of art reflects to me what is otherwise not reflected by
anything, namely that absolutely identical which has already divided
itself even in the self . . . [A]rt is at once the only true and eternal
organ and document of philosophy, which . . . speak[s] to us of what
philosophy cannot . . ., name the unconscious element in acting and
producing, and its original identity with the conscious. (Schelling
1978:230-1)
One recent commentator has gone so far as to claim, “The System can be
described simply as an elaborate proof of the proposition that only
aesthetic intuition can provide, in the production of the work of art, the
reconciliation in consciousness of finite and infinite, conscious and
unconscious activities, without assimilating the unconscious to the
conscious” (Snow 1996: 120). Art is the way in which the primordial
unity of subject and object, of nature and freedom, of unconscious and
conscious, becomes manifest to consciousness. Art as the intuitive
awareness of original unity is Schelling’s Romantic conclusion to Fichte’s
reflection on the subjective conditions of knowing.
Finally, Schelling pulls together these elements into a single
“Identity Philosophy” that emphasizes that the unity of subject and
object in knowing and doing is always already rooted in a primordial
“Absolute Identity” that precedes the separation into subject and object.
In his later work, Schelling moves away from the sympathetic approach
to Fichte with which his 1800 System of Transcendental Idealism began;
rather than saying that “the result of the operation is bound to be the
same” whether one starts with Nature or with the I, Schelling’s later
emphasis on the Absolute involves a fundamental subordination of the
“I” to a whole (das Alls) that precedes it:
Since Descartes, the I think, I am, has been the basic mistake of all
knowledge; thinking is not my thinking, and being is not my being,
for everything is only of God or the whole. (Aphorisms as an
Introduction to the Philosophy of Nature (1804))
215 It is not the I that knows, but the whole [universe] through me . . .
[Without] some knowledge totally independent of all subjectivity . . .
of . . . the simple One . . . , we would be eternally locked inside the
sphere of subjectivity. (System of the Whole of Philosophy and of
Nature in Particular (1804), I/6:140, 143)
With this shift away from subject-centered idealism, however, Schelling
also solidifies his criticisms of attempts to come to complete knowledge –
of self, Nature, or the Absolute – through concept-based philosophy; art
and intuition, rather than conceptual analysis or objective knowledge,
become the access points for contact with the Absolute, and no
“understanding” of that Absolute can ever be complete.
In the end,159 Schelling shares with early German Idealism a
commitment to overcoming the dualisms in Kant’s distinction between
appearances and things-in-themselves, and in affirming a Kantian
emphasis on combining a philosophy of human freedom with a natural
philosophy that could do justice to the empirical world. But Schelling
adopts from the Romantics a skepticism about ultimate conceptual
knowledge of the world, an emphasis on art and creativity, and even –
from Hölderlin in particular – an insistence that the really real must
precede the distinctions between subject and object, nature and freedom,
that are so central not only to Kant but also to Reinhold and Fichte.
The climax of German Idealism comes with G.W.F. Hegel. Hegel got
his philosophical start through working with Schelling in Jena during a
period in which Schelling had just taken the philosophical mantle from
Fichte. By the time Hegel surpassed Schelling to become the dominant
voice in German philosophy, Kant’s role in German philosophy had
become largely symbolic. The particular ideas associated with Kant were
those appropriated or criticized in Fichte, Schelling, and the Romantics,
and Hegel interacts primarily with these later figures. Nonetheless, Hegel
pulls together many of the central criticisms of Kant’s philosophy that
emerged in the decades after the publication of the first Critique. Like
Schelling, he seeks to appropriate but move beyond not only the Early
German Idealists but also the German Romantics. Unlike Schelling,
159
Well, not quite the end. I have cut short my discussion of Schelling here at his 1804 System. His
thought continues to undergo significant change for 30 more years. Of Human Freedom, his last published
work (in 1809) is particularly valuable its challenge to Kant’s conception of freedom, but it is also a work
that arguably takes Schelling beyond German Idealism, and the interpretation of the work is widely
contested (compare, e.g., White 1983, Snow 1996, and Heidegger’s very important treatment in Heidegger
1985). As important as the work is, getting into its details would take the present chapter too far astray.
216 Hegel’s sympathies lie more with the system-building Idealists than the
aesthetic Romantics. Thus where Hegel follows earlier thinkers in
rejecting Kant’s distinction between appearances and things-inthemselves, Hegel does so – unlike Schelling or Hölderlin – in the service
of Absolute Knowledge. In this Introduction to his Phenomenology of
Spirit, after laying out various ways in which a “mistrust of Science”
might come about through thinking about the gap between our faculties
of cognition and the Absolute that “Science” aims to know, Hegel says, “if
. . . Science, . . . in the absence of such scruples [about its possibility]
gets on with the work itself and actually cognizes something, it is hard to
see why we should not turn around and mistrust this very mistrust”
(Hegel 1979: 47). Hegel aims to undermine both Kant’s idealism about
knowing things in themselves and Schelling’s skepticism of scientific
knowledge of the Absolute by actually establishing that knowledge.
In order to do this, Hegel develops his own philosophical
methodology, a “logic” distinct from Kant’s “transcendental” style of
argument, Fichte’s foundationalism, Romantic aphoristic and
mythological philosophy, and Schelling’s appeal to (aesthetic or
intellectual) intuition. In some respects, this dialectical logic can be seen
as a systematizing the reasoning Kant used in his Antinomies in The
Critique of Pure Reason. In the third antinomy, for example, Kant shows
how one can prove both determinism and the necessity of a freedom that
contradicts determinism, and this “antinomy” – proof of both sides –
leads him to diagnose and reject the underlying premise of both sides:
transcendental realism. In a similar way, Hegel’s dialectical logic
involves moving through positions that are revealed as “one-sided,” in
such a way that one first moves from, say, an overly subjective approach,
to an overly objective approach, and then moves forward by rejecting the
common one-sided assumption underlying both approaches. For
example, Hegel’s Phenomenology starts with the naïve view that what is
real is simply “This,” that which is immediately present and certain to
the senses, but shows that this “This” ends up being empty without some
conceptual determination. This challenge to “Sense-Certainty” does not
lead to an empty skepticism, but to a further position, in which one
privileges abstract concepts over immediate sense experience. But this
view has problems of its own, and that leads to a further refinement, and
so on. In his moral philosophy, Hegel begins with the view that freedom
is simply doing what one feels like doing (the “natural will,” see Hegel
1991: §11), but this does not allow one to rise above contingently-given
inclinations, so one pursues a “negative will” (Hegel 1991: §§5, 15), which
ends up empty of content, and so on. The general strategy here is to start
from some naïve given conception of reality and our knowledge of it and
217 “negate” this conception by showing its immanent conflict with itself, but
to negate it in a way that “determinately” gives rise to a more
sophisticated conception of reality (see especially Hegel 1979: §§77ff.).
Hegel’s dialectical arguments lead to a more holist conception of
human beings than Kant’s. Hegel not only objects to distinguishing
empirical objects from things-in-themselves, but also – like Schelling –
incorporates various Kantian dichotomies into a single, coherent
conception of the self (and world) that combines objective and subjective,
volition and cognition, understanding and sensibility. Hegel accepts the
force of the Affection Problem and rejects the unknowable “thing-initself.” He appropriates and broadens Schiller’s critique of Kant’s
separation between duty and inclination, insisting that “what is actual
becomes rational and what is actual becomes rational” (cited in Hegel
1991: viii, cf. § 1). For human motivation in particular, “it is an empty
assertion of the abstract understanding to require that only a [moral] end
shall appear [autonomously] willed . . ., and likewise to take the view
that, in volition, objective and subjective ends are mutually exclusive”
(Hegel 1991: 151). Like Romantics, Hegel seeks unity between subjective
inclinations and moral duties. (He finds this, first, in love, but eventually
also in the feelings of honor, trust, and patriotism that lead one to do
one’s duties in society and the state.) Like Kant, Hegel insists that
human particularity must be subordinated to universal principles, but
his conception of “universality” is concrete and social rather than
abstract. Hegel argues that Kant’s conception of the categorical
imperative as an “abstract universality” makes morality an “empty
formalism.” Without “material from outside,” the categorical imperative
gives no particular duties, since anything can be universalized if one
does not care about any particular consequences: “the fact that no
property is present is in itself no more contradictory than is the nonexistence of this or that individual people . . . or the complete absence of
human life” (Hegel 1991: 162). But while Hegel considers Kant’s abstract
ethics too one-sided, he sees the Romantic emphasis on feeling and
individual creativity as equally one-sided and empty (see especially Hegel
1991: §140-41). Instead, Hegel proposes that “ethics” – as opposed to an
abstract Kantian “morality” –must be situated in particular social and
political contexts. He approvingly quotes “a Pythagorean” who advised a
father asking about how best to “educat[e] his son in ethical matters . . .:
‘Make him a citizen of a state with good laws.’” (Philosophy of Right, §
153, Wood, p. 196). Hegel develops a complicated description of ethical
life in which moral duties are given by a person’s place in a familial,
economic, and political order.
218 Hegel thinks that humans can get insight into the legitimacy of the
existing world – including one’s social order – because insight emerges
from the unfolding of the world itself. Like Schelling, Hegel sees art (and
religion) as important sources of insight into the rationality of the world,
but against Schelling, he argues that ultimate insight into the world’s
rationality is provided by philosophy. Moreover, with Herder and
Hamann, Hegel insists that human beings must be understood
historically and, with Schelling, he sees human rationality as an
historical achievement rather than an eternal condition or a
transcendental fact. But Hegel insists that this historical development is
rational and rationally comprehensible, that world history justifies its
stages. Human beings arise out of nature through an inevitable process
of Spirit, or the Absolute, coming to know itself. And for Hegel, ethical
and epistemic norms not only arise out of the concrete historical
situations in which one finds oneself but are, at least in principle,
ultimately conducive to Absolute Knowledge. Hegel ends up with a
conception of humans as agents and knowers situated in terms of a
nature, history, and social life that are rationally comprehensible
through a Science of dialectical reason. Reason is not the purified faculty
to which Hamann objected in his Metacritique but an ability made
possible through the use of language shaped in particular historical
societies. Freedom is not an abstract metaphysical concept, not an
“uncaused cause” or noumenal thing-in-itself grounding an empirical
world, but an historical and social accomplishment. Human beings are
free because (or insofar as) we are self-knowing members of well-ordered
communities at the right moment(s) in world history.
IV. Conclusion
The immediate responses to Kant’s anthropology focused on his
transcendental anthropology. Kant’s pragmatic and empirical
anthropology had important influences, but much less important than he
had hoped. Kant’s student Herder was influenced at least as much by
the proto-pragmatic anthropology he was exposed to in Kant’s lectures as
by any transcendental anthropology developed later. Schleiermacher
famously – and quite negatively – reviewed Kant’s Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View. Kant’s general approach to empirical
anthropology, and especially his tripartite conception of human mental
states, helped set the stage for later developments in empirical
psychology. And Kant’s conception of human evil became a major focus
of discussion not only by Schelling and Hegel but also by Kierkegaard.
But in the end, Kant’s empirical and pragmatic anthropology was largely
219 marginalized during the 19th century. Herder’s more radical historicism
and Platner’s physiological anthropology, rather than Kant’s pragmatic
anthropology, drove the agenda of empirical research on human beings
throughout 19th century Germany (see Zammitto 2002:253).
As we have seen in this chapter, there were a wide range of
responses to Kant’s transcendental anthropology. There are, of course,
important figures during this period that this chapter has passed over.
Among these, two of the most important for later developments
(especially Nietzsche) are Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard. Schopenhauer
stands largely outside of the traditions of German Idealism and
Romanticism that characterized the early reception of Kant’s philosophy,
though like these movements, Schopenhauer saw himself as the true
heir – but also corrector – of Kant: “While I start in large measure form
what was achieved by the great Kant, serious study of his works has . . .
enabled me to discover great errors in them” (Schopenhauer 1966: xv).
Like the early German Idealists, especially Reinhold, Schopenhauer
sought to develop a more simplified, foundationalist structure to Kant’s
philosophy. But whereas early Idealists such as Reinhold drew largely
from Descartes as a model for foundationalism, Schopenhauer was more
sympathetic to Berkeleyan idealism, and his reading of Kant – which
focused on the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, the version
that Feder and Garve referred to as merely a new Berkeleyanism –
pushed Kant in this Berkeleyan direction. Schopenhauer’s magnum
opus, The World as Will and Representation, starts with the fundamental
claim that “The world is my representation” (Schopenhauer 1966: 3). But
Schopenhauer simplifies both the argument for this position and the
transcendental structure of cognition itself, ridding Kant’s argument of
what many saw as unnecessarily complicated arguments and artificial
taxonomies of “categories,” “faculties,” and so on. Unlike many early
responses to Kant, Schopenhauer does not reject a distinction between
appearances (the World as Representation) and something akin to an
underlying thing-in-itself, which Schopenhauer calls the Will. Unlike
Kant, however, Schopenhauer restricts all cognition (not just space and
time) to the world as representation, which means that the relationship
between Will and Representation cannot, in any sense, be a relation of
causation or grounding. Schopenhauer aims to get around the Affection
Problem by positing that there is a single world that is known by human
subjects as a world of representation, but of which human beings have
direct “consciousness” as Will in awareness of their own wills
(Schopenhauer 1966: 99-100). Given that all categories are precluded
from the analysis of the Will, however, Schopenhauer argues that “the
will, considered as such . . ., knows no plurality and consequently is one”
220 (Schopenhauer 1966: 128). With that move, Schopenhauer moves in
quasi-Kantian way toward the undifferentiated “Being” that had been
posited by Hölderlin. From there, Schopenhauer develops his own
version of the developmental story that we saw in Schelling and Hegel.
The Will is engaged in a constant struggle against itself, emerging in
higher and higher “Forms,” culminating (so far) in what we think of as
individual human wills. Since this whole activity of the Will is struggle
against itself, however, it is also a sort of suffering, so Schopenhauer
moves on to recommend a sort of asceticism that would turn the Will
against itself, ending in a “death . . . which breaks up the phenomenon of
this will, the essence of [which has] long since expired through free
denial . . .; for him who ends thus, the world has at the same time
ended” (Schopenhauer 1966: 382).160 A few decades later, Nietzsche
would adopt much of this picture of the Will struggling against itself in a
constant path of suffering and self-overcoming, but reject the ascetic
pessimism and, embracing suffering, also embrace higher and higher
manifestations of Will.
Where Schopenhauer represents an alternative sort of systembuilding appropriation of Kant, Kierkegaard inherits the anti-systematic
interests of the Romantics (whom he read sympathetically) and the late
Schelling (whose lectures he attended). Kierkegaard’s thought cannot be
easily summarized – one of his psuedonyms “dreads what is . . . frightful,
that one or another enterprising summarizer [and] paragraph-gobbler . .
.will cut him up into paragraphs” (Kierkegaard 2006:6) – but one
important trend of this thought is an emphasis on what he calls
“Subjective Truth,” or, more radically, the notion that “Truth is
Subjectivity” (Kierkegaard 1992: 189ff.). Briefly, one might understand
this as a sort of fruit of taking Kant’s Copernican turn seriously while
rejecting the principled distinction between cognition and volition. The
point, then, is that what can be taken to be “true” by an individual is
constrained not merely by forms of cognition but also by forms of
volition, or relevance. This leads to an emphasis on the importance of
truths to which one can relate passionately, and eventually to an antisystematic conception of Christian faith any ethical or epistemic
universals (see, e.g., Kierkegaard 1985, 2006).
Even with the addition of these figures, there are some general
aspects of the reception of Kant that are common amongst most of his
immediate successors. Many of Kant’s ideas were retained, such as his
160
This account skips several important steps in Schopenhauer’s argument, and his entire (important)
discussion of art (especially music) as a will-less knowing of the Will as such, but these aspects of his view
would go beyond the needs of the present chapter.
221 emphases on human freedom and some version of his Copernican turn,
but most of Kant’s successors sought to move away from Kant’s sharp
distinction between appearances we can know and “things-inthemselves” we cannot. There was also a general effort to overcome the
wide variety of distinctions and dichotomies within Kant’s system in favor
of a more holistic approach to human beings, whether in the form of
Reinhold’s reemphasis on representation as such, or Herder’s (and
others’) rejection of the sharp division between cognition and volition, or
Schelling and Hegel’s rejection of the subject-object dichotomy, or
Schiller and Hegel’s efforts to overcome the distinction between
inclinations and duty. Throughout the period of Kant’s immediate
reception, there was a tendency to push Kant’s philosophy as a whole
towards extremes of systematicity, either making it much more
systematic (Reinhold, Fichte, Hegel) or resisting systematic knowledge
altogether (Herder, Romantics, and to some extent Schelling). Kant’s
interest in human history was also increasingly transformed and
radicalized during this period towards something like a transcendental
historicism that sees not only particular human tendencies and
structures as historically developing but even the basic structure of
human reality as subject to historical change.
222 Chapter 7: 19th Century Alternatives–Darwin, Freud, Marx, and
Nietzsche
At the time of his death in 1831, Hegel was the pre-eminent
philosopher in Germany (and arguably the world) and philosophy, at
least in Germany, was the most important discipline in the academy.
Within a decade, the philosophical world in Germany had largely moved
beyond Hegel, but without an obvious replacement. Schelling, who held
Hegel’s old position at the University of Berlin, was an able critic but
failed to generate many philosophical followers of his own. For the rest of
the 19th century, philosophy in Germany was largely dominated by a
variety of neoKantian philosophical movements, attempts to get “back to
Kant!” in ways that would be honest to the scientific and historical
developments of the 19th century. At the same time, since Hegel’s death
no single philosopher has dominated the philosophical scene in any part
of the world, and philosophy has seen its role increasingly diminish.
Hegel’s philosophical system – like Kant’s – included a detailed logic, an
account of the nature of being, an investigation of the basic principles of
physics and biology, explanations of political and social organization
both historically and in his own day, an account of the proper role of the
state, a detailed aesthetics (including, in Hegel’s case, a history of art),
interpretations of the French Revolution and the rise of the nation-state,
and so on. For many of these questions, it is hard to imagine that
philosophers provide the best answers today, and for none of them is it
clear which philosopher one should turn to. Many people even suspect
that any questions for which one needs a philosopher are likely to be
those for which there cannot be any real answer. Whereas many in
Hegel’s time held out hope that philosophy could provide solid, lasting,
and comprehensive answers to all important questions, today the most
plausible “Theories of Everything” seem to come from physics, or biology,
or even social sciences. This shift is particularly dramatic in terms of the
question, What is the human being? For Kant, this question was simply
equivalent to philosophy as such. Even for Kant’s immediate successors,
the question was a properly philosophical one. Today, however, most
would be more likely to turn to the sciences – biology, psychology, or
sociology – for a rigorous answer to the question. And even those who
worry that the sciences might miss something essential about human
beings are more likely to follow the Romantics into art or literature than
to embrace philosophy.
Our present condition did not emerge from a vacuum. While
neoKantianism dominated the philosophical scene in Germany after
Hegel, many figures arose during the mid-to-late 19th and early 20th
223 centuries that have shaped the context of our current thinking about
human beings in ways that cannot be ignored. And several of the most
important such influences relate directly to both Kant’s own
philosophical anthropology and to the way in which that philosophy was
appropriated by Kant’s immediate successors. In this chapter, I look at
four episodes in the development of this contemporary perspective. In
each case, I point out both the ways in which these developments pose
significant problems for Kant’s conception of human beings and the ways
in which they draw from (or mesh with) important dimensions of Kant’s
thought. I start with the figure who marks, in retrospect, the most direct
successor to Hegel: Marx. Marx’s historical materialism and his
conception of human beings as socially and materially determined beings
not only reflected an important response to and appropriation of earlier
philosophical accounts of the human being, but it also helped set the
stage for the emergence of the social and historical disciplines that play
such important roles in our conceptions of human beings today. Second,
I turn to the 19th century thinker least closely connected to German
philosophy: Darwin. I focus here on two important roles of his theory of
evolution by natural selection. This theory solidified the status of biology
as a natural science, and it offered a theoretical structure for a new
biological account of human beings. Third, I look at the most important
purely philosophical development in 19th century philosophy: the work of
Friedrich Nietzsche, and especially his genealogical revaluations of
values. And finally, I look at the development of these trends and the
emergence of scientific psychology in the work of Sigmund Freud.
I. Marx and the Rise of Human Sciences
Marx (1818-1883) is one of the dominant intellectual figures of the
century, and Marxism was undeniably one of the greatest political
influences on the 20th century. Marx is typically thought of more in
connection with the revolutionary Communist Manifesto that he coauthored with Engels than with his close analysis of Hegel’s Philosophy
of Right or even his own magnum opus, Capital. In this brief section,
however, my emphasis will be on Marx’s philosophical conception of
human beings and the way in which this conception affected his
communist ideas. Of all the figures discussed in this chapter, Marx most
directly follows from the issues and debates discussed in chapter six.
Marx was a close reader of Hegel, and from Hegel he took the core idea
that human beings are essentially constituted by historically situated
social interactions and that human freedom requires embodiment in the
world through socially recognized work. But Marx rejects what he saw as
19th
224 Hegel’s “uncritical” political conservatism that teaches a mere
“restoration of the existing empirical world,” seeking to redeem that world
in abstract thought rather than to change it (Marx 1963: 201; Marx
1994:83). The result is a conception of human nature as a historical
accomplishment that depends upon certain economic conditions,
conditions not yet realized under the current (both then and now)
capitalist economic system. In this short section, I start with a
discussion of Marx’s human ideal, then turn to an account of the ways in
which this ideal is not yet achieved because of the alienation in capitalist
(and pre-capitalist) forms of life, and then end with a discussion of
Marx’s dialectical materialism and revolutionary, change-oriented
approach to philosophy.
For Marx, humans are relational, and our most important
relationships are with nature, society, and ourselves. With respect to the
natural world, Marx follows Hegel in emphasizing that what is means to
be human is in part to make the world in our own image, not merely in
the Kantian sense that we see it through human categories, but in the
more practical sense that we work on nature – whether physically or
intellectually or both – to make it into a human world. “The human being
. . . begins to distinguish himself from the animal the moment he begins
to produce his means of subsistence . . . By producing food, the human
being indirectly produces his material life itself” (Marx 1970: 42, also in
Marx 1994:107). Put another way, “It is just in his work upon the
objective world that the human being really proves himself . . . By means
of it nature appears as his work and reality. The object of labor,
therefore, is the objectification of man’s species-life” (Marx 1963: 128). By
working on nature, human beings make real the sort of beings that they
are: “In the type of life activity resides the whole character of a species,
its species-character” (Marx 1963: 128). Thus in the ideal, humans
should “create the human being by human labor” that effectuates “free,
conscious activity [which] is the species character of human beings”
(Marx 1963: 128, 166). While the species character of animals need
involve nothing more than perpetuating the physical and instinctive
characteristics of their species, human engagement with the world
should bring about expressions of the freedom that is characteristically
human. Thus Marx explains that in contrast to animals, “man produces
when he is free from physical need and only truly produces in freedom
from such need” (Marx 1963: 128), for example, when a human being
“constructs . . . in accordance with laws of beauty” (Marx 1963: 128).
The emphasis on human work as our proper relationship with
nature is combined, in Marx, with a strong emphasis on the social nature
of human beings. The human being is a “species-being” that “is in his
225 existence . . . a social being” (Marx 1963: 154). Marx takes as an example
his own “scientific work,” since science – as the pursuit of truth about
the world – might seem to be something that could be carried on in
isolation from others. But Marx insists that this activity is “social,
because human” (Marx 1963: 157) in that even “the material of my
activity – such as language itself” is a social contribution to that activity,
and “what I myself produce I produce for society, and with the
consciousness of acting as a social being” (Marx 1963: 158). To be truly
human, one must live and work in the context of relationships to society.
Finally, self-realization – our proper relationship with ourselves –
takes place through actualizing free, conscious activity of sociallysituated work in our own particular way. Marx emphasizes that even
one’s individuality matters as the individuality of a social being: “the
human being is a unique individual–and it is just his particularity which
makes him an individual, a really individual communal being” (Marx
1963: 158). My particular strengths and weaknesses show up and are
relevant only within a social context. Just as Marx’s unique political and
social theorizing depends upon a social context, so too does the activity
of any human individual. For Marx, one truly becomes who one is when
one “makes the community (his own as well as those of other things) his
object both practically and theoretically, [and] also (and this is simply
another expression for the same thing) in the sense that he treats himself
as the present, living species, as a universal and consequently free being”
(Marx 1963: 128). As an individual communal being drawing from society
to contribute to society, our labor helps define and expand the
parameters of human possibility. One relates to oneself properly, as a
“species being,” when one’s individual life becomes a means for
expressing the goods of the species in free and creative ways.
For Marx, then, humans are those beings that engage in free,
conscious, social activity. Unfortunately, according to Marx, one living in
a capitalist society “exists only as a worker and not as a human being”
(Marx 1963: 137), and, what’s worse, “the worker sinks to the level of a
commodity, and to a most miserable commodity” (Marx 1963: 120). The
dehumanization of workers takes place through what Marx calls
“alienation.” In general, alienation occurs when what should be an
essential aspect of one’s own humanity is made foreign – or “alien” – to
oneself. Marx diagnoses four key forms of alienation within capitalism:
alienation from the products of one’s labor, from other people, from
oneself, and from humanity.
Alienation from the products of one’s labor is the simplest to
comprehend: “the alienation of the worker in his product means not only
226 that his labor becomes an object, assumes an external existence, but
that it exists independently, outside himself, and alien to him, and that it
stands opposed to him as an autonomous power” (Marx 1963: 122-3).
Any product, simply by virtue of being a product, will stand independent
of its maker in some sense. When Marx develops a scientific theory or
when an artist makes a work of art or when a good cook makes a
delicious meal, the theory and the work of art and the meal are
independent of their creators. But in all of these cases, the work is the
concrete expression of the free activity of its maker. Insofar as the theory
is studied or the work contemplated or the meal eaten, its maker
accomplishes his own ends and the activity is merely completed in the
external existence of the product. But within capitalist economies,
workers no longer produce for the sake of their products but for the sake
of wages.161 In such a system, the goal of the worker is wages that are
used for sustaining (animal) life, and the independent product – the
automobile or the blue jeans or even the artwork marketed to wealthy
collectors or the meal sold to paying customers – is an alien product,
something that does not express the free and conscious activity of its
human maker but merely the mechanical operations of a worker. The
result, for Marx, is devastating: “The more the worker expends himself in
work the more powerful becomes the world of objects which he creates in
the face of himself, the poorer he becomes in his inner life, and the less
he belongs to himself” (Marx 1963: 121). Rather than taking an alien
nature and transforming it in the light of free human activity, the
workers in a capitalist economy imbue alien nature with their own labor
in order to make it an even more powerful and more alien force working
against them. One ends up alienated not only from the immediate
products of one’s labor, but – because labor is the way in which the
world becomes one’s own – one is alienated from the “sensuous external
world” as a whole (Marx 1963: 125).
Moreover, for Marx, within capitalism, human relationship become
increasingly corrupted. People are valued for the extent to which they
can generate higher profits. This valuing can be direct and obvious, as
when employers pay all workers the same wages based on their
productivity, treating them as more-or-less efficient product-generators
rather than as human beings in a cooperative enterprise of transforming
nature for the good of society. But alienation in human relations
happens even in more intimate contexts, where one increasingly regards
friends and neighbors, and even parents and children, in terms of how
161
This emphasis on wage-labor is distinctive of capitalism, but alienated labor is not. In early epochs, one
might work for the sake of God, for instance, but one’s product would still be alienated, expressing the will
of God rather than one’s own free, conscious activity.
227 much they help or hinder one’s economic interests. Think here of parents
who make decisions about how much time to spend with children based
on what they can afford, or of the ways in which friends seek to ensure
that bills are split equally so that no one falls into another’s debt. And
even more subtly, human relationships end up being crafted around
communities of common interest, where “interests” end up being largely
a matter of one’s situation within the labor market. As Marx puts it,
“every man regards other men according to the standards and
relationships in which he finds himself placed as a worker” (Marx 1963:
129).
The alienation from the products of one’s labor and from truly
human relationships with others leads to an alienation from one’s self.
For one thing, alienation from the products of labor quickly becomes
alienation from the activity of labor:
the work is external to the worker . . . [I]t is not a part of his nature;
and . . . consequently he does not fulfill himself in his work but
denies himself, has a feeling of misery rather than well-being, does
not develop freely his mental and physical energies but is physically
exhausted and mentally debased . . . His work is not the satisfaction
of a need, but only a means for satisfying other needs . . . This is the
relationship of the worker to his own activity as something alien and
not belonging to him, activity as suffering (passivity), strength as
powerlessness, creation as emasculation, the personal physical and
mental energy of the worker, his personal life (for what is life but
activity?), as an activity which is directed against himself,
independent of him and not belonging to him. This is the selfalienation as against the . . . alienation of the thing. (Marx 1963: 1246).
What starts as the selling of the products of labor quickly transforms
labor itself, one’s life-activity as such, into something that is not part of
who one is, but something to be traded away in exchange for satisfying
basic needs. But because, for Marx, life is activity, who one is is what
one does and one’s place in society, alienation from one’s activity is
alienation from oneself.
The result of this three-fold alienation from the sensuous world,
other people, and oneself, is an alienation from true humanity. “[T]he
human becomes animal” as people
find fulfillment not in work and relationships but in food, sex, and at
best “decorating and personal adornment” (Marx 1963: 125). Rather than
228 the activity of the individual contributing to defining the species, one
puts one’s distinctively human traits – one’s language, reason,
relationships with nature and others – to the service of merely animal
ones:
alienated labor . . . makes species-life into a means of individual life .
. . For labor, life activity, productive life, now appear to man only as
means for the satisfaction of a need, the need to maintain his
physical existence. (Marx 1963: 128)
Even if, say, one constructs a home in accordance with aesthetic ideals,
in a capitalist economy one does so only so that one can meet merely
animal needs, so that one can get better wages and thereby more food,
sex, entertainment, and so on. Capitalism is precisely that condition “in
which every natural and social characteristic of the object is dissolved, in
which private property has lost its natural and social quality (and has
thereby lost all political and social disguise and no longer even appears
to be connected with human relationships) and in which the same
capital remains the same in the most varied natural and social
conditions, which have no relevance to its real content” (Marx 1963:
139). In the end, “alienated labor . . . alienates from man his own body,
external nature, his mental life, and his human life” (Marx 1963: 129).
This account of alienation requires Marx to answer to the question
“What is the human being?” for future humans, those not living under
alienating economic conditions. For Marx, humanity is the end of a
process –“world history is . . . the creation of the human being” (Marx
1963: 166-7) – and a process that is not yet finished: “the human level . .
. will be the . . . future of [currently capitalist] nations” (Marx 1963: 52).
This conception of humanity as not-yet-realized has at least two
important implications for Marx’s overall philosophy of the human being.
First, like Hegel, Marx endorses a form of historicism according to which
the actual lives of human beings are characterized differently at different
times in history. Marx, along with Engels, has become extremely well
known for his “dialectical materialism” or “historical materialism,”
according to which material conditions of people at different stages
determine the form of “human” life at that stage, shape the philosophies
and “ideologies” that dominate that period, and also – inevitably – set the
stage for a transition to a different stage in world history, one with
different material conditions of labor and thereby different ideologies and
forms of life. Second, unlike Hegel, Marx sees the historical process as
far from finished, and this leads him to emphasize action over mere
thought, revolution over mere philosophizing. The rest of this section
briefly takes up these two themes.
229 Marx’s dialectical materialism involves two central claims: first,
that historical changes are results of an “inevitable” or “necessary”
development (Marx 1963: 115, 120), and, second, that the fundamental
basis for these changes are material conditions, where “material” here
primarily refers to the control over the means for putting human work to
use, whether these be physical factories or institutions or knowledge.
Marx specifically distinguishes his philosophy of history from Hegel’s in
emphasizing not the unfolding of rational ideas into material relations
but how material conditions generate the ideas of a particular epoch:
“[c]onceiving, thinking, and the intellectual relationships of men appear
here as the direct result of their material behavior . . . In contrast to
German philosophy, which descends from heaven to earth, here one
ascends from earth to heaven” (Marx 1970: 47, in Marx 1994: 111, see
too Marx 1977: 102).
Marx’s materialism is opposed to Hegel in an abstract way, but is
also opposed to many popular conceptions of historical change. For
Marx, ideas do not change the world, but vice versa. Only as the material
conditions of production change can ideas change, since ideas are merely
the reflection of those conditions: “Humans are the producers of their
conceptions, ideas, etc., but these . . . humans . . . are conditioned by a
definite development of their productive forces” (Marx 1970: 47, in Marx
1994:111). One does not change society by changing “hearts and minds;”
rather, hearts and minds change as the conditions under which people
live and work change. Similarly, historical change is not fundamentally a
matter of political change. Because “legal relations [and] political forms . .
. originate in the material conditions of life” (Marx 1994:210), any
fundamental shift must always be in material conditions. Real political
change must be the consequence, not the cause, of this material change.
Importantly, Marx’s “materialism” is not the physical materialism
of atoms in a void, but the economic materialism of concrete productive
activities. Human beings must labor, first to survive, and then to express
their species-being. And this labor is necessarily social in that we labor
as members of community, not isolated individuals.
In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into
definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely
relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the
development of their material forces of production. The totality of
these structures of production constitutes the economic structure of
society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political
superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the
230 general process of social, political, and intellectual life. It is not the
consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their
social existence that determines their consciousness. (Marx 1994:
211)
Explaining the evolution of the material forces of production and thus
the relations of production gets extremely detailed, and it is largely the
effort to detail the important shift to a capitalist economy and the forces
driving a shift from that economy that preoccupy Marx’s intellectual life.
But the general structure of the account involves looking at the ways in
which human society at a given time is conditioned by the ways in which
human work is capable of taking place, and then tracing how the
development of processes of human labor create needs for new social,
political, and economic structures. Thus, for example, Marx ascribes the
difference between medieval-feudal and ancient economic systems to the
“sparse population . . . scattered over a large area” with declining
agricultural production and little trade (Marx 1994:109-10). Under such
conditions, while the feudal system remained “an association directed
against a subjected producing class[,] . . . the form of association and the
relationship to the direct producers [was] different because of the
different conditions of production” (Marx 1994:110). Marx’s account of
history, moreover, is neither an account of individual human beings
acting under historically local conditions of production nor a description
of humanity in general. As indicated in the example of the feudal system,
Marx’s focus is on associations of producers and those who exploit them,
that is, on classes. Thus not only are ideas in a given period shaped by
that period’s material conditions, but, more specifically, “In every epoch,
the . . . class that is the ruling material power of society is at the same
time its ruling intellectual power” (MSW, 129). In general, “The history of
all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles” (Marx 1994:
158).
Ultimately, while Marx defends historical materialism in general,
his focus is on applying it to his own capitalist society. He emphasizes
how class struggles of previous ages – amongst “patricians, knights,
plebeians, and slaves” or “feudal lords, vassals, guild-masters,
journeymen, apprentices, and serfs” (Marx 1994:159) – are simplified
into a single class antagonism between the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat. The bourgeoisie own the (increasingly industrial-scale)
means of production, while the proletariat work. We have already seen
Marx’s analysis of workers’ alienation. In the context of dialectical
materialism, Marx emphasizes how capitalism generates contradictions
that will give rise to its own downfall. “The bourgeoisie not only has
forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called into
231 existence the men who are to wield those weapons — the modern
working class — the proletarians” (Communist Manifesto, in Marx
1994:164).
Capitalism has at least three important effects that – Marx argues
– will provoke a shift to a communist society. First, capitalism unites
workers and gives them the tools of resistance. Mechanization makes all
work essentially equal in worth and thereby makes workers more and
more united. Improved means of communication (from telegraph to
internet) make it easier for workers to work together as a class. And
capitalists inadvertently arm workers with tools of organization through
attempts to exploit them politically. Capitalists at first mobilize workers
to use against competitors, as, for instance, when bosses of domestic
industries incite workers to push for high import tariffs. But this political
mobilization can (and, Marx argues, will) eventually backfire when
workers recognize their solidarity with other workers around the world,
rather than with their own industry and its bosses. Second, capitalism
sows the seeds of its own destruction, not only through the alienation
and general misery of the workers, but through sets of economic crises –
what we might call the “business cycle” – that, Marx argues, become
increasingly intense as mechanisms for mitigating their effects dry up.
The result will be increasingly severe cycles of booms and busts in
productive output and correspondingly severe cycles of unemployment,
eventually leading to revolutionary demands for radical change in the
economic structure. Finally, by increasing mechanical efficiency,
capitalist society will change the structure of human need. Within
capitalism, economic crises are caused not by underproduction but by
overproduction; the failure to find sufficient markets for the excessive
numbers of products leads to lay-offs and massive unemployment. But
this opens an opportunity. Abolishing private property in a context of
extreme scarcity could lead to severe deprivation of even basic needs. But
when human beings can easily produce what they need through effective
use of technology, most labor can be devoted towards work that is not
tied to human needs. We can finally be truly human in our species-being.
Thus capitalism creates a class that could bring about a shift to a new
world order. It gives that class the motive to bring about that shift. And it
makes such a shift possible: “The development of Modern Industry . . .
cuts from under its feet [its] very foundation . . . What the bourgeoisie . .
. produces, above all, are its own grave-diggers. Its fall and the victory of
the proletariat are equally inevitable” (CM in Marx 1994:169).
How precisely this shift was to occur is a matter of some
contention amongst Marxists. At the end of The Communist Manifesto,
Marx appeals for a “communist revolution” crying out “Working men of
232 all countries, Unite!” In later works, Marx seems to allow that the
“revolution” might be peaceful and political rather than violent and
military. In any case, Marx often endorses the notion that the shift will
not proceed directly from capitalism to pure, property-less communism
but will proceed through various forms of socialism and pseudocommunism, such as the “universal private property” that seeks to
equalize wages for all (and that Marx compares to “universal
prostitution”) (Marx 1963:153; Marx 1994:69). And Marx recognizes the
possibility of many false friends of communism, such as the “bourgeois
socialism” that desires to “redress social grievances” in order to secure
the continued existence of the bourgeois state” (Marx 1994:181) and the
“utopian socialism” that is little more than an idle side-project of the
wealthy and a distraction from real social change (Marx 1994:182-4). In
terms of Marx’s conception of human nature, however, the important
point is simply that for Marx, all history prior to the achievement of a
communist condition within which alienated labor will be overcome is
merely the “prehistory of human society” (Marx 1994:212). Human
beings will be the result of millennia of labor that develops towards the
overcoming of class antagonism and the fulfillment of truly human
potential.
Marx’s account of ideal human nature, alienation, and dialectical
materialism would not, in themselves, have made him one of the defining
figures of the 19th and 20th centuries. But Marx’s philosophy was not the
complacent thought-experiment of an armchair philosopher. Instead,
Marx put his ideas to use to mobilize, organize, and inspire the concrete
activities of communists seeking to change that world. For Marx, “the
chief defect of all hitherto existing materialism,” and of all previous
philosophy, is that it “does not grasp the significance of ‘revolutionary’, of
‘practical-critical’, activity”: “The philosophers have only interpreted the
world, in various ways; the point is to change it” (Theses on Feuerbach
##1, 11; in Marx 1994:99, 101). In describing the dialectically necessary
progress towards communism in the Communist Manifesto, Marx applies
this practical-critical emphasis to a thinly veiled autobiography of his
role in historical progress:
[I]n times when the class struggle nears the decisive hour, the
progress of dissolution . . . assumes such a violent, glaring character,
that a small section of the ruling class cuts itself adrift and joins the
revolutionary class, the class that holds the future in its hands. Just
as . . . at an earlier period, a section of the nobility went over to the
bourgeoisie, so now a portion of the bourgeoisie goes over to the
233 proletariat, and in particular, a portion of the bourgeois ideologists,
who have raised themselves to the level of comprehending
theoretically the historical movement as a whole. (CM in Marx
1994:167)
Through his philosophical descriptions of alienation and even more
through his political-economic analyses of the failures of capitalism to
meet basic human needs, Marx provides the theoretical framework for
uniting the proletariat in its revolutionary struggle.
This practical focus manifested itself in Marx’s writing style, which
tended to be polemical rather than philosophical, and in his active
involvement in worker’s movements around Europe. The ultimate result
was that Marx’s ideas – albeit in warped and incomplete forms – shaped
the ideology of two of the three most powerful nations in the world during
the 20th century, and even today over 1 billion people live under
(nominally) “Communist” rule. Today, after the fall of the Soviet Union
and the increasingly capitalist economic structure in China, Marxism in
its Leninist-Stalinist-Maoist form is increasingly discredited. But the end
of these supposed communist systems opens the possibility for a
reappraisal of the contributions that Marx – as opposed to Marxism162 –
can and has made to our conception of human beings. For example,
while Marx’s strictly political influence may be waning, his intellectual
influence is still significant in disciplines such as history and sociology,
where not only Marx’s general emphasis on material conditions of human
life but even many of his specific analyses continue to exercise significant
influence. More generally, although Marx is widely disclaimed by
professional economists in favor of theorists such as Smith or Ricardo, it
was Marx – far more than Smith or Ricardo – who argued that economics
is the fundamental science of human nature, and the increasing
dominance of economic ways of conceiving of human beings can trace its
origin, at least in significant part, to Marx. Finally, even if Marx’s
description of alienation and his utopian vision for a communist world
order are overstated, his conception of human beings as needing to find a
fulfillment in their lives that capitalist economic structures preclude is a
conception that needs to be taken seriously in a world in which ever
more wealth seems poorly correlated with richer and fuller human lives.
II. Darwin and the Rise of Biology
162
See the aptly titled Marx after Marxism (Rockmore 2002).
234 When Kant was working through his philosophy of biology in the
Critique of Judgment, Newton’s Principia had established a pattern for
scientific physics, but the closest parallel in biology was Buffon’s Natural
History, which consisted primarily in the classification of various
different species based on their anatomical characteristics. Biology as a
discipline that could explain the nature of living things was still in its
infancy. The new physics had, for a short time, given hope to purely
mechanistic accounts of biology, according to which one could see living
things as complex machines. But in Kant’s day, these mechanistic
approaches to biology had given way to either various forms of
“preformationism” or vitalist, quasi-mechanist approaches to the origin of
life. Preformationism posited that each species was separately created
and that individual members of those species were present, in some
sense, in their ancestors. In its crudest version, this implies that every
human being was present, in miniature, in the eggs of Eve. Vitalist
explanations were closer to mechanist ones, positing that complex forms
of life emerge from simpler material interactions, but vitalists posited
that matter itself was best understood on a biological rather than strictly
mechanistic model. (Schelling’s attempt to infuse nature with something
analogous to freedom is an example of how this vitalism developed in the
early 19th century.) The challenge for all of these forms of biological
explanation was how to make sense of the apparent purposiveness of
living things; our hearts seem best explained by the fact that we need
blood to be pumped through our bodies, for example. As we saw in
chapter one, Kant’s own philosophy of biology affirms this purposive sort
of explanation as basic to biology while according it a merely “regulative”
status. But while Kant holds open the possibility in principle of
synthesizing these purposive explanations of organisms with a
mechanistic account of their origins, he doubts the emergence of a
“Newton of a blade of grass.”
Arguably, Charles Darwin (1804-1882) is just such a biological
Newton. He provided the basis for a new sort of mechanism in biology
that showed how purposive structures of organisms can emerge from
natural and not intrinsically purposive causal processes. Over time and
under various environmental influences, random variations in organisms
give rise to increasingly refined and even purposive structures through a
process of “natural selection.” This new approach put biology on
scientific footing by establishing an intuitively plausible and rigorous
methodology for not merely classifying organisms but also explaining
their origins and variations. But Darwin’s new theory of evolution by
natural selection all-too-clearly applied to human beings as well. As
natural organisms, our own specific characteristics must have emerged
235 from a natural process of evolution by natural selection. For many, this
offered new hope of finally and decisively answering the question “What
is the human being?” For others, it offered reason for despair, seemingly
making humans no more than animals and precluding the possibility of
any of those characteristics – such as reason, freedom, and the capacity
for love – that make human beings so unique.
Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection, as described in
his most famous work – The Origin of Species – is fairly simple. Biological
reproduction has two important characteristics: first, descendants tend
to share most of the traits of their ancestors; and second, organisms tend
to reproduce in sufficiently large numbers that there is a “struggle for
existence,” by virtue of which many descendants die early or are unable
to reproduce. Darwin argues,
Owing to the struggle for life, any variation, however slight and from
whatever cause proceeding, if it be in any degree profitable to an
individual of any species, . . . will tend to the preservation of that
individual, and will generally be inherited by its offspring. The
offspring, also, will thus have a better chance of surviving . . . I have
called this principle, by which each slight variation, if useful, is
preserved, by the term of Natural Selection. (Darwin 1859/1985: 115)
Over long spans of time, preserved variations tend to become more
prevalent within a population, and the species “evolves.” Moreover, given
that there is often more than one way members of a species can thrive,
“the greatest amount of life can be supported by the greatest
diversification of structure” (Darwin 1859/1985: 157). If different
members of a population have different variations that are valuable for
different purposes, the species diverges, eventually becoming two or more
distinct species.
The power of this approach is evident in the title of Darwin’s work:
On the Origin of Species. Over the course of the 18th and early 19th
centuries, the idea that one could provide an account of the origin of
biological entities in terms of mechanical forces had increasingly lost
ground against biological theories that took for granted an original
creation of the full range of biological species, each with their distinctive
traits firmly established. In part, this view in biology was motivated by
religious commitments, but in part, it was also due to the apparent
failure to find any clear mechanism by means of which complex
biological interdependence could be explained. As Kant laid out the case
in his Critique of Judgment, organisms seem to be teleologically ordered,
both in terms of physiology (the heart seems to exist for the purpose of
236 pumping blood for a body on which it is itself dependent) and in terms of
ecology (lions need gazelles to eat and gazelles need lions to control their
populations). But Darwin’s straightforward account made perfect sense
of how species could evolve, change, and diverge through selection
processes that are not, in themselves, purposive. In that sense, it
revolutionized biology, making both special creations and inherent
teleology obsolete.
In his Origin of Species, Darwin barely mentions human evolution,
saying only
In the distant future I see open fields for far more important
researches. Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the
necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by
gradation. Light will be thrown on the origin of man and his history.
(Darwin 1859/1982: 458)
Still, the implications of The Origin of Species for the case of human
beings were immediately obvious to both Darwin and his contemporaries.
In notebooks containing writings from a period during which he was first
developing his theory of evolution, Darwin points out “Man . . . is not a
deity,” challenges those who “dare boast of [humans’] preeminence,”
considers “What circumstances may have been necessary to have made
man” and even compares human beings to orangutans (Darwin’s
Notebook C, §77-79, written in 1838, Darwin 1987:263-4). And in 1863
– just 5 years after the first edition of Origin – T.H. Huxley began his
Evidence as to Man’s Place in Nature with a diagram of the human
skeleton juxtaposed to the apes to which Huxley argued he was related.
Darwin entered the fray most explicitly with the publication of his
The Descent of Man in 1871. In this work, Darwin makes use of the
increasingly wide acceptance of the notion that there are homologous
structures in man and the lower animals: “man is constructed on the
same general type or model with other mammals” (Darwin 1871/1902:
10). Like dogs and even pigeons, human beings have a heart, two lungs,
a skeletal structure including vertebrae, a skull, ribs, knees, and even
two distinct bones (radius and ulna) in the fore-arm/leg/wing. Darwin
uses this physical similarity between man and other animals for two
important and related purposes. First, it provides an important piece of
“evidence of the descent of man from some lower form” (9). Second, and
arguably even more importantly, Darwin uses the model of homologous
physical structures as an analogy for homologous mental structures.
Darwin argues both that “there is no fundamental difference between
man and the higher mammals in their mental faculties” (Darwin
237 1871/1902: 35, emphasis added) and that – therefore – the human
mind/soul is descended from some lower form just as much as the
human body. This shift from physical to mental homology is radical:
recall that Descartes, long before Darwin and without raising any
significant threat for religion, had argued that the human body could be
explained as the natural result of evolution by means of natural,
mechanical interactions of matter in motion. But Descartes reserved a
special place for the human soul, which, he claimed, was uniquely able
to explain humans’ rational superiority over animals. Likewise today,
many who are quite comfortable with the idea of humans’ physical
nature as naturally evolved nonetheless argue that there is something
special about humans requiring a separate creation.
Darwin would have no part in this idolizing of human beings. He
was, of course, insistent that “the difference in mental power between the
highest ape and the lowest savage [is] immense” (34). But he insisted
that animals share many supposedly “human” traits, including reason,
abstraction, and even ennui and a capacity for deceit (Darwin
1871/1902: 109, 117f., 102, 99). And, more importantly, he offered an
evolutionary account of the origin of humans’ most distinctive traits,
including language, higher cognitive faculties, morals, and even religious
belief. Among key aspects of his account are his evolutionary treatments
of language, religious belief, and a sense of beauty. But the most
important aspect of his evolutionary account of human beings is
Darwin’s discussion of the evolution of humans’ “moral sense” (Darwin
1871/1902: 134ff.). Darwin starts with a sympathy-based (broadly
Humean or Smithian) moral theory:
any animal whatever, endowed with well-marked social instincts . . .
would inevitably acquire a moral sense or conscience, as soon as its
intellectual powers had become as well, or nearly as well developed,
as in man. For, firstly, the social instincts lead an animal to take
pleasure in the society of its fellows, to feel a certain amount of
sympathy with them, and to perform various services for them. . .
Secondly, as soon as the mental faculties had become highly
developed, images of all past actions and motives would be
incessantly passing through the brain of each individual: and that
feeling of dissatisfaction, or even misery, which invariably results, as
we shall hereafter see, from any unsatisfied instinct, would arise, as
often as it was perceived that the enduring and always present social
instinct had yielded to some other instinct, at the time stronger, but
neither enduring in its nature, nor leaving behind it a very vivid
impression . . . Thirdly, after the power of language had been
acquired, and the wishes of the community could be expressed, the
238 common opinion how each member ought to act for the public good,
would naturally become in a paramount degree the guide to action.
But it should be borne in mind that however great weight we may
attribute to public opinion, our regard for the approbation and
disapprobation of our fellows depends on sympathy, which, as we
shall see, forms an essential part of the social instinct, and is indeed
its foundation-stone. (Darwin 1871/1902:135-6)
Darwin then makes use of his evolutionary account of the origin of
language and reasoning, to fill in the cognitive part of this process and
provides an evolutionary argument for the sympathy that is its
“foundation-stone.” As in the rest of his account of human beings,
Darwin emphasizes the similarities between human beings and other
animals, noting that humans are only one of a wide range of social
animals, and appealing to dogs in particular as examples of animals with
social instincts including love, sympathy, and self-command, even to the
point of “something very like a conscience” (Darwin 1871/1902: 142).
Having shattered the uniqueness of humans’ social affections, Darwin
proceeds to offer a general account of the advantages of social instincts
for the groups whose members have them, and thus of the likelihood that
those instincts will be passed on to offspring. Darwin even specifically
quotes, at the beginning of his discussion of human morals, Kant’s
description of our moral predisposition: “Duty! Wondrous thought . . .
before whom all appetites are dumb” (Darwin 1871/1902: 134-5). Rather
than taking this as an inexplicable human given, though, Darwin
explains its origin through his principle of evolution through natural
selection.
The implications of Darwinism for philosophy in general have been
profound. Within Descartes’ dualistic conception of the human being as
having a mechanistic body and a free immaterial mind-soul,
philosophical discussions of the nature of human beings could focus on
the human mind and thereby insulate themselves from the rise of
scientific accounts of the body. Alternatively, Romantic biology and its
Schellengian-Hegelian variations made even physical biology
fundamentally vitalist in a way that required philosophical reflection on
the purposes of nature. But Darwin provided a methodology for an
empirical biology that marginalized many sorts of reflections on human
nature that had dominated philosophy. Moreover, the scope of Darwin’s
theory seemed to include every aspect of human nature, leaving nothing
for philosophers of human nature to do except engage in Darwinian
biological research.
239 For Kant, Darwinism might seem particularly problematic. At the
most mundane and direct level, Darwin seemingly provided a refutation
of Kant’s philosophy of biology. Kant presumed that teleology was
intrinsic to the study of biological entities as such, but Darwin showed
how apparent teleology is merely the effect of a process of evolution by
natural selection that is not teleological at all. This rejection of teleology
at the foundation of biology could call into question the unification of
theoretical and practical reason that Kant sought to effect in his Critique
of Judgment. But Darwinism might also seem to pose even more serious
problems, since it suggests that the transcendental anthropology at the
core of Kant’s answer to the question “What is the human being?” is
fundamentally secondary to a revamped empirical anthropology. And
even within Kant’s empirical anthropology, Darwin suggests that the
most important part of any such anthropology is precisely the part that
Kant ignored: the description of how humans’ “predispositions” (in Kant’s
lingo) evolved from more primitive structures. Only such study can
provide real explanations for human nature, and given these
explanations, one can better understand the nature and role of the
faculties that Kant erroneously sought to explore through transcendental
philosophy. Moreover, the recognition of the way in which such
structures evolved will require giving up the idea that any human mental
powers are fundamentally fixed.
Of course, Darwin’s theory lacked sufficient evidence at the time,
and he left many issues unresolved, such as the sources of variations
amongst individuals – which, Darwin said, “seem to arise from . . .
unknown causes” (Darwin 1871/1902: 97) – and the specific biological
mechanisms by which advantageous traits were passed on to offspring.
But gaps in evidence were relatively insignificant in comparison with the
added explanatory power that it provided. The unresolved issues were
potentially more devastating in the early 20th century when the results of
Gregor Mendel’s work on genetics showed that traits were not heritable
in the way that Darwinian evolution seemed to require.163 But since
1953, when Watson and Crick discovered the molecular basis for
genetics in the DNA molecule, Darwinians have embarked upon a
“modern synthesis” of Darwinian selection and molecular genetics, one
that aims to provide an integrated and complete evolutionary account of
human beings.
163
For discussion of these issues, their resolution, and some remaining issues for Darwinism in the 21st
century, see Depew and Weber 1996 and Kitcher 1984.
240 III. Nietzsche, Art, and Literature
While Darwin and Marx helped shift the question “What is the
human being?” outside of the field of philosophy, Friedrich Nietzsche
(1844-1900), though trained as a philologist rather than a philosopher,
has become the most well-known and widely read 19th-century
philosopher of human nature. Unlike Darwin and Marx, however,
Nietzsche refuses to advance a particular answer to the question. His
philosophy of human nature can be seen as a continuation of the
Romantic appropriation of and response to Kant that we examined in the
last chapter. Like the Romantics, Nietzsche is anti-systematic and antimetaphysical, even employing the same aphoristic form cultivated by the
Romantics. Thus at the end of one of his most important articulations of
his philosophy, Nietzsche laments,
Alas, what are you after all, my written and painted thoughts! It was
not long ago that you were still so colorful, young, and malicious, full
of thorns and secret spices . . . and now? You have already taken off
your novelty, and some of you are ready, I fear, to become truths:
they already look so immortal, so pathetically decent, so dull! (BGE §
296, Nietzsche 1966: 236164)
While Nietzsche articulates provocative and important claims about
human nature, his writings are also permeated with a Romantic
resistance to theory that precludes his settling on any particular “theory”
of human “nature.” Nonetheless, important claims about human beings
can be gleaned from his writings, claims that he repeats, develops, and
reiterates, even if he would resist them being classified as “Nietzsche’s
answer” to Kant’s question.
Like the German Romantics, Nietzsche stresses creativity and
individuality over abstract rationality and universal duty. He pulls these
Romantic themes together with a sort of historicism – akin to Herder’s –
that emphasizes the contingency and a-rationality of the particular
systems of thought and morals that exist in the present. And Nietzsche
situates all of this in the context of an optimistic Schopenhauerian
conception of the will to power as an underlying creative force in the
universe that seeks ever higher forms of expression through a selfovercoming that always involves suffering and, at its best, involves a
creative suffering, “like pregnancy” (GM §2.19, Nietzsche 1967: 88). In
164
Throughout, references to Nietzsche provide both section numbers from particular works and the page
numbers in recent translations. Abbreviations for Nietzsche’s works are BGE for Beyond Good and Evil, Z
for Thus Spake Zarathustra, GM for On the Genealogy of Morals, GS for The Gay Science, and EH for
Ecce Homo.
241 relation to Kant, it will be helpful to emphasize four of Nietzsche’s
primary contributions to thinking about human beings: (1) his
genealogical methodology, whereby human cognition and morals are
seen as contingent historical-cultural perspectives; (2) his opposition to
certain metaphysical conceptions of the self, especially those involving a
coherent and unified “I” or a Kantian conception of human “freedom”; (3)
his perspectivism, which draws from but radicalizes Kant’s Copernican
turn; and (4) his conception of the “overman,” the idea that our current
configuration of moral and philosophical perspectives can and should be
overcome and that a new, higher type of human being can emerge.
Nietzsche’s impact has been most influential in thinking about
morals, and the title of his Genealogy of Morals – much like Darwin’s
Origin of Species – highlights the profound shift he aims to inaugurate.
Unlike the “stiff seriousness that inspires laughter” of “all our
philosophers” who “wanted to provide a rational foundation for morality,”
Nietzsche will
own up in all strictness to what is still necessary here for a long time
to come . . .: to collect material, to conceptualize and arrange a vast
realm of subtle feelings of value and differences of value which are
alive, grow, beget, and perish—and perhaps attempts to present
vividly some of the more frequent and recurring forms of such living
crystallizations—all to prepare a typology of morals. (BGE § 186,
Nietzsche 1966: 97)
Just as natural scientists required Darwin to shake them from
confidence in the fixity of species, so moral philosophers can thank
Nietzsche for shattering their assumption of a given, fixed morality for
which they could provide the “conditions of possibility.” As Nietzsche
puts it, “my curiosity as well as my suspicions were bound to halt quite
soon at the question of where our good and evil really originated . . .
[U]nder what conditions did man devise these value judgments good and
evil” (GM §Preface.3, Nietzsche 1967: 17).
It is not necessary to get into the details of Nietzsche’s account of
the origin of 19th century European values here. Throughout, he appeals
to social and natural forces in explaining shifts in human values,
pointing out, for example, how “the change which occurred when [man]
found himself finally enclosed within the walls of society and of peace”
gave “old instincts” a new – inward – direction (GM §2.16, Nietzsche
1967: 84, cf. BGE § 201). The most important shift, for Nietzsche,
involved turning away from a “noble morality” that was fundamentally
self-affirming, active, and strong, the morality of the ancient and heroic
242 Greeks, the morality of Achilles or – even earlier – Gilgamesh. For
Nietzsche, this morality was overturned in a “slave revolt” in morals, a
context where the weak and oppressed turned against their oppressors,
not through active revolt but through a subtle “revaluation of values”
that rejected as “vices” the strengths of the nobles and affirmed as
“virtues” the characteristics of the weak. As Nietzsche so eloquently puts
it, “Weakness is being lied into something meritorious . . . and impotence
which does not requite into ‘goodness of heart’; anxious lowliness into
‘humility’; subjection to those one hates into ‘obedience’” (GM §1.14,
Nietzsche 1967: 47). Kant’s emphasis on autonomy is recast as an
“instinct of obedience” to “formal conscience” (BGE §199, Nietzsche 1966:
110), a slavish and herdlike “morality as timidity” (BGE §197, Nietzsche
1966: 109). Against Kant’s “bad taste of wanting to agree with many”,
Nietzsche proclaims that “My judgment is my judgment; no one else is
entitled to it.” “How,” he asks,” should there be a ‘common good’ . . .
[W]hatever is common always has little value” (BGE § 43, Nietzsche
1966: 53). But as important as these descriptions of Kant’s morality as
common, timid, and slavish are, Nietzsche’s shift from justifying a
timeless morality transcendentally to describing the emergence, changes,
and possibilities of contingent moralities is – as we will see in more detail
in chapter nine – Nietzsche’s most lasting and influential “criticism” of
Kant.
For Nietzsche, the shift from justification to genealogy, and the
exposing of supposed philosophical truths as merely natural phenomena,
is not limited to morality:
Perhaps the time is at hand when it will be comprehended again and
again how little used to be sufficient to furnish the cornerstone for
such sublime and unconditional philosophers’ edifices as the
dogmatists have built so far: any old popular superstition from time
immemorial (like the soul superstition, which, in the form of the
subject and ego superstition, has not even yet ceased to do mischief);
some play on words, perhaps, a seduction by grammar, or an
audacious generalization of some very narrow, very personal, very
human, all too human, facts. (BGE, Preface, Nietzsche 1966:1)
The whole edifice of philosophical truths is built, for Nietzsche, on
contingent and historically emergent prejudices. In criticizing these
“philosophical truths,” Nietzsche offers general criticisms of metaphysical
systems, such as that “every great philosophy so far has been . . . the
personal confession of its author and a kind of unconscious and
involuntary memoir . . . [in which] the moral (or immoral) intentions . . .
constitute [its] real germ of life” (BGE §6, Nietzsche 1966: 13). And
243 Nietzsche also takes aim at concepts particularly important for Kant’s
philosophy. About the fundamental question of Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason, Nietzsche says,
[I]t is high time to replace the Kantian question, “How are synthetic
judgments a priori possible?” with another question, “Why is belief in
such judgments necessary?” – and to comprehend that such
judgments must be believed to be true, for the sake of the
preservation of creatures like ourselves, though they might, of
course, be false judgments for all that! (BGE § 11, Nietzsche 1966:
19).
Rather than a transcendental justification of the legitimacy of such
judgments, Nietzsche challenges his readers to think of the interests that
are served by them, and thus undermines the whole foundation of Kant’s
Critique. With respect to freedom, Nietzsche’s opposition to Kant is more
specific. First, he argues that while “[p]hilosophers are accustomed to
speak of freedom as if it were the best-known thing in the world,” in fact,
this approach only “adopt[s] a popular prejudice and exaggerate[s] it”
(BGE § 19, Nietzsche 1966: 25). The whole concept of “freedom” is “a sort
of rape and perversion of logic” and “nonsense” (BGE §21, Nietzsche
1966: 28). Against this empty, formal, nonsensical notion of freedom,
Nietzsche offers an alternative, wherein the “will” is a “complex of
sensation, thinking, and above all affect,” such that “freedom” is always
the freedom of one aspect of human nature to dominate others (BGE §
19, Nietzsche 1966: 25). Kant’s “transcendental freedom” is the
domination of a particular instinct over others, rather than – as Kant
supposed – a freedom from domination by instinct altogether. Once
willing is properly understood as “something complicated,” the sort of
metaphysical freedom appealed to by Kant is exposed for what it is, an
empty verbal embrace of an incoherent prejudice.
For Nietzsche, this general unmasking of philosophical pretensions
to “absolute truth” or “universality” was only part of a more general effort
to radicalize and relativize Kant’s Copernican turn in the service of a
perspectivism that would in turn pave the way for a more creative
approach to human existence. Nietzsche asks “under what conditions did
man devise value judgments good and evil?” only to go on to ask “and
what value to they themselves possess? Have they hitherto hindered or
furthered human prosperity?” (GM §Preface.3, Nietzsche 1967: 17). What
Kant saw as necessary conditions of the possibility of any human
experience become, in Nietzsche’s hands, particular prejudices of
244 particular ages, embodied in language and shared prejudices. In the
context of distinguishing between mere “philosophical laborers” and true
“philosophers,” Nietzsche explains the real value (for him) of mere
laborers like Kant.
It may be necessary for the education of a genuine philosopher that
he himself has once stood on all the steps on which . . . the scientific
laborers of philosophy remain standing . . . in order to pass through
the whole range of human values and value feelings and to be able to
see with many different eyes and consciences . . . Those philosophical
laborers after the noble model of Kant and Hegel have to determine
and press into formulas, whether in the realm of logic or political
(moral) thought or art, some great data of valuations–that is, former
positings of values, creations of value which have become dominant
and are for a time called “truths.” It is for these investigators to
make everything that has . . . been esteemed so far easy to . . . think
over, intelligible and manageable . . . Genuine philosophers, however,
are commanders and legislators: they say, “thus it shall be!” . . . With
a creative hand they reach for the future, and all that is and has been
becomes a means for them, an instrument, a hammer. (BGE § 211,
Nietzsche 1966: 136)
Kant’s transcendental analyses provide an invaluably deep and detailed
account of the conditions of possibility of particular ways of thinking,
feeling, and acting. But Nietzsche’s genealogies do more. They pave the
way for a truly creative revaluing of values, one within which
particularity, creativity, strength, and life would be affirmed.
Becoming conscious of the historical contingency of one’s values
and prejudices opens a new sphere of freedom, a recognition that values
and prejudices are precisely not an a priori that constrains us but a set
of tools to be utilized as we see fit. And insofar as we live – as Kant
argues – in a world that is in part the product of our presuppositions and
values, our power over these presuppositions is a power to create new
worlds: “it is enough to create new names and valuations to create new
‘things’” (GS §58, Nietzsche 1974: 122). There is, of course, something
frightening about this freedom.
We have forsaken the land and gone to sea! We have destroyed the
bridge behind us – more so, we have demolished the land behind us!
Now, little ship, look out! Beside you is the ocean . . . [T]here will be
hours when you realize that it is infinite and there is nothing more
awesome than infinity. Oh, the poor bird that has felt free and now
strikes against the walls of this cage! Woe, when homesickness for
245 the land overcomes you . . . and there is no more ‘land’! (GS § 124,
Nietzsche 1974: 180-1)
Having seen the contingency of all values, it is no longer possible to go
back to the naïve “a priori” to which we had only to submit. But
homesick nostalgia for unreflective naïveté is not the only possible
reaction to the death of our old prejudices and values, our old “God.”
[A]t hearing the news that ‘the old god is dead’, we philosophers and
‘free spirits’ feel illuminated by a new dawn; our heart overflows with
gratitude, amazement, forebodings, expectation—finally the horizon
seems clear again, even if not bright; finally our ships may set out
again, set out to face any danger; . . . the sea, our sea, lies open
again; maybe there has never been such an ‘open sea’. (GS § 343,
Nietzsche 1974:280)
For Nietzsche, the bases for our old values and morals are gone. We have
moved – or at least, should move – beyond good and evil. Some will
respond to this loss with despair. Most will respond with a self-deception
that refuses to admit the loss. Pretending that the old values still live,
they will throw themselves into business and “commonsense” to avoid
the reality that they are living on an open ocean. But this openness gives
rise to a new sort of ideal, an ideal of the true “philosopher” and “free
spirit,” the one who can respond to the loss of naïveté with honesty,
courage, and the strong creativity needed to form one’s own values.
This emphasis on creativity, on the possibility of new possibilities
for human beings, makes Nietzsche a philosopher of the future165. For
Nietzsche, “the human being is something that shall be overcome,” a
mere “rope” between “beast” and what Nietzsche calls der Übermensch,
literally that which is over, or beyond, the human being (Z, Nietzsche
1978: 12, 14). Given Nietzsche’s condemnation of universality, there is
not – and cannot be – a formula for what an Übermensch is. But
Nietzsche does lay out a few general visions of a future, better, humanity.
An Übermensch, unsurprisingly, will be creative and self-confident, not
seeking to accommodate his views to those of the masses but willing to
strike out on his own. This self-confidence goes further in Nietzsche’s
doctrine of the “eternal recurrence.” In describing Thus Spake
Zarathustra, Nietzsche claims that “the idea of the eternal recurrence” is
“the fundamental conception of this work” because this notion is “the
highest formula of affirmation that is at all attainable” (EH, Nietzsche
1967: 295). The thought that the world will repeat itself infinitely, that
165
See the subtitle to Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future.
246 “whatever was and is” will be “repeated into all eternity” (BGE § 56,
Nietzsche 1967: 68) is a thought that at first terrifies Zarathustra (the
protagonist of Thus Spake Zarathustra), but which ends up being
embraced in those moments when Zarathustra is most akin to the
Übermensch. The Übermensch will be the “opposite” of all of those lifedenying and pessimistic moralists; he is an “ideal of the most highspirited, alive, and world-affirming human being . . . shouting insatiably
da capo [repeat] – not only to himself but to the whole play and spectacle
[and] who makes [this whole play] necessary because again and again he
needs himself–and makes himself necessary” (BGE § 56, Nietzsche 1978:
68). The ideal person is so self-affirming that he is willing to affirm all of
the pettiness, misery, and evil in the world, and to affirm that again and
again, on the grounds that all of this was and is worth it because it went
into making a world that included himself.
But this self-affirmation also implies that the Übermensch live her
life in such a way that it can justify the world. “Übermensch” takes the
place of the “God” who is now dead and the moralities of mediocrity that
lived off God for centuries. While “once one said ‘God’ when one looked
upon distant seas,” Nietzsche now invites us to say “Übermensch” (Z,
Nietzsche 1978:85). And for Nietzsche, there is a crucial difference
between these ideals: “God is a conjecture, but I do not wish your
conjecturing to reach beyond your creating will. Could you create a
God?- Then, I pray you, be silent about all gods! But you could well
create the Übermensch” (Z, Nietzsche 1978:85). Nietzsche is ambivalent
about the full extent to which one can bring about the Übermensch – the
preceding quotation continues “Not perhaps you yourselves . . . but into .
. . forefathers of the Übermensch you could transform yourselves” – but
the Übermensch is, at least, a goal that is attainable in principle,
something towards which we can orient our active, creative powers
rather than someone to whom to submit. Thus Nietzsche (in the guise of
Zarathustra) asks, “What have you done to surpass humankind?” (Z,
Nietzsche 1978:12, my emphasis).
Unlike Darwin, Marx, and (as we will see) Freud whose legacy is
clearly identifiable in contemporary biology, psychology, and social
sciences, Nietzsche did not leave behind a discipline distinct from
philosophy. But Nietzsche’s legacy lingers today not only in the discipline
of philosophy itself, where he continues to be one of the most widely read
philosophers, but – perhaps more importantly – in the ever increasing
emphasis on art, literature, and now film as sources for answering the
question, “What is the human being?” In fact, just as some may be likely
to turn to biology or psychology as sciences that can answer that
question, those with a sense that there is more to being human than
what science can capture are at least as likely – if not more likely – to
247 turn to literature and art than to philosophy. And this emphasis on
literature as a source for thinking about humanity reflects deeply
Nietzschean impulses about the nature of that question. For one thing,
literature refuses to simplify human behavior into simply formulae or
universal rules; “common” literature is bad literature, and that which is
truly great is something particular, individual, extraordinary. Moreover,
good literature exposes its readers to a range of human possibilities,
opening new vistas and perspectives rather than simplifying all
perspectives into a taxonomy. And good literature (or art) is precisely the
literature worth reading and rereading, literature depicting the lives that
meet Nietzsche’s vision of the Übermensch who can reflect with pleasure
on the eternal return of all things because these are vindicated in her
own interesting, original, dynamic, and creative life.
IV. Freud and the Rise of Psychology
While Marx helped inaugurate the rise of history and social
sciences in general and Darwin brought new importance to biological
studies of human beings, Freud can be seen as one of the key figures166
166
Arguably, Wilhelm Wundt, though much less well-known than Freud, was at least as important
in the emergence of psychology as a viable science. Wundt was the first modern psychologist to set up a
lab, and he developed a systematic method for investigating human mental states that helped get
“psychology” as a discipline off the ground.
Wilhelm Wundt was born in 1832 in Mannheim and studied medicine at Tübingen and
Heidelberg, where he remained until 1874, spending most of this period working alongside Hermann von
Helmholtz, whose approach to human psychology was heavily influenced by both Kant and German
empiricists. In 1874, Wundt took a chair in “inductive philosophy” at the University of Zürich, and the
following year was appointed to a chair in philosophy at Leipzig. There Wundt set up a laboratory in
experimental psychology and set to work developing an experimental approach to the study of the human
mind. Wundt published extensively on a wide range of topics in psychology and philosophy, he had over
160 doctoral students work in his psychology laboratory, and he is widely credited with being the founder
of modern experimental psychology.
Wundt’s most important impact on the history of psychology was sociological rather than
philosophical. His laboratory-based psychological methodology and his large number of students were
significant in helping to establish experimental psychology as a viable new discipline at the end of the 19 th
century. Theoretically, Wundt helped establish psychology as a rigorous experimental science of purely
mental phenomena. Like Kant, Wundt focused on “special laws for our psychical life [that] . . . differ from
the universal physical ones” (Wundt 1912: 154), but unlike Kant, he insisted that psychology is not limited
to “the description of facts” but can attain the same level of “universally valid rules” as the natural sciences
(Wundt 1912: 156).166 Wundt articulated a variety of psychical laws, such as “the principle of intensifying
contrasts,” shown in the fact that a line surrounded by smaller lines will look larger than the same line seen
alone. And he developed a general theory of the basic “simple elements” of consciousness and their
combinations as a way of showing how relations amongst complex psychic phenomena can be explained in
terms of laws governing their simple elements. Wundt also uses his account of psychologically simple
248 behind the rising importance of psychology as a way of answering the
question,“What is the human being?” In some respects, Freud can be
seen as making Nietzsche’s emphasis on unconscious drives and
genealogies of morals into a rigorous psychological science distinct from
biology. At the beginning of the 20th century, Freud said:
You have been trained to find an anatomical basis for the functions of
the organism and their disorders, to explain them chemically and
physically and to view them biologically. But no portion of your
interest has been directed to psychical life, in which, after all, the
achievement of this marvelously complex organism reaches its peak.
For that reason psychological modes of thought have remained
foreign . . . This is the gap which psycho-analysis seeks to fill. It tries
to give psychiatry its missing psychological foundation . . . With this
aim in view, psycho-analysis must keep itself free from any
hypothesis that is alien to it, whether an anatomical, chemical, or
physiological kind, and must operate entirely with purely
psychological . . . ideas. (Freud 1920/1963: 23-4)
Freud here articulates a general mood at the beginning of the 20th
century, one that helped launch psychology, sociology, history, and even
“anthropology” (which in today’s English means something quite different
from what it meant in Kant’s German) as new realms of “human
sciences” not reducible to mere biology. This quotation makes it seem as
though there is a sharper contrast between psychology and biology than
exists today, and sharper than Freud intends. But while Freud admits
that psychological structures will ultimately be found to be based on
biological structures (see, e.g. Freud 1920/1963:315-6 and Freud 1914),
his more important point is that there is room for sciences that study
human beings empirically in ways that are not reducible to physical or
biological investigations. And these “human sciences,” among which
elements to highlight the distinction between psychological and physical laws, noting that while “there is
no psychical process . . . which does not run in parallel with a physical process . . ., a simple
[psychological] process . . . does not correspond to even a relatively simple . . . physical one” (Wundt 1912:
186).166 Wundt also continually refined his methodology, shifting away from brute introspection and
towards a more rigorously experimental method that isolated simple mental processes as a basis for further
carefully constructed experiments to get at more complex phenomena. (In his Introduction to Psychology
(Wundt 1912), for example, the auditory cognition of patterns of beats on a metronome gets dozens of
pages of discussion.) Ultimately, Wundt provided a theoretically justified methodology for experimental
psychology, a set of theories and concepts further psychologists could develop and correct, and a cohort of
well-trained experimental psychologists who would go on to help found an autonomous discipline of
empirical psychology that could compete with and/or supplement philosophy and biology in providing
answers to the question, “What is the human being?”
249 psychology still dominates today, have transformed our conceptions of
human beings.
Sigmund Freud (1856-1939), the inventor of psycho-analysis, is
perhaps best known for a whole set of popular theories and expressions,
such as “Freudian slips,” penis-envy, the Oedipal complex, the thesis
that all neuroses can be traced to childhood sexuality, and, more
generally, a basic obsession with sex in mental life. But Freud played an
important part in the emergence of modern empirical psychology. He
insisted that psychology should be an empirical science, emphasizing
that “the psycho-analytic view is . . . empirical – either a direct
expression of observations or the outcome of a process of working them
over” (Introductory Lectures, p. 302) and comparing psycho-analysis with
astronomy, as two subjects in which “experimentation is particularly
difficult” but which can nonetheless make inferences based on
observations (see, e.g., New Introductory Lectures, p. 27). Moreover,
Freud emphasized the distinction between psychology and physiology
and thereby helped provide a realm of its own to scientific psychology.
Importantly, Freud also emphasized the clinical and therapeutic
importance of non-physiological psychology and helped establish a model
for productive interaction between clinical and theoretical work in
psychology.
But Freud’s most important contribution, not only to modern
empirical psychology but also to modern conceptions of the human being
more generally, was his emphasis on unconscious mental processes and
structures, a key difference between his psycho-analysis and other
contemporary approaches to psychology, such as that of Wilhelm Wundt.
Where Wundt claims that psychology “has to investigate the facts of
consciousness, its combinations and relations, so that it may ultimately
discover the laws which govern these thoughts and combinations”
(Wundt 1912: 1),167 Freud did not think that empirical psychology was
limited to mental phenomena that were directly “observable” in inner
sense. Rather, he suggested—or rather insisted–that the most important
mental phenomena were unconscious and thus that empirical psychology
would have to be indirect. Thus, for example, Freud argues that slips of
the tongue and dreams “have a sense . . ., meaning, intention, [and]
purpose” (Freud 1920/1963: 74)168, but asks “To whom?” (Freud
167
To be fair, Wundt admits the influence of “dark…fields of consciousness” (Wundt 1912: 74, 107, 10910) and even the influence of past associations between ideas that might not be in consciousness at any
given moment but can affect what does arise in consciousness. In that sense, Wundt anticipates the broad
conception of the unconscious on which Freud would later focus.
168
For elaborate discussion of slips of the tongue and similar phenomena, see Freud 1901/1960. For
dreams, see Freud 1900/1965, 1920/1963(Part II ), and Freud 1933/1964: ch. 29.
250 1920/1963: 267). That is, we can best interpret certain actions and
conscious mental processes as expressing aims and purposes of which
one is not conscious or even consciously rejects. But then the
psychologist must posit unconscious aims and purposes operative in
one’s mental life. Today, even if relatively few psychologists are
“Freudian” in any strict sense of the term, virtually all empirical
psychologists agree that inner sense is an unreliable indicator of one’s
mental processes, that one must use indirect means to discern what is
really going on in the mind of a human being, and that the
analyst/experimenter can often know what is going on in a person’s
mind better than the person herself.169
Freud was well aware of the importance of his emphasis on the
unconscious: “the hypothesis of their being unconscious mental
processes paves the way to a decisive new orientation in the world and
science” (Freud 1920/1963: 26). Just as Kant’s “Copernican” turn –
discussed in chapter one – was one of his most important claims about
the human being, Freud’s most important and lasting impact on the
question what is the human being comes from his own appropriation of
Copernicus. As Freud puts it in his Introductory Lectures on
Psychoanalysis:
In the course of two centuries, the naïve self-love of men has had to
submit to two major blows at the hands of science. The first was
when they learnt that our earth was not the center of the universe
but only a tiny fragment of a cosmic system of scarcely imaginable
vastness. This is associated in our minds with the name of
Copernicus . . . . The second blow fell when biological research
destroyed man’s supposedly privileged place in creation and proved
his descent from the animal kingdom and his ineradicable animal
nature. This revaluation has been accomplished in our own days by
Darwin . . . But human megalomania will have suffered its third and
most wounding blow from the psychological research of the present
day which seeks to prove to the ego that it is not even master in its
own house, but must content itself with scanty information of what is
going on unconsciously in its mind. We psycho-analysts were not the
first and not the only ones to utter this call to introspection; but it
seems to be our fate to give it its most forcible expression and to
support it with empirical material which affects every individual.
Hence arises the general revolt against our science. (Freud
1920/1963: 352-3)
169
For some classic examples of positing psychological processes of which one is not conscious, see
Nisbett and Wilson 1977.
251 Like Kant, Freud compares his own radical revolution to that of
Copernicus. But whereas Kant turns back towards placing humanity at
the center of the universe, Freud – like Copernicus – continues a
trajectory of undermining our privileged sense of self. Freud’s revolution,
however, goes radically further than either Copernicus or Darwin
because Freud challenges our centrality in our own lives. For Freud,
much of who “I” am is not up to me. Not only am I not the center of the
universe, nor even the pinnacle of life on earth; I am not even the most
important force in my own soul.
As the preceding passage shows, Freud did not limit his conception
of “unconscious” to rare and relatively unimportant mental processes of
which one might not be aware at the moment. Freud shifts from
“unconscious” as “the name of what is latent at the moment” to a whole
theory of the unconscious as “a particular realm of the mind with its own
wishful impulses, its own mode of expression, and its particular mental
mechanisms” (Freud 1920/1963: 262). As his thought develops, he
refines the structure of this realm of the mind, such that in his mature
theory, the human mind can be seen as structured along two axes. On
the one hand, there is a distinction between the conscious, the preconscious, and the unconscious. The “preconscious” is an “unconscious
that is only latent and thus [that] easily becomes conscious” (Freud
1933/1964: 89, cf. Freud 1920/1963: 366-8), while the unconscious
strictly speaking is further from consciousness. The “transformation” of
what is truly unconscious to consciousness is difficult, requiring for its
possibility something like psycho-analysis, and this transformation is
always incomplete (Freud 1933/1964: 89). One the other hand, cutting
across the divide between conscious and unconscious processes is a
threefold distinction between the id (literally das es, or ‘the it’), the ego
(literally das ich, or ‘the I’), and the super-ego.170 The ego is what one
normally considers one’s self, the generally-conscious, self-aware,
decision-making regulator of one’s life, the “reason and good sense” that
must “guide the powerful movement” of the id (Freud 1933/1964: 95-6).
The super-ego performs the functions of “self-observation, conscience,
and [maintaining] one’s ideals” (Freud 1933/1964: 83). What Kant calls
the “predisposition to personality,” the conscience against which one
measures one’s activities and evaluates them morally, is, for Freud, the
“super-ego.”
170
This account is different from Freud’s early theory in two important respects. In his early work, Freud
had not yet distinguished between the ego and the super-ego, and he had identified the ego with
consciousness and what he would later term the id with unconscious processes. For his most detailed
discussions of this shift, see Freud 1923/1960 and Freud 1933/1964 (chapter 31).
252 The id is Freud’s most important contribution to the theory of
human nature: “The space [in the mind] occupied by the unconscious id
[is] incomparably greater than that of the ego or the preconscious” (Freud
1933/1964: 98); in fact, all of the parts of the mind are really just
modifications of the id, such that, for instance, the ego is “the better
organized part of the id, with its face turned towards reality” (Freud
1933/1964: 116). The id is “the dark inaccessible part of our personality
. . ., a chaos, a cauldron fully of seething excitations . . . [It] knows . . .
no good and evil, no morality . . . [but only] instinctual cathexes seeking
discharge” (Freud 1933/1964: 91). The ego is subject to a “reality
principle” that requires that it moderate its desires so that they are
consistent both with each other and with what is possibly achievable in
the world. But in the id, “contrary [and unrealistic] impulses exist side
by side” (Freud 1933/1964: 92). The law of non-contradiction and even
“the philosophical theorem that space and time are necessary forms of
our mental acts” do not apply to the id, where “no alteration . . . is
produced by the passage of time.” The fundamental principles of the id
are the pleasure principle, which Freud associates pre-eminently with
sexual desire, and a principle of self-destruction and aggression.171 The
particular fixations and excitations of the id arise partly from innate
natural instincts, partly from unconscious cultural inheritances, and
largely from events – especially in infancy and childhood – that had a big
effect on structuring one’s sexual and aggressive desires but that one
refuses, for various reasons, to admit to consciousness. Thus the famous
Oedipal Complex arises from innate sexual desires in infancy that focus
on the mother as a desire-object. Particular and forgotten details of one’s
infantile relationship with one’s mother can then exercise powerful but
unconscious influences on one’s later life.
In relation to Kant, Freud’s most important challenges relate to the
general problem of self-knowledge and to the specific issue of the origin
and nature of morality. With respect to self-knowledge, Freud is arguably
even more modest that Kant’s own claim that “we can never, even by the
most strenuous self-examination, get entirely behind our own covert
incentives” (4:407). But in Kant, this strong claim implied only a fairly
straightforward humility about self-knowledge and was conjoined with
what remained a fairly naïve approach to psychological investigation, one
that privileged introspection and relatively straightforward inferences of
motives from actions. Freud’s complex psychic architecture, his
willingness to posit unconscious forces radically at odds with what we
experience in conscious life, and his development of a specific
171
See Beyond the Pleasure Principle (Freud 1920/1961) and New Introductory Lectures (Freud
1933/1964), especially chapters 32 and 34.
253 psychoanalytic methodology for unlocking the secrets of this
unconscious all take him in a very different direction from Kant.
Far more important than his particular Copernican turn, however,
is Freud’s revaluation of the value of conscience.172 For Kant, what it
ultimately means for a human being to reach his potential is for him to
live autonomously, to live in accordance with the normative principles of
thought, feeling, and action that arise from his participation in an
intelligible world. In Freudian terms, Kant advocates a complete
subordination of one’s id (or “untamed passions,” Freud 1933/1964: 95)
and even one’s ego to one’s super-ego, one’s conscience. But while Freud
shares with Kant a commitment to articulate “rational explanations” for
moral requirements rather than ascribing them to divine decree (Freud
1927/1961), he does not see the super-ego as the unconditionally good
expression of human autonomy. Freud’s “rational explanation” is
ultimately in terms of the realistic satisfaction of desires rather than a
defense of a categorically valid imperative governing humans as members
of an intelligible realm. Even the super-ego, which arguably issues
categorical imperatives, is seen by Freud as an internalization of one’s
infantile fear of punishment from one’s parents and Oedipal desire to
please one’s mother (Freud 1933/1964: 77f.). It is a “vehicle of tradition”
(Freud 1933/1964: 84) and largely responsible for the repressions and
neuroses that haunt people in their adult lives. In sharp contrast to the
moral-prudential goals of Kant’s pragmatic anthropology, “the
therapeutic efforts of psychoanalysis have [the] intention . . . to
strengthen the ego, to make it more independent of the super-ego . . . so
that it can appropriate fresh portions of the id” (Freud 1933/1964: 99).
While Freud’s specific insights have waxed and waned in terms of
their importance for contemporary psychological practice,173 his legacy
continues to influence contemporary thinking about the human being in
at least four important ways. First, Freud brought the unconscious mind
into center stage for psychological explanation of human thought and
action. Today, even those who distance themselves from Freud’s specific
theories often continue to think of mental life on the model of competing
(or cooperating) psychic forces of which one is only rarely conscious.
Second, there continue to be vibrant psychoanalytic practices, and
psychoanalytic techniques for diagnosing and treating mental disorders
continue to be used in contemporary medical psychiatry. Third, near the
172
Arguably, this is a point Freud took from Nietzsche.
Peter Kramer, for example, notes that at Harvard Medical School in the 1970s, “there was no distinction
between studying psychiatry and following Freud” (Kramer 2006: 10), but many psychology textbooks
today largely dismiss him.
173
254 end of his career, Freud applied his general models of explanation to
historical and cultural analysis, where they continue to be widely
appropriated by anthropologists and cultural critics. And finally and
most importantly, Freud’s Copernican Revolution continues to exercise a
profound influence on general human self-conceptions. The sort of naïve
assertions of self-awareness that dominated earlier attempts to know and
express oneself have been replaced by suspicion of our own selfawareness and a willingness to accept that who we are is largely the
product of psychological forces that we do not control and of which we
are often unaware.
V. Conclusion.
The last book that Kant published during his lifetime, published
just after his Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, was entitled
The Conflict of the Faculties. The book consists of three essays, taking on
each of the three academic “faculties” – what we would now call
“departments” or “disciplines” – against which philosophy, at the the end
of Kant’s life, was contending for relevance. At the end of the 18th
century, these competitors were limited to jurisprudence, medicine, and,
first and foremost, theology. The targets were misplaced, but the title of
Kant’s work remains apt. There is still a conflict of faculties for
dominance in answering the question of what the human being is, with
biology, psychology, sociology, history, “anthropology” (in the modern
sense), literature, art, and literary theory taking the place of theology. For
a brief period culminating in Kant and Hegel and in what Nietzsche aptly
described as the “death of God,” philosophy dominated cultural
reflections on what it means to be human. But as theology receded,
philosophy increasingly lost its influence to other arts and sciences.
This chapter has surveyed four of the most important figures who
helped bring about this shift, and whose conceptions of human nature
continue to be profoundly relevant and deeply influential today. In very
different ways, Marx, Darwin, Nietzsche, and Freud helped open new
vistas for understanding ourselves. Even within philosophy, many of the
most important ways of addressing the question of human beings go
back to one or more of these four thinkers. But each also helped shift
Kant’s question out of philosophy, into biology, psychology, other human
sciences, and the arts. In the next chapter, we will take up the
contemporary philosophical heirs of Darwin and Freud, who seek
255 answers in the sciences of biology and psychology. Chapter nine turns to
thinkers who emphasize the contingency, historicity, and diversity of
human natures, drawing from the historical and genealogical approaches
of Marx and (especially) Nietzsche. And in chapter ten, we look at
existentialist approaches to the self, approaches that in many respects
trace themselves to Nietzsche’s movement “beyond good and evil,”
towards a radically self-affirming conception of the (super-)human self.
256 Chapter 8: Scientific Naturalism
When Kant answered the question “What is the Human Being?,”
biologists still took seriously the idea that every human being might
literally and physically have “pre-existed” in Eve’s womb174 and that
species were eternal creations. Kant himself despaired of finding a
“Newton . . . of a blade of grass” (5:400) and emphasized that scientists
“do not know cranial nerves and fibers, nor do [they] know how to put
them to use” (7:119). Empirical psychology was based more on
introspection than strict scientific methodology and was not yet
distinguished from philosophy.
Things have changed. Consider just a few highlights of our
scientific knowledge about human beings:
o The Human Genome Project has successfully mapped humans’
genetic code and we increasingly understand both where we came
from and how our genes direct our development
o MRI and CT scans have detailed the structure of the brain
o
PET and fMRI scans can now track the brain activity of human
beings involved in specific mental tasks
o Studies on non-human primates have shown possible origins of
human altruism, language, culture, and even our sense of justice.
o Psychologists have developed models of unconscious motivation,
and new methodologies (such as neural mapping, controlled
correlational studies, and double-blind experiments) have begun to
transform empirical psychology into a rigorous science.
In addition to these very general developments, scientists have recently
made a number of counter-intuitive discoveries with the potential to
dramatically change our sense of what it is to be human. For just a few
examples,
o Benjamin Libet and others provide evidence suggesting that
unconscious physical processes in the brain precede and cause
conscious choices
o A biases and heuristics program in contemporary psychology offers
evidence that irrationality is widespread and unrecognized even in
the most careful and thoughtful human beings
o Situationist psychology provides evidence that much human
behavior is determined by context rather than by character
174
Perhaps even more dramatically, scientists like Anton Leeuwenhoek – the first scientist to observe
sperm with a microscope – and Nicolaas Hartsoeker argued against this view with purported observations
in microscopes of very tiny human forms seen within male spermatozoa.
257 These developments cover only a small fraction of the progress in human
biology and psychology, without even mentioning the contributions of
economics, sociology, anthropology and history to understanding human
beings.
Taken together, this scientific progress not only calls into question
fundamental aspects of Kant’s anthropology but also offers some hope
that the question “What is the human being?” can be answered by
science rather than philosophy. In other words, scientific progress
provides hope for scientific naturalism about human beings. Scientific
naturalism is the view that everything that is real is part of nature, the
world that is investigated by the natural sciences (including biology and
scientific psychology). Generally, people tend to think that questions
such as “What is the emu?” or “What is the monarch butterfly” or “What
is oxygen?” are sufficiently answered, in principle at least, by fully
developed scientific accounts of emus, butterflies, or oxygen. Many have
suggested that human beings are not fundamentally any different, that
the best answer to the question “What is the human being?” is just
whatever our best biological and/or psychological theories say the
human being is. Philosophy has nothing distinctive to contribute to
understanding human beings; instead philosophy should simply “clarify
and unify” what is given by science (Dennett 2003:15).
One task of this chapter is to explain and critique scientific
naturalists’ answers to Kant’s question. Because Kant’s way of dealing
with science is not naturalist in this sense, this chapter also provides
Kantian responses to recent scientific developments. Given the breadth
of empirical research on human beings and the range of naturalist
approaches to human beings, this chapter limits itself to discussing a
few highlights from recent empirical research and its philosophical
appropriation. By the end of my brief survey, I hope that simplistic
reactions to naturalism will become more complicated. Naturalism does
not flow as neatly from the progress of science as its proponents might
have hoped, but it also has much more adequate resources for dealing
with important aspects of our self-conception (such as freedom,
creativity, and morals) than many of its opponents feared. Moreover,
understanding human beings as natural beings provides valuable
resources for actually helping us to be better human beings, but the
value of science is greatest, I argue, when its insights are incorporated
into a broadly Kantian anthropological framework.
Because scientific naturalism often involves a commitment to
“materialism” – the view that there is nothing non-material (such as a
soul) – and “reductionism” – the view that non-physical processes such
258 as cognition can be understood in terms of (or “reduced to”) physical
processes, I start by looking at the most thoroughly materialist and
reductionist approach to human beings: cognitive neuroscience, which
investigates human reasoning, emotion, decision-making, and even
creativity from the standpoint of physical processes in the brain. I then
turn to evolutionary biology, which provides an account of how human
beings have developed from more primitive biological ancestors. Such an
account is necessary to complete the materialist naturalism of
neuroscience, since without an account of the origin of the brain, one
might posit – as some creationists do – that even if what it is to be
human can be explained physically, the physical structure of the brain
could not have come about through natural processes. Evolutionary
biology also provides a scientific methodology for thinking about human
beings that is not wholly dependent on neuroscience, and thus opens the
door to a different sort of naturalist explanation of cognition,
consciousness, culture, morals, and even freedom. Finally, I examine
current trends in empirical psychology. Psychological naturalism is
consistent with materialism but does not depend on it. One can hold that
empirical psychology provides everything we need to explain the human
mind without believing that psychological processes are reducible to
physical processes. And philosophers have increasingly used
psychological theories about human beings to develop naturalistic
approaches to epistemology (what we can know) and ethics (what we
should do).
I. Human Brains: Neuroscience and the Philosophy of Mind
In 1848, 50 years after the publication of Kant’s Anthropology, an
accidental explosion sent an iron rod through the head of Phineas Gage,
a railroad worker in Vermont. After recovering from the initial shock,
Gage arose, rode into town awake and alert, and saw a doctor. Within
two months, Gage was said to be cured, and by all indications was
perfectly functional. But whereas Gage before the accident had been a
polite, well-balanced, self-disciplined worker; Gage after the accident was
“fitful, irreverent, indulging . . . in the grossest profanity . . ., manifesting
but little deference for his fellows . . ., capricious and vacillating”
(Valenstein 1986:90, cf. Damasio 1994). A physical alteration to Gage’s
brain seems to have engendered a wholesale transformation in his
character.
259 Gage’s case is not unique; physical brain injuries have long caused
mental and dispositional changes in human beings. And recent years
have brought increasingly fine-tuned accounts of the parts of the brain
responsible for different mental functions. At first, such scientific
developments occurred primarily through careful analyses of victims of
accidents like Gage’s. But since the mid-1970s, PET and fMRI scans
have made it possible to scan the brains of normally functioning adults
performing different mental tasks. This brought neuroscience to a whole
new level, resulting in increasingly fine-tuned maps of different control
centers in the brain. Scientists have identified specific parts of the frontal
and temporal lobes as loci of linguistic activity, a primary projection area
in the parietal lobe that controls most moter activity, and C-fibers in
peripheral nerves of the somatosensory area that are instrumental in
feeling pain. At the same time, studies of neurons and glial cells at the
cellular level help scientists understand brain activity and development.
While direct studies of brain activity have been an important
source of greater understanding of the physiological bases of human
mental life, other developments have provided analogies and models for
thinking about the brain. Computers have been particularly important in
two phases of thinking about the neurobiological basis of cognition. Even
before functional computers existed, the idea of the brain as a computer
was posited as a metaphor for thinking about human mental processes.
The “Turing Machine,” an early theoretical model for a sort of machine
that could engage in basic “cognitive” tasks such as arithmetic and the
contruction of grammatically correct sentences, is now a commonplace
metaphor for human cognition. In the early days of computing, the
dominant model was to think of the brain as a sort of linearly processing
computer. With the rise of computer networks as powerful technology,
the idea of a “neural network” has taken off as a model for thinking
about the brain. Just as computers can be networked together, neurons
can be networked together to create an “everything-connected-toeverything” neural network capable of building connections based on
past experience.175 Even more recently, the use of “parallel processing” in
computing – where multiple computers work on different parts of a
process “in parallel” and then reassemble the results – has been used a
model for humans’ “unconscious parallel processing (in which many
inputs are processed at the same time, each by its own mini-processor)”
(Pinker 1997: 140).
Applying these neuroscientific discoveries to thinking about the
human mind and its relationship with the brain has become a central
175
For a helpful discussion relating neural networks to computer networks, see Pinker 1997: 99-131.
260 problem within the subfield of philosophy called “philosophy of mind.”
One view of the mind, which might seem to be the most intuitive
implication of the close correlation between brain-states and mentalstates, is “eliminativist materialism” about mental properties, the
“identification of mental states with physical states,” such that what
seem to be mental states are really physical states. Paul Churchland
compares the case with that of color: “In discriminating red from blue . . .
our external senses are actually discriminating between subtle
differences in intricate electromagnetic . . . properties of physical objects
. . . The same is presumably true of our ‘inner’ sense: introspection”
(Churchland 1984: 29). Such a view represents a strong scientific
naturalism, in that there is nothing more to human beings than our
(neuro)physiology.176 It also implies materialism and reductionism: what
seems mental is really physical, and psychology is wholly reducible to
neurobiology. As Daniel Dennett has put it, “there is only one sort of
stuff, namely matter – the physical stuff of physics, chemistry, and
physiology – and the mind is somehow nothing but a physical
phenomenon. In short, the mind is the brain” (Dennett 1991: 33).
There are some important problems with eliminativism, however,
that have led philosophers of mind to articulate alternatives. Three of the
most important problems are qualia, multiple-realizability, and
intentionality/normativity. The term “qualia” refers to the subjective feel
of particular mental states. As Thomas Nagel puts it in his famous essay,
“What is it like to be a Bat?”, the subjective character of an organism’s
mental states entails that “there is something that it is like to be that
organism-- something it is like for the organism” (Nagel 1974:476).177
Many philosophers have come to think that it is precisely this subjective
character of our mental states that makes the mind irreducible to the
brain states investigated by neurobiology. The problem of multiple
realizability arises for many attempts at reductionism, including the
reduction of the mind to the brain. In its most basic form, the problem is
that phenomena that appear at one level of explanation are realizable in
many different ways at a different level of explanation. Pain, for example,
might be instantiated in many different neurobiological configurations.
And even if these all share a common element in humans (such as the
firing of C-fibers), one might find other animals (and one could certainly
176
Obviously no one would deny that, in some sense, our physiology more broadly is part of what it is for
us to be human. But contemporary philosophers and scientists, like Kant, typically emphasize the human
mind as particularly distinctive to human nature. That said, there has been an increased attention in recent
years to the way in which the “mind” may be located, not in the brain per se, but in the body as a whole or
even beyond the body in the world in which we live (see Dennett 2003 and Noe 2009.)
177
For a helpful overview (with bibliography) of recent discussions of qualia, see Tye 2007.
261 imagine other creatures) that feel pain with a different neurobiological
architecture (with some other neural element playing the role of C-fibers)
(see Putnam 1967). Moreover, there may well be psychological laws that
cannot be formulated in physical terms, because of the different ways in
which psychological states can be realized. A simple psychological law
(like “fear of a lion provokes a fight or flight response”) might be
untranslatable into strictly physical terms since the physical states
associated with a particular instance of fear might not fit into a
physically delineable type that would be consistently correlated with a
physically delineable type of effect corresponding to “fight or flight.”
Insofar as psychological laws are both informative and untranslatable,
eliminativism fails to capture the whole truth about human mental life.
The problems of intentionality and normativity come from the fact that
many human mental states seem to about something and/or have the
potential of being right or wrong. One is not merely afraid, but afraid of a
lion. One does not merely have a belief-state, one believes (rightly or
wrongly) that the lion is going to attack you. One does not merely have a
volitional state, one decides (rightly or wrongly) to run away from the
lion. In each case, one seems to simply have a brain-state. And while a
brain state can be caused by something else (say, the perception of a
lion), it is not clear how a brain state can be of something else, nor how a
brain-state could be true or false or right or wrong (it just is what it is).178
These three considerations have led many philosophers of mind to
develop alternatives to eliminative materialism about the mind. One
alternative is Descartes’s substance-dualism. Descartes was well aware
of the close connections between mental states and the brain179 but saw
mental changes as irreducible to physical brain-changes. Instead,
Descartes described the mind-brain connection as a mutual influence
between two distinct substances: a non-material soul, or mind, and a
material part of the brain. The soul experiences qualia and engages in
intentional, normatively-governable mental activity. The body is purely
material and acts on other material things. These two substances are
capable of interaction, so that changes in one can cause changes in the
other, but neither is reducible to the other and either could in principle
persist without the other.
178
These examples differ in important respects. Intentionality is not identical with normativity, and
different forms of normativity (epistemic, prudential, moral) are not identical with one another. But
intentionality and the normative dimensions of mental states all raise a common problem for eliminativism,
which is that we ascribe properties to mental states that seem untranslatable, even in principle, into
anything that could be said of a brain-state.
179
He even famously located the “pineal gland” in the brain as the locus of higher cognitions in human
beings.
262 Currently, most philosophers of mind reject both substancedualism and eliminativism in favor of a more complex view that can be
called functionalist property-dualism with token-identity between mental
and physical states (Botterill and Carruthers 1999). Each element of this
description is important. Property-dualism is way of responding to the
problems with crude materialism without falling into a full-blown
substance-dualism. The idea is that there are two irreducibly distinct
sorts of properties of human beings, our physical properties and our
mental properties. These are not different substances, but they are
irreducible to one another, such that one could make true claims about
the mind – say, claims about qualia or connections between mental
states – that could not be translated into claims about the brain.
Functionalism is a way of making sense of what one refers to when one
describes a particular type of mental state: “functionalists characterize
mental states in terms of their [functions or] causal roles, particularly, in
terms of the causal relations to sensory stimulations, behavioral outputs,
and other mental states” (Block 1980:172, cf. Putnam 1967). And tokenidentity is the view that each particular mental state “token” – such as
the initial feeling of pleasure I experienced last night as I began eating
dessert – is identical to a particular brain-state “token.” This provides for
an important measure of materialism, since each individual mental state
is identical to a particular physical brain-state, but it avoids problem of
multiple realizability, since each type of mental state can be realized in
many different types of brain-state (see Davidson 1970).
To some, Kant’s view on the relationship between mental states
and brain-states might seem similar to Descartes’s substance-dualism.
Kant distinguishes between the noumenal thing-in-itself and the
phenomenal appearances, and Kant specifically applies this distinction
to human beings, who are both transcendentally free things-inthemselves and embodied, empirical appearances. But this apparent
parallel with Cartesian dualism is misleading. While Kant makes use of
the distinction between transcendental and empirical anthropology to
make sense of some of the problems that lead philosophers of mind
towards various dualisms, his own account of Cartesian dualism locates
this dualism within the realm of appearances (see e.g. 28:680-1). In fact,
since the category of “substance” is a category that structures the
empirical world, Kant’s distinction between things-in-themselves and
appearances cannot, except in an analogical sense, be considered a
“substance-dualism” at all. For Kant, the “mind” is an empirical object
available to inner sense, and Kant must therefore ask to what extent this
empirical mind is reducible to something purely physical. Kant thus
distinguishes empirical-substance-dualism, by virtue of which the mind
263 and body would be empirically distinct substances, from transcendentaldualism, according to which the mind-in-itself must be distinguished
from the empirically-knowable-mind.180
Kant is certainly committed to a transcendental-idealist-dualism
that implies two irreducible perspectives on mental life. Transcendental
anthropology is distinct from empirical anthropology, and insofar as
there is an empirical mind, it can be distinguished from its noumenal
ground. But it is far from obvious that substance dualism is needed to
preserve both a standpoint on the mind-in-itself that is irreducible to
empirical descriptions and the possibility of normative claims about
human thoughts, feelings, and choices. Even if some metaphysics of
mind is needed to ground this distinction between standpoints –
something about which contemporary interpreters of Kant sharply
disagree – one could simply draw on a sort of transcendental property
dualism according to which the human mind has properties “in-itself”
that are irreducible to its empirical properties.181 Kant’s transcendental
idealism thus commits him to some sort of dualism, but not to a
distinction between two interacting substances. And in this way, Kant
actually provides a way in which one can be a materialist about the
empirical mind while reserving a space for normativity and other “fromwithin” aspects of the mind understood transcendentally.
Kant’s transcendental idealism also does not commit him to any
empirical dualism. Within the realm of appearances, Kant could accept a
strictly eliminativist philosophy of mind without threatening his
transcendental anthropology. Even Kant’s empirical anthropology could
be preserved on an eliminativist reading. One would simply need to
translate the psychological laws that Kant lays out there into physical
180
For discussions of Kant’s philosophy of mind, see Ameriks 1982a, Aquila 1983, and Brook 1994. There
could be yet a third dualism, which we could call transcendental-ground-dualism, by virtue of which the
transcendental ground of the mind is distinct from the transcendental ground of the body. If there is any
argument for transcendental-ground-dualism, it would be a moral one. Since we hold people responsible for
their choices, we can identify a free noumenal ground for those choices. Since we do not hold them
responsible for their physical states in general, we might think that the noumenal ground of physical states
for which we are not morally responsible is different than the ground of states for which we are morally
responsible. Kant does not offer this argument, and his transcendental anthropology need not commit him
to this distinction, but it opens up room for a new, morally-grounded, way of thinking about something like
a mind-body dualism. (For Kant, we are never responsible for bodily states themselves, but only for certain
higher volitions that might have bodily conditions or effects. There are, however, lots of mental states for
which one is not directly responsible – including most perceptions, cognitions, and emotions – so the
sphere of the “body” would be much wider than what we normally think of as our physical body.)
181
For a discussion of different approaches to the metaphysics of the transcendental-empirical distinction,
see chapter one and Ameriks 1982b. It is noteworthy that even as Ameriks raises serious problems for nonmetaphysical readings of Kant’s transcendental idealism, he tacitly endorses a “two-aspect” rather than
“two-substance” reading of human agents.
264 laws of the brain. Kant’s claim that “feelings depend on cognitions” would
become a claim about the dependence of certain brain-states upon
others. And underlying natural predispositions would be reducible to
structural limitations on the physical operations of the brain.
Nonetheless, Kant rejects eliminativism for two main reasons.
First, because “the soul can perceive itself only through the inner sense”
(12:35) and inner sense is purely temporal while the physical body is
always spatiotemporal, the most that physiological explanation could
ever do it to explain “the matter that makes possible” mental phenomena
(12:35). Mental phenomena as such have a character that is irreducible
to the physical. The content of an inner experience – a feeling of fear, for
example – thus cannot be identical to the content of an observed brainstate. Second, just as Kant argues that empirical psychology must posit
multiple different kinds of mental state to make sense of the phenomena
of human mental life, he argues that science in general cannot depend
upon purely physical causes in making sense of the behavior of living
(and especially human) things. In general, for Kant, science should use
as few general principles as possible, but as many as are truly needed to
make sense of observed phenomena. Just as Newton legitimately
(according to Kant) positing gravitational force in order to better model
physical motions, Kant posits “preformed” teleological and psychological
predispositions to better explain living and animal behavior. And just as
Newton did not reduce gravitational force to the mechanistic forces of
inertia and collision that dominated 17th century physics, Kant does not
reduce psychological forces to purely physical ones.
Neither of these Kantian arguments need imply empiricalsubstance-dualism, however. The first argument – based on the
distinction between inner and outer sense – is a sort of qualia argument,
put in terms of Kant’s general account of the difference between the way
inner and outer states appear to human knowers. Inner states have a
certain feel – non-spatiality – that outer states necessarily lack. But this
lack of equivalence does not imply any difference of substance between
mind and body. In the same way that the irreducibility of auditory to
visual sensations is consistent with having both kinds of sensations of
the same object, perceptions of mind in inner sense and of brain in outer
sense could be irreducibly distinct perceptions of the same thing. Kant
even does some speculative neuroscience, suggesting chemical processes
in “the water of the brain” that might underlie the processes of
“separating and combining given sensory representations” (12:34). The
second argument – the need for purely psychological laws – is an
empirically-contingent one that might be falsified given neuroscientific
progress. At present, however, optimism that all psychological laws will
265 eventually be translatable into neurophysiological laws is merely a
scientific ideal; and the multiple-realizability of mental states provides
reasons for thinking that even the most sophisticated neuroscience will
still leave room for properly psychological laws in explaining human
thoughts and actions. But this argument, too, does not require a
substance-dualism, only an irreducibility of the relevant laws, or, for
Kant, powers. The same substance can have different powers – as Kant
clearly thinks is true of the human soul – and there is no reason that the
physical powers of the brain and the mental powers of the mind could
not be distinct powers of the same thing (the brain-mind).
In general, then, Kant’s anthropology puts him in an excellent
position vis-a-vis contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind.
Kant’s argument based on the non-spatial character of inner sense
contributes an important variation on the qualia argument for the
difference between mind and body. His generally Newtonian approach to
science provides a basis for distinguishing psychological and physical
laws, one that is appropriately modest about the prospects for
neuroscience, not limiting these prospects a priori but also recognizing
the still-present need for non-physical laws to fully make sense of human
(and other living) beings. In both respects, Kant’s philosophy of mind
anticipates some of the most important contemporary arguments for an
empirical dualism between mind and body. Kant’s transcendental
idealism, wherein the mind as seen from-within and bound to normative
laws is distinguished from the mind as an object of empirical knowledge,
further enriches his philosophy of mind. Moreover (as I argue in more
detail below), Kant rightly shows that the distinction between the
empirical mind as the object of psychology and the empirical body as
object of biology is insufficient to account for normativity. With respect
to normativity, the problem is not eliminativism or materialism but any
form of naturalism. Treating the mind as an object of description
according to natural laws is insufficient for giving an account of the mind
as bound by normative laws. The normativity problem calls for a different
sort of solution than the problems of irreducibility and qualia.
Kant opposes eliminativism from two directions, neither of which
requires a commitment to full-blown Cartesian dualism. The nonspatiality of inner sense and the (so far) irreducibility of psychological
laws to physics ones give good reasons to distinguish mental properties
from physical ones in empirical descriptions of human beings.
Transcendentally, the normativity of the from-within standpoint on
human mental life requires distinguishing this standpoint from any
empirical standpoint (whether psychological or physical). Kant’s
distinction between transcendental and empirical anthropology both
266 allows for these necessary distinctions and provides a natural way to
incorporate neuroscientific insights into his overall philosophy without
compromising his transcendental philosophy.
Even if Kant’s overall account of the human being is compatible
with general developments in neuroscience, particular neuroscientific
findings challenge Kant’s particular claims about human beings. Most of
these findings require only minor modifications of or additions to Kant’s
empirical account of human beings, but some recent research suggests
pictures of the human mind that seem to challenge some of our (and
Kant’s) most fundamental conceptions of what it means to be human. A
study by Benjamin Libet, for example, has subjects flick their wrists
while researchers scan their brain activity with an EEG. Subjects flicked
their wrists at will, and Libet found that each wrist-flicking was preceded
by a consistent EEG pattern. Libet then asked subjects to look at a
simple, rapidly-moving clock-face and note the position of a dot
(equivalent to a clock-hand) at the moment they made the conscious
decision to flick their wrist. The surprising result is that the EEG pattern
that brings about wrist-flicking preceded the conscious decision to flick.
As Libet puts the results of his study, “The initiation of the freely
voluntary act appears to begin in the brain unconsciously, well before
the person consciously knows he wants to act! Is there, then, any role for
conscious will in the performance of this voluntary act?” (Libet 1999:51).
Or, as the same result was put by Dennis Overbye for the New York
Times, “The decision to act was an illusion, the monkey making up a
story about what the tiger had already done” (Overbye 2007).
Against such apparently paradoxical conclusions, Kant’s humility
about science reduces the threat of Libet’s findings without requiring
bizarre accommodations. When Libet tries to answer his question of
whether there is “any role for conscious will in the performance of a
voluntary act,” the most he can do is to give the will a sort of “veto” over
the flick based on the fact that “it must be recognized that conscious will
does appear about 150 milliseconds before the muscle is activated” (Libet
1999:51). This attempt to salvage some remnant of freedom is, of course,
implausible. The fact that the neural process is not yet finished by the
time one is consciously aware of one’s decision to flick does not imply
that consciousness can bring that neural process to a halt.182 For Kant,
182
Daniel Dennett (see Dennett 2003) has, somewhat more helpfully, pointed out a variety of mental
architectures that could explain how one might mistake the location of the dot at the time of one’s decision
and thus report a time that was later than one’s conscious decision-making. The connection between events
in inner sense and events in outer sense – the brain – is likely to be complicated. There is no reason to think
267 however, “conscious decision-making” is an ambiguous phrase, one that
can refer to either an object of inner sense – one’s introspection of a
particular event of cognition giving rise to a volition – or to a
transcendental perspective on action, the standpoint of considering
alternatives or evaluating choices “from-within” for the purposes of
deliberation or the ascription of moral responsibility. Empirically, Libet’s
experiment need not raise any red flags, since Kant’s empirical dualism
is consistent with conscious psychological states being correllated with
and even caused by physical states. Explanation in terms of conscious
decisions takes place at a different level than explanation in terms of
brain-state fluctuations, so what matters in this case is merely that
conscious decision takes place, not the timing of that decision relative to
the physical changes that underlie it.
The greater threat might seem to be to the transcendental
perspective on action, since Libet’s experiment makes it look as though
brain-states must be the causes of choices rather than vice versa, since
they precede those choices. But for Kant, the priority of free choice over
the determinism of the empirical world is not temporal. The suggestion
that brain-patterns precede conscious choices seems threatening
because we assume that unless our choices come temporally first and
determine the structure of the world, we cannot really be responsible for
them. This is just the conception of freedom that Kant’s transcendental
anthropology rejects, by showing that we can be responsible for actions
even if, from a scientific perspective, we need to see those actions as the
results of prior causes in a deterministic world. It should come as no
surprise that scientists looking for causes of human actions eventually
find them, since they modify their overarching theories in order to make
human behavior fit into the same causal-determinist models as other
phenomena. But the fact that scientists can and must continue to refine
their theories to develop better and better causal models of human
behavior does not change the nature of our transcendental standpoint on
human action. From-within the standpoint of a deliberating agent, we
must still see our actions as the free results of choices that ground those
actions and are undetermined by physical causes.
that the moment at which one becomes aware of a decision is identical to the moment at which one makes
the decision. Even empirically, choosing is one thing and introspectively reflecting on that choice is
another. Thus the fact that one’s consciousness of one’s choice post-dates the physical mechanisms that
correlate with that choice may be interesting, but it is not particularly threatening to Kant’s conception of
the human being. Dennett’s argument is one with which Kant could entirely agree, but for Kant, such
theorizing about possible looseness in the empirical account is not necessary. In principle, for Kant,
freedom will never be found in the timing of events in the brain, nor could any particular mental
architecture be more undermining of freedom than any other. All human choices are, when seen
empirically, the determined results of prior natural causes.
268 Before leaving this section, it is worth noting one further context
for thinking about Kant’s relationship with contemporary neuroscience.
Neuroscience affects most people’s lives neither through knowledge of
particular scientific theories about brain-states nor through
philosophical reflection on the nature of mind, but through psychopharmaceuticals used to improve psychological health. To some extent,
Kant would be pleasantly surprised by this use of neurobiology for
improving human lives. Although he refers to “inquiries as to the manner
in which bodily organs are connected with thought” as “eternally futile”
(10:146), Kant is willing and even eager to appeal to physiological
treatments when they are reliable and available (see 7:213, 220). And
when Kant objects to physiological approaches to pragmatic
anthropology, he refers to approaches that emphasize bodily bases of
mental states and that therefore cannot be put to any practical use. For
Kant, a physiological focus implies practical uselessness because of the
limited knowledge of how to manipulate the body to bring about shifts in
mental states.
He who ponders natural phenomena, for example, what the causes of
the faculty of memory may rest on, can speculate back and forth . . .
over the traces of impressions remaining in the brain, but in doing so
he must admit that in this play of his representations he is a mere
observer and must let nature run its course, for he does not know the
cranial nerves and fibers, nor does he understand how to put them to
use for his purposes. Therefore all theoretical speculation about this
is a pure waste of time. (7:119, emphasis added)
The improvement of neuroscience has the potential to transform a
formerly useless physiological anthropology into an important part of a
genuinely pragmatic anthropology.
But Kant’s pragmatic anthropology, while it would certainly
appropriate contemporary neuroscience for practical purposes, also
provides an important counterweight to and caution about the clinical
approaches that had already begun in the 18th century and have
developed even further today. For Kant, “Medical science is philosophical
when the sheer power of man’s reason to master his sensuous feelings by
a self-imposed principle determines his manner of living” (7:101). Kant’s
concern with physiological approaches to mental disorder is not merely
that they do not work. Such approaches also put one’s mental life in the
hands of someone else. Rather than taking charge of one’s own mental
well-being, one “has a doctor who decides upon a regimen for me” (8:35).
269 And this turning over of one’s own mental capacities to another grates
against the autonomy that Kant repeatedly emphasizes in both morals
(see especially Groundwork and Critique of Practical Reason) and
intellectual life (see “What is Enlightenment?”).183 The increasing
dependence on pharmaceuticals can also encourage people to abdicate
personal responsibility for failings that, however physiologically
influenced, are nonetheless expressions of a character that is ultimately
free. Kant rightly notes that empirical anthropology is most important
not as a theoretical endeavor but as a part of a practical discipline
oriented towards improving human lives, and in that sense psychiatry is
extremely valuable. But Kant also provides an alternative model of
practical self-control that, while still being empirically-grounded, allows
for genuine self-improvement rather than an abdication to others of the
autonomy that is so important to being human. In the end, the overall
structure of Kant’s anthropology provides a framework for incorporating
but also recognizing the limits of neuroscience in both practical life and
theoretical self-understanding.
II. Humanity Evolves: Darwinism and the Fate of Humanity
However interesting the connection between the human mind and
the human brain, contemporary neuroscience invites the question of how
a physical system such as the human brain arose. Without a naturalist
account of its origin, the human brain might seem literally miraculous,
reflecting some supernatural design (much as computers reflect their
human designers). As we saw in chapter two, Kant rejected attempts by
his contemporaries to offer naturalistic explanations of basic human
predispositions (8:110). But Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural
selection in the middle of the 19th century offered a major new theoretical
framework for answering such questions. The 20th century saw a
“Darwinian synthesis” between Darwin’s theory of natural selection and
Gregor Mendel’s theory of heredity through the recognition that the
random variations that Darwin left unexplained as brute inputs to his
system could be understood as mutations of sub-cellular “genes” that
were both hereditable and susceptible to environmentally-induced
mutations. The discovery of DNA by Watson and Crick in 1943 and the
subsequent development of molecular genetics further explained the
physical bases of genetic variation.
183
As we will see in section three below, this is true even for non-neurological ways in which
contemporary psychology encourages people to put their own mental and moral lives in the hands of others.
270 The immediate implications of the current biological synthesis
between Darwinian natural selection and molecular biology for thinking
about human beings are fairly straightforward. Like all life on earth,
humans evolved from simpler organisms. Early in the history of our
planet, molecules emerged that were capable of replicating themselves
with slight variations. Those variations better at self-replication and
persistence in the environment increased in number, and at a certain
point reached levels of complexity that could warrant ascribing the label
“life” to them. These self-replicating “organisms” competed for energy and
other resources and, through natural selection, those better at
replicating in their environments grew in number. The features that
distinguish human beings from other animals are features that arose by
means of molecular (primarily genetic) mutations that were preserved
through this process of natural selection, whereby variations that add
“fitness” – that is, allow survival and reproduction in greater numbers –
grow more prevalent in the population. Human animals are well-adapted
to our environments because earlier members of our genus that were not
well adapted died and left no offspring. The human brain has the
complex structure that it does because this advanced brain allowed
ancestral humans to outcompete their closest relatives.
As a tool for understanding our world and ourselves, evolutionary
biology has proven incredibly powerful over the past 50 years. Our
knowledge of DNA allows us to more accurately diagnose genetic diseases
and determine the likelihood that a disease will be passed on to one’s
progeny. The success of the Human Genome Project in mapping the
entirety of the human genome has helped us to identify genes associated
with muscle disease, blindness, and deafness, and to understand the
complex DNA sequences at the root of cardiovascular disease, arthritis,
diabetes, and various kinds of cancer. The project has fueled new
research with the aim of creating more specific and targeted treatments
for many diseases, with fewer harmful side effects. Understanding
natural selection and patterns of adaptation is central to developing and
properly managing the use of antibiotics and vaccines, and evolutionary
biology is at the core of our attempts to preserve endangered species and
fragile ecosystems. Modeling lines of descent through genetic mapping
provides guides population patterns over time and explanations for
physiological differences across different populations, and DNA tests are
used in forensics, parental rights, and tracing family genealogies.
Evolutionary models of human beings also provide a naturalist
framework and scientific discipline to the popular philosophical pastime
of armchair theorizing about human nature. Daniel Dennett, one of the
foremost philosophical popularizers of Darwinism, explains,
271 Speculative exercises in agent-design have been a staple of
philosophers since Plato’s Republic. What the evolutionary
perspective adds is a fairly systematic way to keep the exercises
naturalistic (so we don’t end up designing an angel or perpetual
motion machine). (Dennett 2003: 217-8)
Rather than introspection or hand-waving about human nature,
evolutionary theory forces one to explain, for any proposed physical or
psychological feature, what effects such a feature would have on the
fitness of an organism that possessed it. One cannot simply say that
humans have features that would be nice to have or that would help
explain particular behaviors. One must also give some account of how
those features could have evolved through processes of natural selection.
Given much recent work in applying evolutionary theory to human
beings, there is reason to think that such accounts will prove to be more
illuminating than one might have expected. One might even think that
given the advanced state of human sciences such as evolutionary
biology, there is little left for philosophy but to clarify and systematize
“investigations in the natural sciences” (Dennett 2003:15).
Still, one might fear that evolutionary accounts would have
difficulties making sense of central aspects of human life. Kant famously
offers a sort of anti-evolutionary argument in the opening of his
Groundwork, explaining that reason can have as its purpose neither
human happiness nor reproductive success, since it is notoriously bad at
promoting those, and certainly much worse than animals’ instincts
(4:395-6). Many also worry that any evolutionary approach to human
beings will result in a picture of humans as hopelessly selfish animals
seeking only to thrive and reproduce in a cut-throat world where “only
the fittest survive.” More generally, one might wonder whether central
human concerns – morality, art, and even the sciences themselves, not to
mention true love and religious experience – can be accounted for by
evolutionary theory. Some of these concerns are concerns about
naturalism more generally, questions about whether any theory that
treats human beings as natural beings can accommodate central aspects
of who we are. But some are tied to the particular kind of naturalist
explanations offered by evolutionary theory.
In last 30 years – starting with the publication of E.O. Wilson’s
Sociobiology and Richard Dawkins’ The Selfish Gene in the mid-70’s –
sophisticated Darwinian accounts of human nature have emerged that
move beyond caricatures of evolution as implying that human beings are
fundamentally nothing more than clever, selfish primates. The richness
of these accounts is impossible to convey in this short chapter, but three
272 central issues – the evolution of altruism, the role of “memes” in
evolution, and the nature of human freedom – give a sense of how
evolutionary theory is used to make sense of aspects of human beings
that might seem to transcend simplistic inferences from our descent by
means of natural selection.
Evolutionary theorizing about altruism might seem oxymoronic
because many see the claim that everyone is out for themselves as a
central premise of evolution. But Darwin’s own Descent of Man
emphasized that human fitness is enhanced through the development of
“social instincts” that “lead an animal to take pleasure in the society of
its fellows, to feel a certain amount of sympathy for them, and to perform
various services for them” (Darwin 1981: 72). As our understanding of
the processes of evolution grows, we see cooperative forms of natural
selection playing key roles in the development of virtually all life on
earth. A first approximation to altruism is present even in the most basic
units of life on earth. The first few billion years of life on earth were
dominated by “prokaryotes,” simple, single cells that “did everything for
themselves.” If these cells moved, they moved themselves. If they
generated energy, they generated it for themselves. If they broke down
other cells to get organic materials for themselves, they had within
themselves the resources to break down those cells. But about a billion
years ago, some prokaryotes found themselves teamed up with others (by
being incorporated into others without being broken down), and in some
cases, these teams outperformed independent prokaryotes around them.
These so-called “eukaryotes” prospered, and virtually all life today
consists of complex cells that include “parts” that are descendents of
these paired simple cells. Human cells contain, for example,
mitochondria, which do most of the energy-processing in our cells and
which have their own DNA,184 and the vast majority (more than 99%!) of
the genes in our bodies are in “non-human” micro-organisms living in
our guts (Gill et. al. 2006).185 Evolutionary “fitness” is not merely – nor
primarily – a matter of killing off opponents. It can just as easily be a
matter of cooperating in particularly effectively ways (cf. Dennett 1995).
In the human case, for example, societies whose members cooperate tend
to outperform those that are constantly at each other’s throats, so social
affection and cooperation evolved among human beings.
184
One can even trace maternal descent through these mitochondrial DNA because, unlike humans’ nucleic
DNA, mitochondrial DNA comes entirely from one’s mother.
185
Gill goes so far as to say that “humans are superorganisms whose metabolism represents an
amalgamation of microbial and human attributes” (Gill et. al. 2006: 1355).
273 This importance of cooperation-as-evolutionary-fitness is made
clearer by thinking about so-called “Prisoner’s Dilemma” scenarios. The
standard Prisoner’s Dilemma is the following. Two suspects are being
questioned for a crime. Each faces the following possibilities: If you
betray your partner and your partner stays faithful to you, you go free
and your partner gets life in prison. If you do not betray and your partner
does, you get life and he goes free. If neither betrays the other, you’ll both
be convicted only of minor charges for which you’ll spend only a short
time in prison (say, a year and a day). If both betray, you’ll both probably
end up spending a moderate amount of time in prison (say, 5-7 years).
The ideal scenario overall is for both you and your partner to hold fast
and say nothing; then you will both spend only a year in prison. But you
both have strong incentives to betray, since whatever your partner does,
you end up better off if you betray. The specific example highlights a
general kind of case, one where the group as a whole (here you and your
partner) would be better off if everyone adopted a particular course of
action, but where each member of the group has an incentive to adopt a
different, less optimal, course of action. For evolutionary theory, the
Prisoner’s Dilemma might seem, at first blush, to pose a particularly
pessimistic, even tragic, picture of life on earth. If evolution proceeds
through a model of the “survival of the fittest,” then it looks like only
betrayers will survive. Faithful humans who pursue strategies good for
the whole will end up being evolutionary suckers, exploited by the
betrayers looking out only for number one.
In fact, however, a sophisticated understanding of evolution shows
that the Prisoner’s Dilemma has precisely the opposite implication:
humans are more likely to evolve strategies that favor the group to which
they belong than strategies that narrowly favor themselves, for several
reasons. For one, situations like the Prisoner’s Dilemma described above
are rare. Far more common are iterated Prisoner’s Dilemmas, in which
one finds oneself in Prisoner’s Dilemma scenarios with the same people,
or members of the same community, again and again. And in these
contexts, selfishness (betrayal) is generally not the best strategy. In these
cases, the best strategy tends to be some form of altruistic tit-for-tat. One
starts by not betraying and continues to remain true to others, unless
they betray (or are known to betray), in which case one prudently (or
vindictively) betrays them in turn. Organisms – including humans – who
are involved in iterated prisoner’s dilemma scenarios tend to thrive and
reproduce most when they are altruistic but temper their altruism with
what we might call justice and prudence. Human life is full of such
scenarios, where cooperation is beneficial but a potential for exploitation
exists. Thus even if evolution were simply a matter of the fittest
274 individuals surviving and reproducing, altruism tempered by prudence
and justice will tend to evolve in human beings, since this configuration
of dispositions is in the best interest of those who have them.186
But the evolution of altruism is further enhanced by the fact that
evolution is not simply a matter of fittest individual organisms surviving
and reproducing. In the The Descent of Man, Darwin explains how “social
qualities” such as “sympathy, fidelity, and courage” evolved “though
natural selection.”
When two tribes of primeval man, living in the same country, came
into competition, if the one tribe included . . . a greater number of . . .
sympathetic and faithful members, who were always ready to warn
each other of danger, to aid and defend each other, this tribe would
without doubt succeed best and conquer the other. (Darwin 1981:
162)
Even if, among individuals, a more selfish individual were likely to have
more offspring and thereby take over that population, one can also adopt
a higher standpoint from which one sees competition amongst
populations. To go back to our initial Prisoner’s Dilemma case, if one
compares individual criminals, ones that betray their confederates will
spend less time in prison than those that do not. But if one compares
different criminal gangs, then the gangs whose members steadfastly
refuse to betray confederates will spend less time in prison that those
that are full of betrayers. Gangs that develop a tendency not to betray
will be more successful than those that do not. In the evolutionary
context, mutations that make members of society altruistic (at least visa-vis other members of their own society) will make that society as a
whole more fit than other human populations. More altruistic societies
(that is, societies whose members are altruistic) will tend to win out over
less altruistic ones, and altruism will gradually become part of human
nature.
186
One might wonder whether it wouldn’t be better to have a more sophisticated strategy, whereby one
cooperates only when one will be found out for betraying, but betrays whenever one can do so secretly, or
whenever one will not need to depend upon those who become of one’s secrecy. There is evidence that
such a strategy can be somewhat successful, but there are two problems for it. First, it requires a lot of time
and effort to assess one’s situations in this fine-grained a way. The result is that it is probably more
efficient simply to forego possible opportunities for safe exploitation rather than suffer either the cost of
ensuring that one has diagnosed the scenario properly or the risks of getting it wrong. Second, the evolution
of such a fine-grained strategy of deception will provoke counter-strategies of detection. There is good
evidence that in human beings, whose brains provide the cognitive power to assess situations in finegrained ways, both deception and counter-deceptions strategies have evolved. The result is a human nature
that includes altruism and a sense of justice alongside selfish and deceitful tendencies and strategies of
prudence for dealing with other selfish, deceitful people.
275 This point about group selection can also be made from the
opposite perspective. Evolution works on groups as well as individuals,
but especially in the light of the synthesis between Darwin and molecular
genetics, biologists typically emphasize the primary locus of evolution as
the gene, rather than the individual organism or group. In The Selfish
Gene (1974), Richard Dawkins helpfully highlights that evolutionary
selfishness takes place at the level of the genes. This does not mean that
there is a gene “for selfishness,” but rather that genes code for what best
allows the gene to survive and replicate (over the long term). And this
gene-centered point of view has the same effects as the group point of
view. The notion of “kin-selection” is a case in point. The idea behind kin
selection is that because members of the same family share much of
their genetic material in common, genes will tend to survive and
propogate insofar as they give rise to instincts to protect one’s kin. The
“interest” of one’s genes might well require that one sacrifice oneself for
the sake of a sibling or child who shares copies of those genes. Insofar as
human behavior is genetic (instinctual), it will tend at least to be
altruistic towards groups to which one is genetic similar. Importantly, for
the human individual, there is nothing “selfish” about this behavior;
one’s genes code for behavior that – from the standpoint of the individual
– is genuinely altruistic. In the end, whether one looks at evolution from
the standpoint of individuals involved in iterated prisoner’s dilemmas, or
groups competing for fitness, or selfish genes striving to replicated
themselves, there is good reason to think that evolution by natural
selection will give rise to human beings (and other organisms) that are
cooperative and altruistic in the main senses in which those concepts are
important to our self-conception.187
Even if evolutionary theory is not committed to a conception of
human beings as thoroughly selfish, however, it it may seem ill equipped
to account for the great cultural achievements of human beings. Can
Darwinian evolution explain how we came to construct religious
institutions, or create great works of literature, or develop complex
societies and governmental systems and economies, or acquire scientific
knowledge? In recent years, evolutionary theorists have developed
various theoretical tools for making sense of these tendencies in
Darwinian terms. Among these, arguably the most important is the
concept of “memes.” A meme is a “cultural replicator parallel to [a] gene,”
or, put another way, a “parasite . . . [that] use[s] human brains . . . as
187
The language of groups “competing” or genes “striving” is obviously anthropomorphic. I mean only that
they are subject to forces of natural selection.
276 [its] temporary homes and jump[s] from brain to brain to reproduce”
(Dennett 2003:175, cf. Dennett 1995 and Dawkins 1976). The basic idea
behind memes involves applying the general logical structure of
Darwinian natural selection beyond the specific context of genes or other
physical-biological entities. Genes are relatively complex molecules
capable of mutations that can either enhance or diminish the capacity of
the gene to replicate in a particular environment. Self-enhancing
mutations produce more gene-copies and the mutated genes spread and
persist, while self-diminishing mutations eventually perish. Similarly,
memes are relatively complex units of culture; “made of information,”
memes can be “carried” as contents of mental states or written in a book
or stored on a computer or posted on a billboard.188 Like genes, memes
are capable of mutations that can either enhance or diminish the
capacity of the meme to replicate in a particular environment. Selfenhancing mutations produce more meme-copies and the mutated
memes spread and persist, while self-diminishing mutations eventually
perish. Memes can include items as diverse as melodies that get stuck in
one’s head, corporate logos, mathematical theorems, cooperative
strategies, religious doctrines, habits, biases, artistic techniques, and so
on. Any possible “unit of culture” is capable of mutation and subject to
forces of natural selection. The most successful memes survive.
Just as genes did not exist on earth until a couple billion years
ago, sophisticated memes did not exist until about 50,000 years ago,
when certain groups of animals developed brains sufficiently advanced to
develop cultural mechanisms for the transmission of information. Daniel
Dennett has referred to a “euprimatic revolution” (Dennett 2003: 179),
when a new form of primate emerged – a euprimate or “superprimate,” a
“hominid with an infected brain, host to millions of cultural symbionts.”
The “chief enablers” of this revolution “are the symbiont systems known
as languages” (Dennett 2003: 173). Many animals, of course, have
primitive forms of culture, and the culture study of animals has become
an increasingly important topic within contemporary biology. Birds pass
on songs, non-genetically, from parents to their young; and gorillas pass
on strategies for hunting and tool use. But the scale of human culture is
unique among animals on earth. At first, the development of linguistic
188
Strictly speaking, one could consider genes to be a subset of the general category meme, since genes,
too, carry information. If one pushed the point sufficiently far, one could consider rays of light to be
memes, since they carry information about objects that have emitted them. For the rest of this discussion,
however, I reserve the term “meme” in general for bundles of information that could be considered “units
of [human] culture.” Thus a billboard could be the medium for a meme, insofar as it presents a unit of
human culture as a possible content of a human mental state. A gene is not a meme, since, while we can
think about it, it is not a “unit of culture.” (The idea of a “gene,” however, is a meme, as is the idea of a
277 capacity served humans’ selfish genes. Humans with brains that could
host more memes created communities with more advanced possibilities
of cultural transmission that were better able to navigate the world in
which they lived. Such communities grew and thrived, while
communities with less cultural potential died off. Human brains’ abilities
to generate, host, and transmit memes grew.
But once human brains became efficient meme-creators, mutators,
and replicators, memes took on a life of their own. Like parasites, some
memes enhance the fitness of their hosts (e.g., hygiene techniques), while
others do not (birth control techniques). In some cases, memes that
inhibit their hosts’ fitness thereby destroy their potential for replication
(Shakers’ commitment to universal celibacy). In other cases, memes can
thrive and replicate even when they do not serve the interests of the
genes of their hosts (birth control, again). And some memes that might
enhance their hosts’ fitness nonetheless aren’t very good at replicating
(information about foods’ caloric content). Of course, memetic fitness and
genetic fitness are not wholly unrelated. Memes are only possible
because genes that code for meme-friendly brains were more successful
than genes that code for meme-resistant brains. Memes sufficiently
destructive to their hosts (suicide-for-fun) rarely survive. And memes
sufficiently destructive to human genes in general (knowledge of nuclear
weapons) could bring the whole memetic enterprise on earth to its end.
Moreover, the particular structure of the brain evolved through selection
of genes and provides the context for which particular memes will thrive.
But these forms of dependence are loose. In general, memes have lives of
their own, using human brains as hosts, but promoting the interests of
human genes (and even human beings) only as far as that is necessary
for their own replicative success.
This relative independence of memes and genes provides a
Darwinian way of explaining those aspects of our lives that can seem
mysterious from a narrowly gene-centered point of view: art, religion,
poetry, and even the sciences are all memes or systems of memes.189
Creativity in these fields is the result of the tendency of memes, in the
medium of the human brain, to mutate. Moreover, because memes often
include standards for the adoption of future memes, “successful” memes
189
Some aspects of human culture – filial piety, for instance – might be so basic and so universal that a
genetic explanation seems more plausible than a memetic one. Even basic and universal cultural practices
could be the results of either early memetic inheritances shared in common due to common (or interacting)
cultural ancestors or convergence upon useful memes by disparate communities. Here there is a close
parallel with phenotypic similarities amongst diverse populations of organisms. Often, these similarities
reflect common ancestry. In other cases (such as the development of “fins” in both whales and fish) they
reflect the convergence of genetically dissimilar organisms towards similar adaptive characteristics.
278 will be those that conform to the standards of the memetic landscape in
which they emerge. The general model of memes as structures that
mutate and compete for replication and persistence in human brains can
make sense of progress in science; “great works” of art, music and
poetry; the delicate balance of tradition and development that
characterizes religious traditions; and the tendency of most complex
memetic structures to incorporate techniques of
education/indoctrination and persuasion/proselytizing. Recognizing the
role of memes even helps make sense of how we can find insatiable
human thirsts for knowledge and art “for their own sakes,” since these
memes are not dependent upon their connections with any other form of
success but solely focused on exploiting the distinctive characteristics of
the human mind to replicate themselves.
The combination of more sophisticated thinking about evolutionary
theory (as in the case of altruism) combined with the addition of memes
to the evolutionary framework has given rise to Darwinian-naturalistic
accounts of human freedom and morality. Not all Darwinian naturalists
think that freedom is something worth saving. Explaining human beings
in terms of evolution by natural selection, especially with the addition of
selfish genes, makes many think that freedom, and even morality, is
simply a relic of scientific ignorance (e.g. Pereboom 2001). But the most
sophisticated philosophical appropriations of Darwinism have sought to
make sense of freedom and morals. Memes provide a first, crucial tool in
freeing human beings from genetically programmed behaviors. Just as
Kant emphasized the importance of the “higher faculty of desire” –
motivation to act on principles to which we are committed rather than
mere instincts – Darwinian naturalists who appeal to memes distinguish
humans from other animals based on the fact that we often act in the
interest of memes rather than genes. And meme-motivated action has a
very different character than gene-motivated behavior.
[A]ccess to memes [has] the effect of opening up a world of
imagination to human beings that would otherwise be closed off. The
salmon swimming upstream to spawn may be wily in a hundred
ways, but she cannot even contemplate the prospect of abandoning
her reproductive project and deciding instead to live out her days
studying coastal geography. The creation of a panoply of new
standpoints is, to my mind, the most striking product of the
euprimatic revolution. Whereas all other living things are designed by
evolution to evaluate all options relative to the summum bonum of
279 reproductive success, we can trade that quest for any of a thousand
others… (Dennett 2003: 179).
Already, this is a huge step towards both freedom and morality. Human
action takes place in the light of memes, reasons that motivate us insofar
as we think about them. And moral systems, as complex memetic
structures that develop in the context of our natural tendencies toward
altruism, can present themselves as standpoints that inform our actions.
But even the addition of the memetic point of view does not yet achieve
the sort of freedom that we might want, a freedom captured well by
Richard Dawkins in the conclusion to his groundbreaking book, The
Selfish Gene:
We have the power to defy the selfish genes of our birth, and, if
necessary, the selfish memes of our indoctrination . . . We are built
as gene machines and cultured as meme machines, but we have the
power to rebel against our creators. We, alone on earth, can rebel
against the tyranny of the selfish replicators. (Dawkins 1976: 215)
So far, we have shown only that selfish genes and selfish memes can
pursue their “own interests” independently of each other. Humans need
not serve our genes, since we can also serve our memes. But how can we
rebel against both genes and memes? And what makes human beings
the only creatures that can do this?
The answer to these questions, oddly enough, is a 21st century
naturalist version of a key Kantian empirical claim about what
distinguishes human beings from animals. For Kant, what “raises him
infinitely above all other living beings on earth” is “the fact that the
human being can have the ‘I’ in his representations . . . Because of this
he is a person, and by virtue of the unity of consciousness through all
changes that happen to him, one and the same person” (7:127). In the
context of Darwinian naturalism, this “I” is itself a meme, one that has
proven particularly adept at self-replication and that opens up a whole
new vista of self-understanding and self-control. There are many possible
routes for the formation, development, and persistence of the I-meme,
more than can be discussed here. One route – suggested by Kant –
comes from the conditions necessary for the formation of general
concepts. For Kant, the unification of different representations under a
general concept requires that one see those representations as belonging
to a single “I” (see B131ff.). Thus the complex shift in our mental
machinery that makes it possible to move from mere representations of
objects to general concepts and thereby to the explosion of memes in
human culture is built on a capacity to take oneself as the subject of
280 one’s representations. Another route lies in attempts to coordinate
information. Insofar as one’s language is limited to claims about objects,
it can be difficult to discriminate the perspectives of different knowers.
“There is no game in the forest” contradicts “there is game in the forest,”
but my claim “I did not find game in the forest” need not contradict your
claim that you did find game there. A sense of self provides a way to
coordinate information. Yet a third basis for the I-meme comes from
information-coordination about people, the importance of which is clear
in the context of iterated Prisoner’s Dilemmas. Humans need ways of
communicating about the reliability of other human beings, not merely of
other human genes or memes. Humans benefit from evaluating others as
persons with fixed characters and holding them responsible for their
actions. And as human beings become more sophisticated reasoners, we
become capable of deception, which makes the problem of identifying
persons (including ourselves) more acute. We develop a sense of selfimage, of thinking about how “I” look to others. Cultivating the right
image of myself becomes an important social task, and one responds to
being held responsible by learning to hold oneself responsible as an
efficient way of regulating one’s own behavior before others need to step
in.
Once human beings have a sense of self, there is no reason that
this sense of self must remain motivationally inert. Recall that there were
good reasons, from the gene-centered point of view, for the development
of memes, but once memes came into the world, they took on a life of
their own and could evolve in ways that were not conducive to the fitness
of any particular genes. In the same way, the emergence of an I-meme in
human brains gives rise to a new kind of entity, a “self” capable of
thinking about itself. And this new entity need not serve the interests of
the memes that gave rise to it. Moreover, this new entity is precisely a
being that sets its own ends. As an entity with a sense of self, this new
entity will be capable of higher order desires, reflection on its identity,
and even governance of itself by norms – including moral norms – that it
“autonomously” endorses. For Darwinian naturalists, this is a sufficient
basis for freedom, at least in every sense “worth wanting” (Dennett 1984).
A sufficiently rich Darwinian naturalism thus provides a much
better answer to Kant’s question than one might expect. Human beings
are animals, but we are not “mere” animals. We are social animals that
care about one another, expressing sympathy and compassion for those
in need and resentment towards those who harm us. We evolved genetic
codes that enable the development of a complicated cognitive
architecture that makes us hosts to countless “memes.” These units of
culture mutate and propagate in ways that provide us with a wide
281 diversity of thoughts, opinions, and practices, artistic creations,
religions, and even sciences themselves. Among these memes are moral
rules, social and cultural norms, and even that sense of self by virtue of
which we regulate our thought and behavior in accordance with what we
take to be most important to us. By virtue of our evolutionary history, we
have, as Dawkins put it, “the power to defy the selfish genes of our
birth.” We are animals but also agents, expressions of genes but also
self-expressions, homo sapiens but also wise beings-like-us.
In assessing the possible relationship between Kant and
contemporary Darwinism, the most obvious starting point is Kant’s
philosophy of biology, where Kant seems to be in trouble. One of the
central claims of Kant’s (philosophy of) biology is that
It is quite certain that we can never adequately come to know the
organized beings and the internal possibility in accordance with
merely mechanical principles of nature, let alone explain them; and
indeed this is so certain that we can boldly say that it would be
absurd for humans even to make such an attempt or to hope that
there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even
the generation of a blade of grass according to natural laws that no
intention had ordered. (5:400)
150 years after Darwin laid out a detailed explanation of the origin of
species, and 50 years after the birth of the molecular biology that
describes precisely how genetic material develops into living things,
Kant’s despair about a Newton of a blade of grass seems exaggerated. As
Ernst Mayr has put it, “Darwin . . . solved Kant’s great puzzle” (Mayr
1988:58). Today, the assumption of an intentional order in nature is not
only unnecessary, but hinders biological progress. Moreover, Kant’s
pessimism about mechanical explanations in biology was linked with his
use of the concept of “predispositions,” which play crucial roles in his
empirical anthropology and are simply taken for granted. Kant offers no
explanations of how these predispositions arose and seems to think that
the “origin” of the human species is simply irrelevant to anthropology
(see 8:110). But Darwinism is precisely the attempt to explain the “origin
of species,” and the question of how homo sapiens evolved is central to
Darwinian answers to the question, “What is the human being?”190 At the
190
For the sake of space, I ignore another Darwinian objection to the question “What is the human being?”
Arguably, Darwin’s Origin of Species undermines the whole notion of a “species” or “natural kind.” If
variations in any particular population of organisms in nature could potentially be bases for what would
come to be seen as species-level distinctions, then it seems arbitrary to try to define who “we” human
282 very least, Kant’s indifference to (and even skepticism about) scientific
explanations of origins has been shown to be misguided. Contemporary
evolutionary biology undermines Kant’s pessimism about non-teleological
explanation and his specific appeal to innate and inexplicable natural
predispositions to explain human (and other living) beings.
In other respects, however, Kant’s philosophy of biology is
consistent with, and in some ways presciently anticipatory of, presentday Darwinism. For one thing, Kant’s appeal to predispositions was a
specific and innovative response to the biological debates of his day. In
those debates, the main protagonists argued either that biology was
reducible to physics, so living things required no special laws in order to
be explained, or that all living things were “preformed” in their earliest
ancestors (who were created by God). Kant aimed to find a middle ground
between these views, arguing that living things are not literally preformed
but that explaining them also requires principles that go beyond mere
mechanism. Darwinism clearly fits this general model.191 Evolution by
natural selection, though not “teleological” in Kant’s sense, is a principle
for explanation distinct from the mechanical explanations that dominate
physics.192 Even if “natural selection” is in principle explicable in terms
of physical forces, evolutionary biologists explain the presence and
development of biological features not in terms of physical processes but
in terms of the adaptive advantages of these features. Kant was wrong
about the specific principles that regulate the practice of biology, but
correct that some heuristic principle of a broadly purposive nature is
needed in biology. And even if the origins of (human) predispositions are
in principle explicable in terms of evolution, Kant was correct that any
beings are. However, given that Darwin himself calls the “immense” difference in mental power “between
the highest ape and the lowest savage” (Darwin 1981: 34), for the present chapter I will take for granted
that, for practical purposes, we can make a distinction between humans and other organisms, even if the
theoretical concept of a fixed “human species” is problematic.
191
Two further features of Kant’s biology connect it even more closely with contemporary evolutionary
biology. First, Kant emphasizes that the need for teleological explanation is “regulative” and not
“constitutive,” which means, for him, that despite his claim that humans never will discover nonteleological explanations of living beings, we are “summoned . . . by reason” to “the greatest possible
effort, indeed boldness, in attempting to explain [living beings] mechanically” (5: 429). Second, the details
of Kant’s account reflect a sophisticated 18th century attempt to articulate a biological methodology that
would take into account both the apparent heritability of traits and the ability for new (heritable) traits to
emerge. Kant noted that living things are susceptible to physical forces, but that they seem to develop
according to heritable internal principles. The best explanation for this, Kant suggested, is that the
environment affects the expression of predispositions that are passed on from parents to their offspring.
Kant even suggested that these patterns of expression can become hereditary, such that predispositions can
become inert or substantially modified over what we would now call a process of “evolution.”
192
The issue of whether teleological explanation itself is still necessary for biology remains a live issue, so
Kant may have been even closer to the mark that this section suggests. (For contemporary discussions of
teleology in biology, see Allen et. al. 1998 and Ariew et. al. 2002.)
283 explanation of biological characteristics depends upon seeing how
environmental conditions affect the expression of inherited (and not
immediately explicable) “predispositions” for those characteristics.
But what of the further claim, that an understanding of the
evolution of human beings (and their predispositions) provides the basis
for a sufficient answer to the question, “What is the human being?” Did
Kant, by ignoring the question of origins, pass over the best and most
adequate answer to the question that sums up the whole of philosophy?
I think not. From a Kantian perspective, the question “What is the
human being?” can be answered transcendentally, empirically, and
pragmatically. Kantians must acknowledge that evolutionary biology
greatly enriches Kant’s empirical anthropology by showing the origin of
humans’ natural predispositions, and the accounts of these origins can
even help explain the nature of those predispositions. Because empirical
anthropology provides empirical insights needed for pragmatic
anthropology, revisions and additions to our empirical picture of human
beings can enrich or modify pragmatic anthropology. In addition to the
many pragmatic, medical uses to which genetics, for instance, has been
put, recognizing what makes memes thrive in particular contexts can
help us influence others and avoid unwanted manipulation of ourselves.
But for Kant, transcendental anthropology provides the most
fundamental answers to the question, “What is the human being?”,
answers that not only get to the root of who we are but that provide the
norms that orient pragmatic anthropology. Thus the contest between
Darwinian naturalism and Kant must be decided around two core issues:
(1) Does evolutionary biology provide good grounds for challenging
either Kant’s threefold division of anthropology or his prioritization of
transcendental over empirical anthropology?
(2) Does evolutionary biology provide a more adequate approach than
Kant to transcendental anthropology, and/or does it provide good
reasons to challenge Kant’s transcendental anthropology?
Related to these two questions is a third, one that is central both to
Kant’s anthropology as a whole and to recent philosophical justifications
of evolutionary naturalism:
(3) Is the notion of human freedom allowed within evolutionary
biology sufficient?
In the rest of this section, I argue that the answer to the first two
questions is no. Evolutionary biology does not give good reasons to
284 conflate transcendental with empirical anthropology, and it fails to
provide an adequate transcendental anthropology of its own. I reserve my
discussion of (3) until section IV of this chapter.
First, what is the relationship between transcendental and
empirical anthropology? It can often seem as though evolutionary
biologists deny the need for and possibility of transcendental
anthropology altogether. In explaining his naturalism, for example,
Daniel Dennett insists that the role of philosophy today is little more
than systematizing the insights of empirical sciences. Here the notion of
an a priori human science can just seem absurd. But Dennett does
recognize that there are distinct perspectives that one can take on
human beings (and other things). Even with respect to primitive forms of
“life” in a computer simulation, Dennett insists that “our simplest doers
have been reconceptualized as rational agents or intentional systems”
such that “we can move back and forth between the . . . God perspective
[from which intentionality is the product of other forces] and the
‘perspective’ of . . . God’s creations [in which intentionality is basic]”
(Dennett 2003:45). The “meme-centered” point of view and especially the
self’s point of view can be explained naturalistically but are not
themselves “naturalistic” perspectives. And Dawkins, Dennett, and
others rightly insist that once reflection and self-image enter the scene,
human beings are capable of asking for reasons and reflecting
normatively on what to think and do.
Some memes surely enhance our fitness, making us more likely to
have lots of descendants (e.g. methods of hygiene, child-rearing, food
preparation); others are neutral – but may be good for us in other,
more important regards (e.g. literacy, music, and art)—and some
memes are surely deleterious to our genetic fitness, but even they
may be good for us in other ways that matter more to us (the
techniques of birth control…). (Dennett 2003: 177, emphasis added).
Despite initial appearances to the contrary, there is no dispute between
Kant and the most prominent evolutionary naturalists about whether
there is a normative perspective “from-within.” Kant and Dennett both
acknowledge that human beings can be studied as empirical objects in
nature, and both recognize that the laws that explain the development of
human selves are not identical to the rules that govern those selves fromwithin.
Nonetheless, Kant and Dennett fundamentally differ about the
relative priority of transcendental and empirical anthropology. While
Dennett explains the legitimacy of transcendental anthropology on the
285 basis of an empirical account of its evolution, Kant explains the
legitimacy of empirical anthropology on the basis of a transcendental
account of its justificatory basis. Thus Dennett sees “the creation of a
panoply of new standpoints” as “the most striking product of the . . .
[biological] revolution” that gave rise to human organisms (Dennett 2003:
179), while Kant would see the ability to give an evolutionary account of
human cognition as one of the most striking results of applying our
causal way of thinking about the world to the case of ourselves. Dennett
sees the biological standpoint as, fundamentally, the true standpoint, the
“God perspective” (Dennett 2003: 45). Kant sees evolutionary biology as a
standpoint of empirical cognition, which gets at one kind of truth, the
truth about the world-as-we-experience-it. Fundamentally, then, the
difference between Kant and Dennett relates to the status of science as
such.
Philosophical naturalists like Dennett tend to be strong scientific
realists. A strong scientific realist is someone who takes natural science,
at least ideally, to describe the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but
the truth. A strong scientific realist need not think that the current state
of science gets everything correct, but insofar as our science fails to tell
the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth, it needs to be
improved. By contrast, Kant is a sort of limited scientific realist, in that
he takes an ideal science to lay out the truth and nothing but the truth,
but for Kant, science specifies the truth only about the world-as-we-canexperience-it. Scientific claims are claims that human beings, given our
structure of cognition, should believe about the world. This has two
important implications for Kant’s appropriation of evolutionary biology
(or any science). First, even though evolutionary biology is an empirical
science, it is possible only because of certain a priori structures of
human cognition, and these can be studied independent of particular
empirical results. If (counter-factually) evolutionary biology were to find it
impossible to explain the evolution of causal reasoning, for example, this
would not undermine the legitimacy of causal reasoning, since causal
reasoning is an a priori condition of the possibility of any empirical
science at all. Second, it means that evolutionary biology is itself subject
to transcendental critique. If (again, counter-factually) Kant’s
transcendental philosophy gave some reason to call into question the
methodology of evolutionary biology, we would have to give it up as a
legitimate way of gleaning knowledge about human beings, regardless of
how otherwise handy it seems to be.193
193
For an example of this from Kant’s own work, see A173-4/B215-6 (quoted in chapter nine, p. xxx).
286 Should we be strong scientific realists? There are at least two
reasons for skepticism here.194 The first relates to Kant’s central
argument for his Copernican turn. Science operates in the context of
assumptions that guide inquiry and restrict the scope of scientific
explanation. To some extent, these assumptions are justified in
retrospect, by their success. Hypotheses are “confirmed” when they bear
fruit in terms of predictive or explanatory success. Ultimately, though,
even the claim that predictive success is an indicator of truth is a mere
assumption. And science operates with numerous heuristics (“look for
adaptive advantages of distinctive features” and “as much as possible,
explain similar effects by appeal to similar causes”) and restrictions (“do
not appeal to divine explanations” and “the future cannot cause changes
in the past”) that are not empirically tested but nonetheless constrain
scientific explanation. As Kant argues, some of these scientific
assumptions are simply impossible for human beings to question. We
explain changes in terms of causes, for example, and we assume that
nature is uniform. We might add that insofar as we engage in scientific
explanation of the world, we must treat hypotheses that have a high
degree of predictive success as more likely to be true than those – such
as divine intervention – that have no predictive value at all. But all of
these standards are rooted in the (transcendental) nature of human
cognition; they all reflect the necessary conditions for humans to
understand an empirical world. (A god probably would not need to appeal
to predictive success to confirm hypotheses.)
Evolutionary biology is a human science. As far as we can tell,
neither gods nor animals think about the world in terms of evolution by
natural selection, and there are very basic assumptions underlying
evolutionary biology that cannot be seriously questioned. What are we to
make of the importance of substantive and methodological assumptions
in human science? We could take these assumptions as self-evident, but
doing so imports a dogmatic rationalism into science. We could take
them as purely arbitrary, but this would undermine any justification for
scientific realism. We could simply not worry about them; who doubts,
after all, that a theory with massive predictive success is at least closer
to the truth than one that consistently fails to make accurate
predictions? This approach makes it psychologically possible to sustain a
commitment to strong scientific realism, but provides no justification for
that realism. Kant provides a better approach. Given that certain
conditions seem to be necessary in order for humans to experience the
world, we can simply take these conditions to be true of the world we
194
In the next chapter, I emphasize a third reason in the context of recent historicist accounts of science,
and in chapter ten, I look at existentialist critiques of scientific naturalism.
287 experience. This is a pretty strong sort of realism, in that it takes the
best scientific theories of the world to be true, but it is limited in that it
admits that the world of which these theories are true is the world as we
experience it. While preserving a substantial commitment to scientific
knowledge of the world, Kantian scientific realism rejects the God’s-eye
point of view assumed by strong scientific realists such as Dennett.
In itself, this Kantian scientific realism is consistent with strong
scientific realism (what Kant would call “transcendental realism”) in that
one could simply take on faith that the world we experience exhausts all
that there is. Just as Kant’s immediate successors argued for the
“neglected alternative,”195 contemporary naturalists might affirm that the
basic presuppositions of empirical knowledge are both necessary
structures of human cognition and sufficient for exhausting all there is
to the world. Moreover, one might wonder what the point of limiting one’s
scientific realism could be. Even if there is some mysterious worldbeyond, if we can neither experience that world nor have any way of
getting knowledge about it, what difference does it make? Even if science
does not exhaust “the whole truth,” if it exhausts everything true that
humans can know, then shouldn’t we – humans that we are – just go
ahead and be strong scientific realists?
Perhaps. But Kant gives reasons for rejecting this “neglected
alternative,” of which the most important here is that scientific
explanation is merely one perspective that human beings take on the
world. Scientific descriptions and causal explanations of the empirical
world are constrained by certain basic concepts and methodological
assumptions. But humans must also make sense of the world from
within the standpoints of practical deliberation about actions and
epistemic deliberation about scientific theories. For evolutionary biology
to provide a sufficient answer to the question “What is the human
being?” it must make sense of these standpoints. That is, strong
scientific realism – the view that science provides the whole truth –
depends upon evolutionary biology providing an adequate transcendental
anthropology. And this is something that evolutionary biology fails to do.
Evolution is very good at explaining how various human
predispositions evolved. But these stories fail to reveal the
transcendental structure of our faculties of cognition, feeling, and
volition. For example, we can tell stories about why humans have
cognitive structures that make us think that 2+2=4, but this neither
shows whether the thought that 2+2=4 is actually justified nor reveals
195
See chapter six, pp. xxx.
288 the conditions of possibility of such justification. Neither genetic nor
memetic success can explain why 2+2=4, even if they can explain why we
believe that 2+2=4. Similarly, we can tell stories about how kin selection
and cognitive evolution gives rise to genetic characteristics that
contribute to a propensity to endorse certain ethics-memes, but this
cannot show whether we are right to endorse those memes, nor what the
transcendental conditions of possibility of choice really are (that is, what
is implied in our taking ourselves to be responsible for something).
And when it comes to these sorts of normative claims, evolutionary
approaches are notoriously unhelpful. When Dennett notes that memes
that are deleterious from the point of view of survival and reproduction
“may be good for us in other, more important regards,” he says nothing
about why those other regards are or even may be more important. And
when he asks “whether or not morality itself is a feature we should try to
preserve in our societies” (Dennett 2003: 279), there is nothing in his
evolutionary account that can answer this question. An evolutionary
account might be able to explain why birth control does in fact matter
more to us than genetic fitness, but Dennett does not even attempt to
show how it can explain what makes certain goods (he offers examples
like literacy and music) genuinely more important than reproductive
success. The reason for this failure is one that Kant rightly emphasizes.
From-within, when one is actually trying to figure out what to believe,
feel, or do, one looks not for explanatory causes that could predict future
beliefs or choices but for justificatory reasons of them. Once there are
beings in the world who are capable of reason-guided reflection, those
beings take standpoints on the world from within which causal
explanations are insufficient. If one is trying to decide whether to read an
edifying book or help a friend move into a new apartment, reading a
psychological assessment of oneself that explains that one will avoid
reading books whenever one has something else to do will not actually
help one make one’s decision. And that is because, in itself, the
psychological assessment is not a reason. It might, of course, give one a
reason; one might rebel against the report just to assert one’s
independence, or one might use the report as part of a justification for
reading the book, since it is “inevitable anyway.” (Kant actually thinks
that part of the appeal of determinism is that it allows us to abdicate
responsibility and thereby act on desires and against what is really
normatively required.) But one needs some basis for taking this
psychological assessment as a reason for rebellion or complacency, and
the report itself cannot provide this basis.
The problem of justification is not limited to choices about actions;
it arises even for the practice of science itself. Evolutionary biology fails
289 to provide a justification for the very cognitive practices that it employs.
Alvin Plantinga has emphasized this point against Dennett’s evolutionary
naturalism:
Darwin's dangerous idea is really two ideas put together:
philosophical naturalism together with the claim that our cognitive
faculties have originated by way of natural selection working on some
form of genetic variation. According to this idea, then, the purpose or
function of those faculties (if they have one) is to enable or promote
survival, or survival and reproduction, more exactly, the
maximization of fitness (the probability of survival and reproduction) .
. . [T]he probability that our cognitive faculties are reliable (i.e.,
furnish us with a preponderance of true beliefs) on Darwin's
dangerous idea is either low or inscrutable . . . If so, then it also gives
[one] a reason for doubting any beliefs produced by those faculties.
This includes, of course, the beliefs involved in science itself.
(Plantinga 1996)
Insofar as memes allow human beings to transcend “selfish genes,” it is
not fair to see beliefs as serving merely to promote survival or
reproduction of genes, but Plantinga is correct that nothing about
evolution itself provides a reason to believe that beliefs that arise through
processes of evolution are justified or true.196 Kant helps us see (contra
Plantinga) that evolutionary explanation is compatible with an
epistemology that could justify knowledge-claims, but this does not show
that evolution is sufficient for such an epistemology. The empirical
account of human beings provided by evolutionary theory must be
supplemented by something like Kant’s transcendental anthropology,
and because this transcendental anthropology provides the conditions of
justification of science itself, it must be viewed as more fundamental
than evolutionary biology.197 Moreover, regardless of how sophisticated a
description of human beings – even as empirically knowable “selves” or
“agents” – we have, this description is insufficient to justify adopting any
196
Moreover, evolutionary theory may have at its disposal accounts of human cognition that could provide
justification for scientific realism. See, e.g., Popper 1972: 261ff. and Quine 1969: 126, but cf. Plantinga
1993.
197
I’m not here denying the possibility of a sort of Quinean holism or reflective equilibrium model (see
Quine 1951). Even in those models, there are forms of logical priority, but what is logically secondary can
lead to revisions in what is prior. Given the structure of the relationship between the transcendental
conditions of possibility of empirical science and the specific content of biology, any rejection of the
former would involve a rejection of the latter. Now discoveries within empirical sciences might, for Quine,
provide reasons for rejecting our transcendental conditions of science and the sciences based on them, but
the result of this wholesale revision of our epistemic landscape would not involve a subordination of
transcendental philosophy to evolutionary biology but a rejection of both in favor of some new way of
thinking about the world.
290 particular beliefs or choices without some reason to make use of this
description in some particular way. Because evolutionary biology fails to
provide for a transcendental anthropology that is nonetheless necessary,
strong scientific realism is false. Evolutionary biology might tell the truth
and nothing but the truth, but it does not tell the whole truth.
In itself, evolutionary naturalism fails to provide a transcendental
anthropology. Does it raise fundamental problems for Kant’s attempted
transcendental anthropology? Again, I think not. As in the case of
contemporary neuroscience, Kant’s distinction between empirical and
transcendental anthropology largely insulates his transcendental
anthropology from empirical objections. For example, Dennett has
criticized Kant’s moral theory in the context of his account of the
evolutionary origin of moral judgments:
Kant held that [pure, emotionless] judgments are not only the best
sort of moral judgments, they are the only sort of judgments that
count as moral judgments at all. Enlivening reflection with base
appeals to emotion may be fine for training children, but the presence
of those training wheels actually disqualifies their judgments for
moral consideration. Is this perhaps a case in which holding out for
perfection – a job-related disability in philosophers – conceals the
best path? (Dennett 2003: 213)
The question-mark here is apt, since Dennett actually provides no reason
at all for thinking that Kant is misguided to “hold out for perfection.”
How would one answer this question? Surely not by appealing to our
evolutionary history, nor even to the role that emotions actually play in
most (even all) judgments that are considered “moral.” Rather, one must
look at the structure of volition from-within, asking what would justify
“holding out for perfection” or looking for a better path. And in fact, Kant
does enter into this sort of reflection. In his Groundwork, he argues that
while human beings do in fact act for the most part from what we might
call “emotions,” when reflecting upon what we ought to do, we do not
actually think that a commitment to do what one feels like doing is
morally praiseworthy, even if one feels like doing the right thing. Kant
might be wrong about this, but if he is, it is because he misread what
volition looks like from-within, not because he failed to trace the
evolutionary origin of moral judgment.198
198
Kant also provides good from-within grounds for a stance towards moral life that both holds out for
perfection and pursues a better path. In response to radical evil, Kant insists that one must not give up
moral perfection as an ideal, but also that one can justify moral hope on the grounds of progress towards
this ideal rather than perfect conformity with it.
291 As in the case of neuroscience, contemporary evolutionary biology
fleshes out empirical anthropology far beyond Kant’s expectations. This
not only enriches our empirical self-conception but provides valuable
insights that can be used in pragmatic anthropology. But Kant’s
transcendental anthropology – or something like it – is necessary to
explain the science’s conditions of possibility and to guide how which
empirical knowledge is put to use to justify norms in terms of which
humans ought to think, feel, and act.
III. Contemporary Psychology
The previous sections drew attention to developments in biology
with significant impacts for understanding ourselves as human beings.
Many recent advances in psychology are rooted in these biological
developments. Psychologists today make extensive use of neuroscience
and evolutionary modeling in studying the human mind. For example,
one can make claims about the mental processes involved in various
activities through scanning the brain and noting which areas are most
active while subjects are engaged in various tasks, and psychologists
have used studies of animals– especially those most closely related to us
– to gain insight into the way human brains work. But psychology has
also made significant progress as a science distinct from biology, most
notably through increasingly sophisticated experimental methodologies
that provide evidence for claims about humans’ mental lives. Because
Kant developed a detailed empirical psychology, it is natural to compare
Kant’s psychology with contemporary psychological methods and
theories. Moreover, as in the case of neuroscience and evolutionary
biology, contemporary psychology has been a source for naturalist
approaches to human beings. And recently, philosophers have appealed
to specific findings in psychology that seem to raise problems for Kant’s
anthropology. This section starts with a brief Kantian discussion of
methods and models within contemporary psychology and then turns to
two ways in which contemporary psychology has fed naturalist
philosophical accounts of human beings in ways that seem to threaten
Kant’s epistemology and moral theory.
Contemporary psychology has made considerable strides towards
reappropriating a broadly Kantian approach to the mind. In the mid-20th
century, the dominant approach to psychological research was
behaviorism. Promoted especially by B.F. Skinner, behaviorist
292 psychologists assumed that human mental life was reducible to
externally observable behaviors. In its most extreme form, the human
mind was seen as a mere stimulus-response machine, and psychology
was the science of classifying stimuli and responses. During the past 50
years, however, psychologists have regained an interest in the mind as
such. Partly this has been for experimental reasons; one famous study
on rats suggest the reality of “latent learning,” where animals make
evident that they knew things that were not normally expressed in
behavior (see, e.g. Tolman and Hoznik 1930 and Rescorla 1991). Partly,
though, the shift away from behaviorism comes from a more obvious
source. Human behavior is not a brute fact, nor should scientists be
limited in explaining it to laying out a sequence of physical states.199
Certain very simple human responses might be explicable in terms of
innate or conditioned responses to stimuli. Humans may innately
respond to the perception of a yawn with another yawn, and can be
taught to yawn on cue if sufficiently conditioned. But even to explain
something as simple as why one runs out of a flaming building (see
Pinker 1997:62) or why one looks for one’s own car in a parking lot, one
must appeal to beliefs and desires. And more complicated aspects of
being human seem utterly inexplicable without appealing to mental
states as such. Imagine trying to distinguish, based purely on
conditioned responses, between a person who marries for money,
another who marries because she doesn’t want to die old and alone,
another who remains unmarried to avoid a messy divorce later, and a
last who doesn’t marry in order to have a good career. Explanations in
terms of mental states are straightforward and predictively successful;
those in terms of external inputs and behavioral outputs alone are
hopelessly insufficient. Thus the study of mental states as such has
become a mainstay of psychology (again).
For Kant, this is welcome. Kant’s psychology is a systematic study
of mental states and the relationships between them. Like contemporary
psychologists, Kant is willing to explain some behaviors in terms of
conditioned responses, but like most psychologists today, he appeals to
more complicated mental states to explain most human behavior.
Moreover, like contemporary psychologists, Kant is not content with
casual folk psychological explanations of behavior. Although he resists
behaviorism, Kant seeks law-like relationships among clearly delineated
types of mental states. And this brings out a further important parallel
between Kant’s psychology and contemporary psychology. Increasingly,
199
Even the most ardent behaviorists (such as Skinner himself) implicitly made use of descriptions of
stimuli and responses that appealed to internal psychological states. For discussion, see Dennett 1978,
Fodor 1968, and Pinker 1997.
293 psychologists today reject “blank-slate” approaches to human mental life
in favor of an approaches that look more like Kant’s taxonomy of basic
powers.200 As one philosopher of psychology has put it, “one of the major
insights of [contemporary psychology] has been the extent to which we
depend upon a natural cognitive endowment, which assigns processing
tasks to modular structures with quite specific and restricted domains
and inputs” (Botterill and Carruthers 1999:50; see too Fodor 1983,
Pinker 2002). This “modular” approach to the mind rejects the reduction
of all mental processes to a few simple potentials that develop in different
ways through human learning. Just as Kant divided the mental into
irreducible but interacting “powers” and “faculties” that operate by
different causal laws, contemporary psychologists study the human mind
as a set of interacting “modules” that perform different tasks in bringing
about human thoughts and actions. Moreover, like Kant, psychologists
distinguish between the biological bases for mental modules (what Kant
would call predispositions) and the fully-formed mental modules (powers)
that emerge when these bases are able to develop in particular contexts
(Botterill and Carruthers 1999:96).
There are still important differences between Kant’s basic powers
and modern mental modules. Kant’s approach was situated within a
metaphysical model of substances interacting by means of powers, while
the modern approach sees modules not as distinctive active properties of
a substance but as mental functions rooted in the evolved architecture of
the brain. Kant’s “powers” were also fairly commonsensical, and one
distinguished between them using a broadly introspective approach. And
Kantian powers are domain-general, in that a given power covers a wide
range of possible contents. (Reasoning about baseball statistics and
reasoning about the reliability of one’s friends are both rooted in the
same basic power: reason.) The result is a cognitive map including
powers of vision and hearing, of judgment and reason, of feeling and
desire. By contrast, modern modular accounts of the mind assume that
most modules are unconscious and can be distinguished by studying
developmental evidence (how children’s cognition is able to progress in
some ways before/without developing in other ways), psychological
damage (where one module’s activity is inhibited but not others’), and
even brain-scanning (looking for regions of the brain active in various
tasks). And domain-specific modular accounts of the mind are
increasingly the norm. Thus the lists of mental modules in contemporary
psychology look quite different from Kant’s taxonomy of powers,
200
For the sake of simplicity, I am conflating a blank-slate approach with an anti-modular approach. The
most common forms of anti-modularism are black slate approaches, though there are ways of avoiding both
approaches to mind, such as connectionism and associationism. For further discussion, see Pinker 1997.
294 including specific modules for the perception of color, the perception of
shape, the detection of rhythm, and the recognition of other people
(Fodor 1983: 47-8). While Kant shares with contemporary psychology a
commitment to broad heuristics according to which structures of the
mind are distinguished based on empirical evidence, the much broader
range and types of evidence today has given rise to a taxonomy that is
both different from and more fine-grained than Kant’s.
Kant could accept most of these modifications of his view. While
Kant sought to reduce the number of basic powers to as few as possible,
he would accept that mental structures that seemed unified to him –
such as vision, say, or reason – involve irreducible sub-components. As
some recent philosophers of psychology have noted, “failure to draw a
distinction is not at all the same thing as denying that there is a
distinction” (Botterill and Carruthers 1999:73). Kant did not draw all the
distinctions of contemporary modular psychology, but his empirical
methodology lends itself to a willingness to admit sub-distinctions within
his overall faculty psychology. And many of Kant’s most important
distinctions, such as his tri-partite conception of mental faculties or his
distinction between higher and lower cognition, have been vindicated by
recent psychological research.201 The fact that many of these processes
are unconscious need not pose intractable problems for Kant’s empirical
psychology. 202 While there is a philosophical challenge in making sense
of what it means for a mental state to be unconscious, Kant already
made important steps in this direction. Natural propensities need not be
conscious, lower faculties are not conscious in a reflective sense, and
201
With respect to the tripartite soul, recent research on the chemical bases of pleasure suggests that
pleasure is often but not always connected with desire. Among the most interesting work in this regard is
psychological research suggesting that there is a sort of pre-cognitive feeling of pleasure and pain that is
(sometimes) transformed into something with cognitive and volitional import. The evidence for this
distinctive feeling of pleasure comes from at least two sources. From neurobiology, the recognition that
certain chemical changes in the brain – most notably, the release of endorphins – is consistent across a wide
variety of pleasurable emotions, suggests that there is some basic psychological state shared in common
between these emotions. Situationist psychological research confirms this through studies that show that
the same physiological states will be interpreted as different emotions depending upon situational cues. For
example, in the Capilano Suspension Bridge Experiment, two investigators found that male subjects who
have just crossed over a rickety suspension bridge see themselves as more attracted to female interviewers
than those who have crossed over a safe and secure bridge; the subjects interpret the high heart rate caused
by their anxiety as sexual attraction (see Dutton and Aron 1974).
202
Given that Kant’s psychology is based largely on introspection, one might think that Kant cannot allow
unconscious mental states to play a role in it, since such states are, by definition, unavailable to
introspective awareness. But while introspection enjoys a central place in Kant’s psychological method, he
also makes inferences from that which is directly available to introspection and posits psychological
features of which we are not immediately conscious. There is therefore nothing in Kant’s psychological
methodology that precludes him from accepting unconscious mental states insofar as these are needed to
make sense of what is observed (through introspection and perception of behavior).
295 Kant was perfectly willing to allow for unconscious physical processes
underlying humans’ mental states. To make the further move that there
could be particular psychological processes that operate like conscious
mental states but without consciousness is a step beyond Kant, but not
one he would have to reject.
Methodologically, however, two shifts have occurred over the past
100 years that raise questions about Kant’s conception of the nature of
empirical psychology. First, Kant insisted in his philosophy of science
that psychology “can . . . never become . . . a science” (4:471). Given the
progress over the past 200 years, one might ask: Is contemporary
psychology a genuine science? Second, Kant’s own empirical
anthropology is rooted in introspection, but introspection is widely
regarded with suspicion in contemporary psychology. One might wonder,
then, whether contemporary psychology has shown the fruitlessness of
the fundamental bases of Kant’s empirical psychology. With respect to
both issues, Kant is actually much closer to contemporary psychology
than it might seem, and where they diverge, Kant raises genuinely
important issues that contemporary psychology should address.
With respect to the first issue – the scientific status of psychology –
there is virtually no real disagreement between Kant and contemporary
psychologists about the nature of psychology. Psychology today, as for
Kant, is a wholly empirical study of the human mind that aims to lay out
the structure and explain the development of human mental structures.
Psychologists aim to explain the full range of human mental processes
using the simplest general structures. Specific thoughts and actions as
well as the mind’s underlying structures should be explained in
accordance with causal laws. On all of these points, Kant’s description of
psychology fits contemporary practice. But Kant calls this sort of
discipline a “natural history of the mind” that is only a “science” in a
loose sense. For Kant, science strictly speaking must have an a priori
foundation, and Kant insists that no such foundation can be found for
psychology. As far as contemporary psychologists indicate, Kant is
correct.
There are two ways, however, in which contemporary psychology is
more “scientific” than Kant supposed possible. First, psychology has
made substantial progress towards rooting psychological explanation
(especially of the origin of human mental structures) in biological
explanation. Kant, too, situated his psychology in the context of biology,
but – as we saw in the last section – he underestimated the extent to
which a causal account of the origin of human beings could be given. In
that sense, evolution-informed psychology goes beyond Kant’s
296 expectations for the science. Second, Kant insisted that “there can be
only so much proper science as there is mathematics therein” (4:470) and
that “mathematics is not applicable to” psychology (4:471). But some
forms of contemporary psychology are highly mathematical. In addition
to mathematical models of brain activity, contemporary experimental
psychology is largely dependent upon statistics to describe, organize, and
interpret data. Nonetheless, while this mathematization of psychology is
important and unexpected by Kant, the kind of mathematics of which
psychologists make use is not one that confers scientific status in Kant’s
sense. For Kant, mathematics makes physics scientific because it allows
the physicist to make a priori claims at the foundation of physics. (For
example, Kant uses the fact that the surface area of a sphere is
proportional to the square of the distance from the center of the sphere
to argue – a priori – for an inverse-square law for gravitational force.)
While mathematical laws of statistics help psychologists process
empirical data more effectively, they provide no a priori insights into the
nature of the mind.
With respect to the second issue – introspection – the divergence
between Kant and psychology today might seem more important. While
Kant insisted that empirical anthropology “is provided with a content by
inner sense” (7: 398, cf. 25:252, 863-5), contemporary psychologists
often disparage “introspection” as an outdated and unscientific approach
to studying the mind. Moreover, there is empirical evidence questioning
introspection as a methodological tool. The most famous article to this
effect concludes that “there may be little or no direct introspective access
to higher order cognitive processes” (Nisbett and Wilson 1977: 231). The
evidence comes from countless studies in which subjects questioned
about the causes of their own beliefs or actions fail to accurately report
on these causes. In one such study, subjects were invited to evaluate the
quality of various consumer products (4 different nightgowns in one
iteration of the study, 4 identical nylon stockings in another). The result
was “a pronounced left-to-right position effect, such that the rightmost
object in the array was heavily over-chosen. For the stockings, the effect
was quite large, with the rightmost stockings . . . preferred . . . by a
factor of almost four to one.” But although the position of the products
was clearly a factor the choices of at least some subjects,
when asked about the reasons for their choices, no subject even
mentioned spontaneously the position of the article . . . and when
asked directly about a possible effect of the position of the article,
virtually all subjects denied it, usually with a worried glance at the
interviewer suggesting that they felt either that they had
297 misunderstood the question or were dealing with a madman. (Nisbett
and Wilson 1977: 243-4)
Introspection is so unreliable that even when people seem to be accurate
about what is really moving them to make a particular judgment or
decision, the authors conclude (and have evidence to back up) that this
accuracy is based on an inference from behavior and context to internal
states, precisely the same sort of inference that would be made by an
external observer.203
In fact, however, Kant and contemporary psychology are far closer
than they seem, even with respect to introspection. For one thing, the
move away from behaviorism requires at least some appeal to
introspection. Even the claim, for example, that “subjects are . . .
unaware of the existence of a stimulus that importantly influenced a
response” (Nisbett and Wilson 1977: 231) assumes that the reports
(and/or the “worried glances”) of subjects are reliable indicators of the
subjects’ “awareness.” But the need for some reliance on introspection
goes much deeper insofar as non-behaviorist psychologists take this
research to have implications for how mental states themselves can be
studied. As Nisbett and Wilson put it,
The explanations that subjects offer for their behavior in insufficientjustification and attribution experiments are so removed from the
processes that investigators presume to have occurred as to give
grounds for considerable doubt that there is direct access to these
processes. (Nisbett and Wilson 1977: 238)
“Insufficient-justification” experiments are those in which subjects are
given very small inducement (say, $1) to perform unpleasant tasks, and
subjects typically report that tasks to be more pleasant than those who
are given stronger inducement (say, $20). Investigators typically explain
this in terms of a need for subjects to see themselves as having acted
reasonably. Since a small inducement is not a good reason for
performing a very unpleasant task, subjects convince themselves that
the task is not really that unpleasant. But most subjects, even when
explained this hypothesis, cannot see themselves as having been moved
by this consideration. Introspection fails to pick out relevant mental
processes. Importantly, however, the investigators’ attribution of these
mental processes to their subjects is based, at least indirectly, on
203
I really mean precisely the same sort of inference. Studies have shown that those participating in the
experiments and external observers make the same judgments – either accurate or inaccurate – about
participants’ internal states. Apparently, introspection does not introduce any significant new information
about what is going on. (See references in Nisbett and Wilson 1977 and Bem 1967.)
298 introspection. Investigators do not merely think that $1 has a magical
property of reducing unpleasantness while $20 lacks such a property.
Instead, they think about what would “make sense” of the different
responses of subjects. But this judgment of “making sense” is based on a
very general sort of introspection, one’s long experience with the sorts of
considerations that motivate one to think and act in certain ways.204
Even if people are often wrong about the particular motives for particular
reactions in particular cases, introspection still seems to be an effective
and even necessary tool for discerning what general sorts of mental
states there are and how, in general terms, these mental states interact
with one another. Insofar as psychologists make claims about mental
states as such, rather than seeing people as mere stimulus-response
mechanisms, they must include at least some appeal to introspective
awareness.205
Of course, the need to appeal to introspection in this general way
does not alleviate the very real problems to which these experiments
draw attention. But here it is important to recognize that Kant, too, was
acutely aware of the limits of introspection. In his Anthropology, Kant
lists “considerable difficulties” that face any psychology seeking to
“trac[e] everything that lies hidden in” the human mind. He specifically
mentions both dissembling, where one “does not want to be known as he
is” and a sort of embarrassment that make it impossible to show oneself
as one really is. And with respect to many mental processes, Kant points
204
Cf. NW 1977: 248, where Nisbett and Wilson rightly point out that many of these theories can come
from cultural inheritances. We inculcate cultural expectations about how people act and why, and these “a
priori causal theories” affect our judgments about motivation in particular circumstances. But this only
provides a partial explanation, since these cultural theories must originate and evolve somehow. Most
plausibly, the origin of such theories is introspective; people pay attention to and generalize their own
motivational structure, and then refine their theories through ongoing interaction with others, including
others’ introspective reports.
205
Kant’s approach to human beings can also help shed light on an important possible problem with the
structure of these self-reporting experiments. When asked why one did something, one can interpret this
question either as an empirical-causal one or as a transcendental-justificatory one. A question like “Why
did you prefer that stocking over the others?” is most naturally seen as addressing a person from-within,
asking for a justification rather than a causal explanation of the judgment. As a justification, the fact that
the stocking was furthest to the right is, frankly, mad. (Hence the “worried glance.”) Given Kant’s careful
distinction between introspection – where one looks from-without at one’s internal states – and the fromwithin perspective of justification, one might reasonably conclude that many of these psychological
experiments prompt, not introspection, but self-justification. One interesting experiment in this regard
(Lepper et. al. 1970) even suggests an important connection between the justificatory structure used to
“explain” one’s decision and the deliberative context of the decision itself. How one “explains” one’s
actions seems to depend upon what one needed to think at the time of those actions to justify them fromwithin. Exciting introspection (and cultivating a discipline of careful introspection) is something that
requires specific instructions that can be missing from these psychological experiments. True introspection
– if genuinely elicited – might be more effective than these experiments suggest.
299 out that “when the incentives are active, he does not observe himself,
and when he does observe himself, the incentives are at rest” (7:120-121,
398-9). As with Kant’s empirical anthropology in general, contemporary
psychological research has provided substantially more specification of
and evidence for the difficulties with introspection to which Kant drew
attention. But Kant was not so naïve about introspection that he would
find this recent psychological research surprising, nor is psychology
today capable of doing without at least the general and constantly
corrected introspection that Kant saw as lying at the heart of empirical
anthropology.
Kant’s approach to psychology, then, is broadly compatible with
contemporary “scientific” psychology. But as in the cases of neuroscience
and evolutionary biology, philosophers have appropriated psychology in
the service of a thoroughgoing naturalism about human beings.
Psychological naturalism need be neither materialist nor reductionist,
which alleviates some of the problems directed against neuroscientific
naturalism in section one.206 Since multiple realizability is a problem
only for naturalisms that attempt to reduce the psychological to the
physical, it not a problem at all for psychological naturalism. Qualia and
intentionality might pose problems for psychological naturalism, since
these properties of mental states seem to manifest themselves primarily
from-within cognition, but even mental qualia and intentionality can
become objects of introspective awareness and in that sense could be
incorporated into a scientific psychology. The biggest problem for
psychological naturalism is the problem of normativity, the justificatory
status of reasons from-within. To solve this problem requires providing
psychologically-rooted, naturalized epistemology and ethics.
Naturalizing epistemology has become a thriving research program
among philosophers today (see Feldman 2001). At its most extreme, such
a view involves the commitment to wholly replacing epistemology with
psychology. As W.V. Quine famously put it,
Epistemology, or something like it, simply falls into place as a
chapter of psychology and hence of natural science. It studies a
natural phenomenon, viz., a physical human subject. This human
subject is accorded a certain experimentally controlled input -206
Psychological naturalism is a sort of “naturalism” because it posits that “human beings are . . . subject to
. . . laws of nature,” that is, to “laws of some or other natural science;” but it need be neither reductionist
nor materialist because one can defend the “scientific status of . . . psychology directly, without seeking any
sort of reduction” (Botterill and Carruthers, pp. 1, 186-7).
300 certain patterns of irradiation in assorted frequencies, for instance -and in the fullness of time the subject delivers as output a
description of the three-dimensional external world and its history.
The relation between the meager input and the torrential output is a
relation that we are prompted to study for somewhat the same
reasons that always prompted epistemology: namely, in order to see
how evidence relates to theory, and in what ways one’s theory of
nature transcends any available evidence...But a conspicuous
difference between old epistemology and the epistemological
enterprise in this new psychological setting is that we can now make
free use of empirical psychology. (Quine, 1969: 82-3)
As critics have noted (see, e.g. Kim 1988: 390), such an approach risks
giving up the normative dimension of epistemology. As we saw with
respect to evolutionary naturalism, there is no reason to think that the
theories of natural sciences will be able to make sense of the normative
foundations of knowledge claims as such.
In practice, therefore, most attempts at naturalism in epistemology
today are more modest than Quine’s.207
A fundamental goal of psychology is to describe how humans reason.
A fundamental goal of epistemology – the theory of knowledge – is to
set out how humans ought to reason, and so to acquire knowledge.
There is no responsible way of answering the second question
without accurately answering the first.208
Even at this level of generality, Kant would resist epistemic naturalism.
In general, his response to psychological naturalism will be similar to his
response to evolutionary and neuroscientific naturalism. For the
purposes of studying human beings as empirical objects, naturalism is
appropriate, so the best scientific psychology should give the most
empirically adequate characterizations of and explanations for humans’
thoughts, feelings, motives, and behavior. But naturalism cannot
adequately make sense of the normative demands implicit within
humans’ transcendental standpoint. Rather than recapitulate this
argument in general terms, the rest of this section focuses on two recent
philosophical attempts to appropriate insights from empirical psychology
to make normative claims about human beings. Showing how Kant might
respond to these attempts will further highlight the important distinction
(and relationship) between transcendental and empirical anthropology.
207
Even Quine’s own naturalism has grown more modest. Cf. Quine 1990.
J.D. Trout, from the course description of his course in epistemology, available online at
http://www.jdtrout.com/?q=node/35, accessed 3-3-2009.
208
301 One arena of contemporary psychological research that has
garnered substantial philosophical attention is the so-called “biases and
heuristics” research program pioneered by Daniel Kahneman and Amos
Tversky. This research program has shown a striking degree of
irrationality in human thinking, even among experts thinking about
highly significant but fairly straightforward problems in their field of
expertise. It has highlighted several pervasive forms of human
irrationality, including the “fundamental attribution error” (attributing
behavior to character traits rather than situational factors), “base-rate
neglect,” self-serving bias (the “Lake Wobegon effect”), and various
illusions that arise from seeking to make our experiences match our
expectations. For one example (base-rate neglect), faculty and students
at Harvard Medical School were given the following problem:
If a test to detect a disease whose prevalence is 1/1000 has a false
positive rate of 5% [i.e., 5% of people who take the test falsely test
positive for the disease], what is the chance that a person found to
have a positive result actually has the disease . . .? (Casscells,
Schoenberger, and Grayboys 1978, cited in Bishop and Trout 2005:
122)
Almost half of the respondents (and a much higher percentage of nonexperts) answer that the chances of having the disease are 95%, and only
one in five respondents give the correct answer (the chances are actually
less than 2%).209 So far, all of this is only empirical description of how
humans in fact reason. But this and similar studies of human rationality
call into question our ability to make good decisions, and they have led
some epistemologists to argue for radical revisions in how we ought to
employ our reasoning ability. Michael Bishop and J.D. Trout use this
research to offer a wholesale rejection of what they call “Standard
Analytic Epistemology”(Bishop and Trout 2005: 104-118). Among other
things, they argue “that it would often be much better if experts, when
making high-stakes judgments, ignored most of the evidence, did not try
to weigh that evidence, and didn’t try to make a judgment based on their
long experience” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 25). Because of the
unreliability of basic cognitive processes, we should replace those
processes with others that are empirically demonstrated to be more
reliable.
209
Most people reason that since the false-positive is 5%, the 95% of positive tests must be true. The
correct answer is given by reasoning as follows: For every 1000 people, 50 (5%) will falsely test positive
and one will truly test positive. Thus there will be 51 people who test positive, one of whom actually has
the disease. That is, the chance that the person actually has the disease is slightly less than 2%.
302 Contemporary research in psychology is also use in ethics. One
prominent use has been “situationist” critiques of character-based
ethical theories.210 Psychological research has increasingly shown the
context-sensitivity of human decision-making, and philosophers like
John Doris and Gilbert Harman use this research to critique characterbased ethics: “The experimental record suggests that situational factors
are often better predictors of behavior than personal factors . . . To put it
crudely, people typically lack character”(Doris 2002:2, cf. Doris 2002:5-6,
15-22 and Harman 2000: 168, 178).211 In one particularly dramatic
example, students at Princeton seminary were invited to participate in a
study of religious vocation. Subjects filled out questionnaires and were
told to give a verbal presentation on the story of the Good Samaritan
(Luke 10:25-37) in another building. After the questionnaire, subjects
were told that they were either late, on time, or early for the presentation.
Along the way, the subjects passed an (apparently) extremely distressed
person. Whether students stopped to help correlated strongly with their
level of hurry, with only 10% of the “high hurry” subjects stopping and
63% of the “low hurry” subjects stopping. In this and many other cases,
circumstances are better predictors of behavior than character. Many
philosophers take “situationist psychology” to imply that “[r]ather than
striving to develop characters that will determine our behavior in ways
substantially independent of circumstance, we should invest more of our
energies attending to the features of our environment that influence
behavioral outcomes” (Doris 2002: 146).
How would Kant respond to these and similar sorts of
developments? Starting with the empirical psychology itself, Kant’s
empirical anthropology is not only compatible with but actually
anticipates the findings of both the biases and heuristics program and
situationism. Most of its empirical detail of Kant’s account of cognition
comes in his description of various “prejudices” that explain how people
diverge from ideal ways of thinking. Like the biases and heuristics
program, Kant both characterizes the effects of these prejudices and
diagnoses their underlying grounds. Of course, the specific principles
that Kant lays out are not the same as those discovered recently, and
Kant’s introspective methodology differs substantially from the
experimental and statistical methods being used today. But the overall
210
Although these criticisms are typically directed against theories of “virtue ethics” inspired by Aristotle,
they seemingly apply as well to Kant’s own moral theory, within which action on the basis of consistent
maxims that constitute one’s character is a central feature of moral decision-making.
211
For an excellent defense of ancient virtue ethics against these sorts of critiques, see Kamtekar 2003.
303 structure of Kant’s account – supplementing a logic of ideal thoughtprocesses with detailed empirical studies of systematic divergences from
those ideals – is consistent with the biases and heuristics program.
Similarly, with respect to human choice and action, Kant insists that
character in the strict sense is “rare” (7:292); while most people have
something like character, in that they often act on the basis of principles,
Kant – like situationists – argues that which specific principles people
actually act on depend, often in ways that they do not acknowledge
themselves, on contingent circumstances and inclinations. Kant’s
empirical account of action requires amendment and refinement in the
context of recent situationist research. More actions might be motivated
by lower faculties that Kant envisioned, and the ways in which character
is affected by circumstances seem to be more complicated than he
supposed. But the fundamental structure of Kant’s empirical
anthropology is not challenged by this work.
With respect to both situationism and biases and heuristics,
however, Kant’s ability to endorse key findings of contemporary
psychological research would be conjoined with vehement rejection of the
dominant ways that naturalist philosophers make use of that research.
This anti-naturalism is clearest in the context of Kant’s ethics. Whereas
ethical naturalists see in situationist psychology a reason to “invest . . .
our energies attending to the features of our environment that influence
behavioral outcomes” (Doris 2002:146), Kant sees situationist psychology
as an empirical confirmation of humans’ radical evil (see Frierson 2010c).
Rather than accomodating the demands of morality to the general lack of
character among human beings, Kant argues for precisely the opposite
emphasis. Since Kant gives good a priori grounds for the moral
importance of character,212 the rarity of character provides a reason to do
empirical research on the means by which character can be cultivated.
Kant suggests specific, empirically-informed techniques for cultivating
character in oneself and others, including such things as the importance
of avoiding even apparently innocent dissembling, keeping company with
specific sorts of people, and “moderat[ing] our fear of offending against
fashion” (7:294). As with much of his pragmatic anthropology, these
suggestions are based on limited empirical knowledge. But rather than
subordinating moral philosophy to situationist psychology, Kant’s
approach suggests the importance of devoting resources to studying the
means to cultivating and fostering character. Thus rather than using the
fact that situational variables were highly explanatory of behavior in the
Princeton seminary case, Kant would focus on the 10% of “high hurry”
212
See chapters one and three, and Frierson 2006.
304 subjects that did stop, in order to gain insights that might make it
possible to better foster strong character in a larger range of people. If all
that matters morally is maximizing good behavior or consequences, then
one might reasonably take situationism in psychology to imply that
resources should be devoted to putting people in situations conducive to
behaving well. But if, as Kant argues, it matters morally whether or not
one acts from a good character, then one cannot ignore character even if
it is difficult to cultivate.
Similarly, with respect to epistemology, Kant can and does make
use of empirical insights into flawed reasoning for the purposes of
pragmatic anthropology. The fact that people err in reasoning in
predictable and systematic ways gives one good reasons to develop
techniques for counter-acting these errors and for cultivating reasoning
abilities less liable to error. But the facts about how people do reason
cannot in themselves set the standard for how people ought to reason.
One example of such normative divergence can be highlighted by the
recent attempt by Bishop and Trout to use empirical studies of human
reasoning to justify reasoning strategies such as the use of “statistical
prediction rules,” simple rules based on a few variables that highly
correlate with desired predictions. For example, to figure out whether a
married couple will be happy (or at least, report that they are happy),
“take the couple’s rate of lovemaking and subtract from it their rate of
fighting” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 30). Or, to figure out whether a
particular patient is neurotic or psychotic, use the “Goldberg Rule,” a
formula based on the patient’s MMPI (Minnesota Multiphasic Personality
Inventory) profile. The point is not merely that these rules should be
used as part of deliberation, but that one should take them to trump
one’s own considered judgment, even if one is an expert. Thus no matter
how well you think you know a couple, you would do better to use the
simple “lovemaking-minus-fighting” rule than to judge based on your
experience, and no matter how sophisticated a clinician you are, you
should use the Goldberg Rule rather than your own careful and detailed
assessment of the patient’s mental state. The evidence for this is that,
quite simply, moderately good SPRs work better than even very good
expert opinion: “when tested on a set of 861 patients, the Goldberg Rule
had a [success] rate of 70%; clinicians’ . . . varied from . . . 55% to . . .
67%” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 89). Relative to judgments based on long
experience and careful examination of all available evidence, simple
prediction rules take less effort, require fewer facts as inputs, and give
more accurate results.
305 Bishop and Trout recognize that as tidy as these rules look from
outside the process of reasoning, it is very difficult to remain faithful to
them in practice:
We understand the temptations of defection. We know what it’s like
to use a reasoning strategy of proven reliability when it seems to give
an answer not warranted by the evidence. It feels like you’re about to
make an unnecessary error. And maybe you are. But in order to
make fewer errors overall, we have to accept that we will sometimes
make errors we could have corrected, errors that we recognized as
errors but made them nonetheless . . . People often lack the discipline
to adhere to a superior strategy that doesn’t “feel” right. Reasoning in
a way that “feels” wrong takes discipline. (B&T 2005: 91)
When thinking about a pair of close friends who don’t make love much,
who fight about substantive issues and end up “stronger for it,” who
work and play together and have kids that they love and care for, it can
seem insane to limit my judgment about their happiness to a simple
“lovemaking-minus-fighting” calculus. But Bishop and Trout claim, for a
variety of cases like this one, that we precisely should ignore the
additional experience and evidence that we think is relevant and focus
just on the simple formula. From-within, such a strategy can seem
irrational, and hence Bishop and Trout say that they “understand” the
temptation to defect. But we should resist that temptation so that we will
get better epistemic results.
Despite their assurances to the contrary, however, Bishop and
Trout’s emphasis on “feeling” suggests to me that they do not really
understand the temptation to defect. The problem is not merely that
something “feels” wrong, but that ignoring evidence violates an epistemic
standard to which we hold ourselves from-within. Bishop and Trout
suggest revising epistemic standards away from reasoning based on what
seems to be good evidence towards reasoning that brings about good
effects, whether aletheic (truth-conducing) or otherwise: “The primary
aim of epistemology, from our perspective, is to provide useful, general
advice about reasoning” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 94, emphasis added),
where advice is “useful” towards the end of “human well-being,”
including such things as “avoid[ing] pain and misery” (Bishop and Trout
2005: 94); “health, deep social attachments, personal security, the
pursuit of significant projects” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 99), and even
“discovering the truth about the basic physical or social structure of the
world” (Bishop and Trout 2005: 97). This pragmatic purpose of
knowledge might seem obvious, especially when we add discovering truth
as one of the central aims of good reasoning. But in fact, it is not clear
306 that maximizing true beliefs about practically and theoretically relevant
features of the world is or should be our highest epistemic value.
Consider here Kant’s famous slogan: “Sapere aude,” or “think for
yourself.” Kant points out, precisely in the context of defending
intellectual autonomy, that such thinking will, especially at first, lead to
more error than simply trusting formulaic thoughts handed down by
experts, and cautions that “the danger . . . makes [those starting to think
for themselves] timid and usually frightens them away from any further
attempt” (8:35). But for Kant, autonomy of thought is a value in itself.
Kant does not spend much time defending autonomy as an epistemic
value, but one might make an argument here akin to his argument for
the value of moral autonomy. Human beings are cognitively free precisely
because we have an ability to weigh evidence for ourselves. Insofar as we
relinquish that capacity, we relinquish our freedom, and, in an important
sense, no longer “think” at all.213 Much more would need to be said here
in order to fully defend what we might call a “deontological” epistemic
standard against Bishop and Trout’s basically consequentialist standard.
But it should at least be clear that the application of psychological
research on the aletheic and practical benefits of certain reasoning
strategies is not sufficient to justify those strategies epistemically.214
So what should we do if we find that reasoning strategies that are
most accurate and useful involve relinquishing epistemic autonomy? We
can’t complacently just accept that we will think false things when we try
to think for ourselves, ignoring the data. And we also shouldn’t abdicate
our responsibility for thinking for ourselves. What is called for is a more
sophisticated applied epistemology, one that looks for ways to maximize
overall good thinking, which includes the value of autonomy. That is, we
should focus on developing strategies and even rules of reasoning that do
not require ignoring available evidence but that give effective tools for
autonomously thinking through that evidence in ways that help us get
accurate and helpful results while still genuinely thinking for ourselves.
Kant, in his lectures on logic, offers some beginning of an empirical
theory of helps and hindrances to good reasoning, and includes the
importance (and a recognition of the difficulty) of using rules of reasoning
213
We can see this if we think about how we might evaluate epistemic failure. If one weighs all the
evidence and makes a judgment in accordance with one’s best estimate of where the evidence falls, one’s
epistemic merit (or demerit) will be genuinely one’s own. But if one simply applies a Statistical Prediction
Rule, and that rule turns out to be misguided (even systematically misguided), it is not really my epistemic
mistake. It is the mistake of the rule.
214
To be fair, Bishop and Trout recognize this, and see “better identify[ing] what is involved in human
well-being” as a necessary step for further research (Bishop and Trout 2005: 156). (Unfortunately, they
mistakenly think that defining human well-being is largely an empirical matter (Bishop and Trout 2005: 99,
156).
307 consistently, diagnosing and unvieling prejudices, and incorporating
social reasoning into individual judgment. Much more detail is needed,
and a Kantian reorientation of the empirical discipline of ameliorative
psychology might be just what is needed to facilitate greater accuracy
and usefulness in reasoning while preserving that autonomy the loss of
which “feels” wrong and “tempts” us to defect.
IV. Naturalism and Freedom
This chapter has only scratched the surface of the amazing
progress in our empirical understanding of human beings over the past
200 years. From the standpoint of Kant’s empirical psychology, this
progress is largely welcome. Kant fully accepted the possibility of
natural-causal accounts of human cognition and activity. He developed
psychological theories about the nature and functions of various human
mental faculties and conjectured about the brain chemistry that made
such mental faculties possible. And while Kant was skeptical of the
possibilities for fully understanding either the brain-states that underlie
human mental life or the historical causes of our basic mental
structures, nothing about his philosophical approach to human beings
precludes such developments. Kant’s transcendental philosophy even
provides grounds for insisting upon a thoroughly naturalist account of
human beings within empirical anthropology. At the same time, his
pragmatic anthropology shows some ways of making use of empirical
findings for improving human lives, and – like ameliorative psychology
today – Kant insisted that empirical research on human beings should be
put to practical use. But Kant’s transcendental anthropology suggests
caution in taking developments in our empirical understanding of
human beings to imply the sort of thoroughgoing naturalism that would
preclude the need for a priori theorizing about human beings fromwithin. Empirical knowledge about how humans think, feel, or choose
cannot establish the ultimate normative standards to which our
thinking, feelings, and choices should be held. In that sense, Kant
embeds a naturalist approach to science in modesty about science’s
scope. Rather than seeing natural sciences as a God’s-eye perspective on
all reality, Kant insists that they are human ways of understanding the
world we experience. And these sciences must be supplemented with an
account of human beings that makes sense of normativity in our lives. In
laying out the relationship between transcendental and empirical
anthropology, Kant’s philosophy not only solves a pressing problem of
the modern age – how to take both science and values seriously – but
308 also helps cut off many of the more egregious misuses of contemporary
scientific theories (to justify sloppy thinking or immoral actions).
So far, however, this chapter has side-stepped what is perhaps the
most important point of contention between Kant’s philosophy and
contemporary sciences. Central to Kant’s philosophy is his view that
human beings are “transcendentally free,” uncaused causes of changes
in the world. Many have (rightly) seen that the sciences depend upon a
more determinist conception of human beings and thus have (wrongly)
taken the sciences to disprove Kant’s account of freedom. Others have
(rightly) recognized the importance of a Kantian conception of freedom for
making sense of our lives and thus have (wrongly) tried to find a place for
freedom within the natural sciences. Both of these approaches are
(partially) misguided, but they reflect the real urgency of the problem of
freedom. Echoing Kant (see Bxxix), the psychologist Steven Pinker has
put the problem this way: “Either we dispense with all morality as an
unscientific superstition, or we find a way to reconcile causation (genetic
or otherwise) with responsibility and free will” (Pinker 1997:55).
Roughly speaking, we can outline four different ways of thinking
about freedom in relation to contemporary natural science:
(1) Anti-normative fatalism. For many, this is the most natural
response to insights of natural sciences into the brain-dependence of
mental states, the genetic and memetic bases of human behavior, or
psychological determinism. If the sciences can explain what a human
being does by appealing to causes that are part of the natural world, and
especially if these causes can in principle be traced to causes that preexisted the birth of the human being, then human beings are not free
and hence not responsible for our thoughts or actions (e.g. Pereboom
2001). (A rarely invoked variation on this theme is to declare science to
be fatalistic but to reject science in favor of morality.)
There are several major problems with this view. First, it involves a
non sequitur.215 The fact that sciences can explain human behavior
causally need not imply (as Kant showed in his Third Antinomy, see
chapter one) that human beings are not free. Second, it overstates the
result of contemporary human sciences. While scientists assume that
human behavior can be explained in terms of natural causes,
contemporary human sciences are far from succeeding in actually
explaining human complexity in natural terms except in the broadest
outlines. Finally, the view is prima facie self-undermining, at least when
215
Actually, it involves several non sequiturs, but I focus on one.
309 applied to epistemic norms. If causal determination precludes normative
evaluation, then the natural sciences themselves are merely successful
memes, with no legitimate claim to truth.216
(2) Indeterminism.217 In fact, contemporary natural sciences,
unlike the Newtonian science of Kant’s day, do not think that everything
in the universe is deterministically-caused; quantum mechanics
postulates indeterminism in nature, and the complexity of the human
brain can give rise to contexts within which quantum indeterminism can
make a significant differences for human thought, choice, and behavior.
Robert Kane has suggested that “physical modeling in the brain” that
incorporates “neural network theory, nonlinear thermodynamics, chaos
theory, and quantum physics” can “put . . . the free will issue into
greater dialogue with developments in the sciences” and, in the end,
provide for a scientifically-plausible view of free will that justifies “the
power of agents to be the creators . . . of their own ends and purposes”
(Kane 1996: 17, 4). Indeterminism in this sense fits with a strong
scientific realism, in that the sciences can exhaust all that there is to
know about human beings. Because the sciences themselves are
indeterminist, however, some human behavior may be as well, and this
leaves room for freedom in human life.
Unfortunately, this view confuses indeterminism with freedom.
Unless I have reason to identify with quantum fluctuations in my brain
rather than deterministic processes shaped by my genetic and
environmental background, the “ends and purposes” arising from those
quantum fluctuations will be no more my own that those arising from
deterministic influences. Because self-image is largely shaped by features
that are stable or at least consistent with our past personality, changes
that arise from quantum fluctuation may even seem less my own that
those that are strictly determined. Moreover, since the physical models
by virtue of which human beings are free posit chaotically complex
systems that are only sometimes affected in significant ways by quantum
fluctuations, there is no way to know, for any particular end or purpose,
whether that end or purpose is really free, which undermines much of
216
One might, of course, be an immoralist fatalist – denying moral responsibility – while still clinging to
epistemic norms in a compatibilist way and thus assuming the legitimacy of norm-governed freedom fromwithin the standpoint of cognition while denying its legitimacy from-within the standpoint of volition.
217
There are two main views among philosophers who take this approach as to the role of indeterminism in
free action. One view, which is known as “simple indeterminism,” holds that an action is only free if it is
not caused, or not deterministically caused, by prior events. The second view, which is known as “causal
indeterminism,” holds that free action must be indeterministically caused by the right kinds of events. For a
defense of the first view, see Ginet 1990 and 1997. For a defense of causal indeterminism, see Kane 1996
and 2002.
310 the practical value of positing freedom. (It will not be the case, for
example, that all cases where one would naturally ascribe moral
responsibility will be cases within which the relevant quantum fluctation
was present.)
(3) Compatibilism. Compatibilists, like indeterminists, seek to find
freedom within scientific accounts of human beings. But compatibilists
do not aim to find room for freedom in the indeterminism of the natural
world. Instead, compatibilists aim to show that mysterious and
metaphysical “transcendental” freedom is not the sort of freedom that
human beings need. What is needed for making sense of moral
responsibility, normativity more generally, and even just our sense of
ourselves as free is something much more mundane, a sort of ability to
impact what happens in our lives and our world. If this ability is itself
grounded in genes or brain-states or psychological structures, that is not
particularly important. What matters is that it is an ability that we can
identify with and that we can see as genuinely efficacious in the world.
Some sorts of determinism might make it hard or impossible to identify
with aspects of our psychological make-up. If we recognize that our
inability to focus on our work is genetically programmed or that our fear
of spiders is a childhood phobia, we might not think of those aspects of
our psychology as really “us.” But the mere fact that some aspect of our
psychology is determined need not preclude us from identifying with it.
Compatibilism might provide an adequate conception of freedom,
and recent philosophical work on freedom has provided substantial
resources for conceptions of freedom that could fit within a wholly
naturalistic approach to human beings. In his own transcendental
analyses, especially of moral responsibility, Kant argued that morality
requires a transcendental freedom that stands above any determination
by natural causes.218 Recent years have seen many attempts to make
sense of moral responsibility without assuming transcendental freedom.
Such attempts, however, cannot be “naturalist” in the sense of merely
“clarify[ing] and unify[ing]” scientific theories (Dennett 2003:13). Rather
than starting with science, figuring out what sort of freedom it allows for,
and then arguing that this freedom is sufficient, a compatibilism that
would do justice to our from-within sense of moral responsibility must
start from-within, look carefully at the presuppositions of our conception
218
See chapter one, pp. xxx-xxx.
311 of moral responsibility, and then see whether this is compatible with
science.219
(4) Perspectivism. The previous three approaches to freedom all fit
well with strong scientific realism.220 Throughout this chapter, however, I
have emphasized that Kant’s contribution to debates about the natural
sciences is his perspectivism. By recognizing that science represents one
perspective on the world, Kant is able to make room for other
perspectives, including a practical perspective within which freedom
plays an important role. Many contemporary natural scientists have
adopted a similar view. Dawkins and Dennett point out that human
beings are capable of taking a stance towards the world that is not
reducible to their genes or memes. Steven Pinker has, more forcefully,
insisted that “science and ethics are two self-contained systems played
out among the same entities in the world” (Pinker 1997: 45).
Perspectivists can thus defend the integrity of an incompatibilist
conception of freedom as a concept that, as Pinker puts it, “makes the
ethics game playable” (Pinker 1997: 45). For perspectivists of this
stripe,221 compatibilism is wrong in trying to find a notion of freedom
that is compatible with our best scientific theories. Freedom is needed
within ethics; causation is needed within science.
Importantly, one can prioritize perspectives in different ways. Most
natural scientists and philosophers heavily influenced by natural science
are what we might call science-first perspectivists. Pinker is typical here:
Ethical theory requires idealizations like free, sentient, rational,
equivalent agents whose behavior is uncaused, and its conclusions
can be sound and useful even though the world, as seen by science,
does not really have uncaused events . . . [T]he world is close enough
to the idealization of free will that moral theory can meaningfully be
applied to it. (Pinker 1997: 55)222
219
For recent attempts to do this, see Frankfurt 1998 and Wallace 1994 and 2006. Even many
contemporary Kantians have backed off a strong commitment to transcendental freedom as a condition of
possibility of moral responsibility. See Korsgaard 1996.
220
In all of these cases, of course, one need not be a strong scientific realist. Theological compatibilists, for
instance, might argue that God is the ultimate cause of all things and causes them in accordance with
natural laws, but that human freedom exists nonetheless. For the sake of comparing Kant with
contemporary naturalism, though, I treat as strongly realist all of those views of freedom that are
compatible with strong scientific realism.
221
One could be a compatibilist perspectivist (as Dennett is) insofar as one takes the ethics game to require
a conception of freedom that the science game need not, but also takes the conception of freedom in the
ethics game to be entirely compatible with conceptions of the self that are evolutionarily explicable.
222
Dennett’s claim that “the creation of . . . new standpoints” is “the . . . product of . . . [a biological]
revolution” (Dennett 2003: 179) also fits here.
312 In thinking of the world as “close enough” to ethical assumptions, Pinker
implicitly assumes that the world “as seen by science” is the real world,
and ethics is all right because its assumptions are not too far off, good
enough for practical purposes. Pinker compares ethics to Euclidean
geometry in this respect. But this sort of perspectivism cannot be
adequate to make sense of the demands of normativity. If we are in fact
only approximately free, then either the “ethics game” (Pinker’s term)
requires only approximate freedom to be legitimate (as, for instance,
getting good results in structural engineering requires only that the
world be approximately Euclidean), or the ethics game, while playable, is
a sham. Perhaps Pinker is willing to affirm some sort of idealized
uncaused freedom merely in the absence of the well-worked-out
compatibilist account that would show that the freedom we really need is
actually compatible with science. But if morality really depends upon
seeing ourselves as uncaused, it is just not clear how a determinist world
can be “close enough” to save it.223
Instead of a science-first perspectivism, then, one might adopt a
neutral perspectivism, as has become increasingly common amongst
contemporary Kantians. Christine Korsgaard, for example, argues that
the fact that “freedom . . . is not a theoretical property which can . . . be
seen by scientists” will be taken to imply “that . . . freedom is not ‘real’
only if you have defined ‘real’ as what can be identified by scientists
looking at things . . . from outside” (Korsgaard 1996b:96). But there is no
reason to do this, since “we need” a from-within practical perspective –
and thus freedom – just as much as we need scientific theories. This
approach is considerably more promising because it preserves all of the
insights of science without according science an unjustifiably priveleged
place in our self-understanding. And it thereby avoids the most serious
problems of science-first perspectivism.
But Kant (and some contemporary Kantians) offer good reasons to
reject even neutral perspectivism in favor of freedom-first perspectivism.
On this view, the scientific view of the world is subordinate to the view of
the world according to which human beings are free. The predominant
argument for the priority of this free perspective on human beings within
223
Here it’s important to remember that morality is meant to be saved in the sense of justified. Of course
the world can be set up to save morality in a psychological sense, that is, as a game that human beings can
and will play. But this does not show that morality is a legitimate game, one that we should play. Moreover,
if freedom is necessary not merely for ethics but for normativity in general, then it seems at least odd to see
the conditions of possibility of science itself (freedom) being subordinated to the best theories within that
science. Especially if these theories posit that we are unfree, they might be able to show that the practice of
theory-construction in science is something that we will in fact do, but it would undermine the basis for
thinking that our scientific theories are really justified.
313 contemporary philosophy is simply that any perspective that claims any
sort of justification – even the scientific perspective itself – implicitly
appeals at least to the freedom to believe on the basis of normative
standards of good evidence. In holding each other and ourselves
responsible for our beliefs, whether scientific or otherwise, we treat those
beliefs as “up to us” rather than mere effects of empirical causes. But
there is no corresponding dependence of normative perspectives upon
scientific ones. Once one treats human beings as natural objects, one
must explain the capacity for norm-governed thought and action in
terms of science, but one can think of oneself and others as normgoverned without committing oneself to a scientific picture of the world.
Kant offers a further reason for freedom-first perspectivism,224
based on a fundamental difference between the “ethics game” and what
we might call the “science game.” Humans treat each other as morally
responsible, which depends upon seeing each other as free; and we study
each other empirically, which depends upon seeing each other as
determined by natural causes. So far, the games are parallel; each
depends upon a certain assumption as its condition of possibility. But
the parallel nature of these assumptions conceals a deeper difference
between them. For the ethics game, as we saw above, it is not enough
that we seem free, or that we are close enough to being free. In that case,
we might still engage in the ethics game, but the game itself would be a
sham. For the science game, however, it is not necessary that we really
be wholly determined by natural causes. It is enough that human
behavior, whatever its ultimate basis, is sufficiently regular to be
explained in terms of natural causes.225 Since the science-game does not
depend upon a science-first perspective and the ethics game does depend
upon a freedom-first perspective, we can and should adopt the freedomfirst perspective.
224
He offers at least one other “reason” that I do not discuss. Aesthetic experience, of the sublime, allows
us to feel the priority of our freedom.
225
Moreover, as Kant argues in his Critique of Pure Reason, the demand for ultimate scientific
explanations is impossible. As one contemporary commentator has put it:
all naturalistic explanations – even the most impressive explanations of some future neuroscience –
are conditional explanations . . . . In a certain sense they are incomplete, for they can never explain
that any natural law should take the form that it does. (O’Neill 1989: 68)
Science at most explains regularities in nature in terms of increasingly general laws, but these explanations
are always incomplete in a way that leaves room for the sort of incompatibilist compatibilism Kant defends
in his transcendental philosophy. Practically speaking, since the evidence that some empirical cause will
bring about an action of ours can never ultimately be based in a causal law that is self-evidently necessary,
it always remains open to us to make an exception of ourselves.
314 V. Conclusion.
In the end, where does modern science leave us with respect to
Kant’s question? We now have a much more sophisticated empirical
understanding of human beings, from our complex psychology to the
brain-chemistry that makes this psychology possible to the evolutionary
origins and genetic bases of our wonderful brains. Kantians can and
should embrace the results of the natural sciences into empirical
anthropology. And that means, of course, that Kantians can and should
embrace the methodological naturalism that makes these sciences
possible; humans should be treated as ordinary objects in the natural
world and studied according to the best methods of natural science. Kant
even provides grounds for embracing a modest scientific realism, in
which one takes the methodological assumptions of natural science to be
empirically real, that is, to be constitutive of the world we experience.
As we have frequently noted, however, the question “What is the
human being?” is not merely a question about the distinctive features of
a certain type of natural entity. Answering the question requires thinking
not only about how to pick out homo sapiens from amongst other natural
objects, but about how to make sense of ourselves, from-within. And this
question from-within is not merely philosophical but also practical, a
matter of asking what to do with our lives, what to think, and what to
find pleasure in. For those questions, naturalism is insufficient. But
Kant’s philosophical framework not only includes an empirical realism
according to which science is true of the empirical world, but also a
transcendental idealism that insists that science is only one perspective,
that there is more to the world-in-itself than what is captured in the
empirically-knowable world. In Pinker’s terms, Kant allows for both the
science-game and the ethics-game, or, more generally, the normativitygame. Kant’s justification of the science-game allows for a realism
sufficiently robust to allow us to pursue and benefit from science, but it
mitigates that realism just enough to make room for freedom. Moreover,
precisely because Kant engages in both the science-game of empirically
studying human beings and the normativity games of epistemology,
ethics, and aesthetics, he provides a better model for answering the
question “what is the human being?” than modern naturalism. Kant
justifies the fundamental normative standards of epistemology, ethics,
and aesthetics independent of the natural sciences; but he is still able to
use the results of those natural sciences in the context of a pragmatic
315 anthropology that thinks about how we, as empirically-knowable human
beings, can best promote ways of thinking, acting, and feeling that
conform to our ideals.
Of course, the fact that science must be complemented by a
perspective from-within does not show that Kant best analyzed that
perspective. Just as modern science accepts the importance of
empirically studying human beings while moving beyond Kant’s specific
empirical theories, one might accept that normativity is not reducible to
empirical science and still reject Kant’s specific normative theories. And
in fact, philosophy in the past two centuries has developed new ways of
thinking about human beings from-within that directly challenge Kant’s
transcendental anthropology. In chapter ten, we look at one of the
twentieth century’s defining “from-within” approaches to human beings:
existentialism. And in chapter eleven, we survey some dominant
contemporary philosophical approaches to normativity. Before turning to
those, however, we turn to a further sort of empirical anthropology. Like
contemporary biology and psychology, Kant typically focused on those
aspects of human beings that were, at least in a loose sense, universal.
But Kant also recognized that human beings are historical in ways that
no other animals are, and he recognized that the human species includes
within it sub-groups with their own distinctive characteristics. The next
chapter turns to contemporary developments that emphasize historical
and cultural differences between human beings. Kant saw these
differences as primarily a small sub-field within empirical anthropology,
but recent thinkers have extended historicism and diversity into
transcendental anthropology. This sort of historicism goes far beyond
Kant’s own and raises a substantial challenge to his anthropology as a
whole.
316 Chapter 9: Historicism and Human Diversity
Perhaps the time is at hand when it will be comprehended again and
again how --little used to be sufficient to furnish the cornerstone for
such sublime and unconditional philosophers’ edifices as the
dogmatists have built so far: any old popular superstition from time
immemorial (like the soul superstition, which, in the form of the
subject and ego superstition, has not even yet ceased to do mischief);
some play on words, perhaps, a seduction by grammar, or an
audacious generalization of some very narrow, very personal, very
human, all too human, facts.
—Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil (Preface)
It seemed to me that, for the moment, the essential task was to free
the history of thought from . . . transcendental narcissism.
—Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge (Foucault
1982: 203)
Kant’s lifetime saw a rise in consciousness of human beings as
historical beings. Throughout the Enlightenment, philosophers and
scientists had in one sense seen themselves in historical terms; the
Enlightenment was a period of rejecting the contingent, tradition-bound
ideologies of the Middle Ages. But the alternative to these traditions was
not taken to be just another tradition. Instead, Enlightenment
philosophers saw themselves as replacing merely historical traditions
with ahistorical truths grounded in reason and direct experience of the
world. In one sense, Kant too is an Enlightenment thinker. His
transcendental anthropology aims to lay out the a priori – and hence
necessary and universal – structures of human thought and action,
stripped free of anything merely empirical (including anything merely
historical). At the same time, as we saw in chapter three, Kant was
attuned to fact that human beings are historical; he even emphasized the
historicity of Enlightenment itself.226 Kant’s students (Herder) and
followers (Reinhold) further emphasized this point. By the time of Hegel
and Marx, the idea that humans’ fundamental ways of thinking about
and acting within the world differ from culture to culture and change
226
See Foucault’s discussion of Kant’s “What is Enlightenment?” (8:33-42) in Foucault 1984: 32-50.
317 from one historical epoch to another had become commonplace. Today,
this emphasis on human variety pervades not only history but also
sociology, anthropology, cultural studies, and even parts of psychology
and literary theory.
But human “historicity” is ambiguous. In its most mundane sense,
the claim that human beings are historical is one that (virtually) no one
would deny. Humans age. We change as we age. We live in communities
that develop cultural practices. These practices get passed on and
modified; they vary from time to time and culture to culture. But
historicism is generally not limited to this mundane historicity. In
chapters six and seven, we saw that two importantly different sorts of
historicism emerged in the nineteenth century. One, represented by
philosophers such as Hegel and Marx, emphasized the necessity of
historical change. For Hegel, historical changes chart rational progress.
For Marx, material changes in humans’ labor and power relations give
rise to both ideological shifts and the need for further historical shifts.
Other philosophers, such as Herder, Hamaan, and Nietzsche, use
historicity and diversity to emphasize the contingency of particular
modes of thought and forms of life. For both sets of historicists, humans’
historical nature is not limited to external studies of changing individuals
and cultures. Over history and across cultures, human beings differ in
the ways they see the world. In Kantian terms, transcendental
anthropology is historicized and localized. No one can elucidate
conditions of possibility of human cognition or volition; instead, as
Nietzsche put it, those who “wanted to provide a rational foundation for
morality” are exposed as having only justified “the morality of their
environment, their class, their church, the spirit of their time, their
climate and part of the world” (Nietzsche 1966:§186). In the rest of this
chapter, I use the term “historicism” to refer to this stronger sort of
historicism, what we might call a “transcendental historicism” since it
claims that humans’ from-within, normative perspectives are historically
conditioned.227
This historicism has become a mainstay of our world. In its most
facile form, it manifests itself in a lame relativism that only refers to what
is true-for-me or good-to-me. Such relativists generally think that the
mere diversity of human ways of thinking establishes that no particular
227
While Hegel, Marx, and Nietzsche all fall into this strong sense of historicism because all three
emphasize the historicity of what Kant considered transcendental anthropology, the figures on which I
focus in this chapter (Kuhn, Foucault, and contemporary anthropologists) are more specifically
Nietzschean, in that all emphasize (to varying degrees) the contingency of historically varying perspectives
on the world. (In chapter 11, we will look at a more Hegelian approach to history in the work of Alasdair
MacIntyre.)
318 perspective on the world can be right. And such relativism is often
confused with tolerance, as though the most respectful stance to take
towards different times and cultures is to recognize that their beliefs and
values were true for them, just as one’s own beliefs and values are true
for oneself. At the end of this chapter, I will come back to this simplistic
but all-too-common appropriation of historicism, but for the bulk of this
chapter, I focus on three significant and more nuanced recent versions of
historicism.
I start with the rise of historicism in the study of the natural
sciences, focusing on Thomas Kuhn, through whom the concepts of a
“paradigm” and a “paradigm-shift” have become commonplace. Kuhn and
post-Kuhnian philosophy of science is important because it seems to
undermine not only strong scientific realism but even Kant’s own modest
realism about natural science. If natural sciences are historically
conditioned, it becomes hard to see how one can even talk about the
empirical world or take Kantian categories of experience to have the strict
universality Kant thinks they do. From Kuhn, I turn to Foucault. Like
Kuhn, Foucault questions basic aspects of Kant’s transcendental
framework, but Foucault focuses on the problematic and historically
contingent notion of “the human being” as such. In particular, while
Kuhn calls into question Kant’s transcendental anthropology of
cognition, Foucault historicizes both the general framework of Kantian
anthropology – what Foucault calls “man” as an “empiricotranscendental doublet” (Foucault 1970: 319) – and the conception of
human agency that underlies Kant’s moral theory. Finally, I turn to
anthropology228 and cultural studies, where human diversity – rather
than historicism as such – provides a perspective within which the
supposed universality of Kant’s anthropology (both empirical and
transcendental) is questioned.
I. Historicism and Contemporary Natural Science: from Kant to
Kuhn
The roots of historicism in the natural sciences lay in mid-19th
century developments within mathematics, Kant’s paradigmatic
candidate for a priori knowledge. Mathematicians such as Nikolai
Lobachevsky, Henri Poincare, and Bernhard Reimann began thinking of
basic geometrical axioms – such as that parallel lines never meet – not as
228
Since this book has generally used the term “anthropology” to refer to the study of human beings in
general, it is worth noting that in this chapter, I often use anthropology (as here) to refer to the narrow
discipline of contemporary anthropology.
319 intuitively obvious truths about space but as “conventions” or logical
axioms. Mathematicians began working through implications of changing
various Euclidean axioms, and a whole field of non-Euclidian geometry
was born. In these systems, familiar geometrical claims – such as that
the sum of the interior angles of a triangle is 180 degrees – no longer
hold true. In itself, this development in mathematics was important since
it suggested that the human mind was capable of thinking about worlds
with structures very different from our own. But Euclid’s axioms were
still generally taken to define the true nature of space. Mathematicians
might have fun thinking about a world where parallel lines touch and
where someone drawing a straight line would end up drawing a line that,
while always straight, nonetheless kept criss-crossing itself. But these
mathematical fantasies were just that: fantasies.
Then Einstein argued that the world itself was non-Euclidean.
Straight lines can cross themselves, parallel lines touch, and the interior
angles of a triangle are not 180 degrees. At the same time, other radical
changes were happening in the physical sciences. Quantum mechanics
challenged basic notions such as the continuity of time, the determinacy
of space, and the principle of causation. Within quantum mechanics,
time no longer passes in a continual stream but in little jumps, or
quanta. Objects are no longer located in particular spaces but are
smeared out in waves of probability. And events in the world are not
universally explicable in terms of causes and effects. Some things
happen, literally, by chance. Not only was Euclid’s space replaced by
Einstein’s, but Newton’s deterministic world was replaced rolls of the
dice.
As philosophers increasingly sought to come to terms with these
and similar developments in science, the Kantian model of science as
built on a set of a priori synthetic claims about the nature of any possible
experience seemed increasingly difficult to maintain. In a now classic
paper (Quine 1951), W.V.O. Quine argued against the distinction
between synthetic and analytic claims and the possibility of any
knowledge that could not be changed in the light of experience. If
Euclidean geometry could be abandoned for the sake of relativity theory
and universal determinism abandoned for the sake of quantum
mechanics, then “no statement is immune to revision”; any claim is open
to empirical challenge, including “even . . . logical law[s]” such as the law
of the excluded middle or the principle of non-contradiction (Quine
1951:40). In the end, Quine claims, “The totality of our so-called
knowledge or beliefs, from the most casual matters of geography and
history to the profoundest laws of atomic physics or even of pure
mathematics and logic, is a man-made fabric which impinges on
320 experience only along the edges,” such that while experience can lead to
revisions in our web of belief, “No particular experiences are linked with
any particular statements in the interior of the field, except indirectly
through considerations of equilibrium affecting the field as a whole”
(Quine 1951:40).
Quine’s account of knowledge set the stage for Thomas Kuhn’s
historical turn in the philosophy of science. Kuhn’s Structure of
Scientific Revolutions rejected what had become dominant models of
historical progress in science and set the agenda for much history and
philosophy of science today. Most science textbooks present a history of
science within which old illusions give rise to more and more accurate
scientific theories. The scientific method is described as a method
whereby one measures theories or hypotheses against empirical
evidence, rejecting theories that fail to be confirmed by evidence. Over
time, theories become better and better confirmed and thereby more and
more reliable. Scientific revolutions occur when empirical evidence
contradicts long-standing theories and these are replaced by more
adequate theories. Thus the transition from Newtonian physics to the
physics of Einstein and quantum mechanics is explained by empirical
evidence (such as the perihelion of Mercury and the bending of light
around the sun evident in the famous eclipse of 1919) that contradicted
Newton’s theory. Against this conception of science and its history, Kuhn
argues both that the “scientific method” does not consist in the attempt
to falsify hypotheses and the rejection of those that fail to measure up to
empirical data and that “scientific revolutions” are not unambiguous
forms of progress.
Kuhn’s account of science involves a fundamental distinction
between what he calls “normal science,” “extraordinary science,” and
“scientific revolutions.” Normal science is what virtually all practicing
scientists engage in virtually all of the time. It consists in “puzzlesolving.” This science takes place in the context of a “paradigm,” a
“constellation of beliefs, values, techniques, and so on shared by the
members of a given [scientific] community” (Kuhn 1996: 174) that
supplies “a criterion for choosing problems that . . . can be assumed to
have solutions” (Kuhn 1996: 37). The paradigm resists falsification by
empirical data. Scientists often are unable even to see data that
contradicts the paradigm – the paradigm structures “the perceptual
process itself” (Kuhn 1996: 62).229 Even if scientists perceive data that
229
Kuhn points to experiments within which subjects were shown playing cards, some of which were
abnormal, such as “a red six of spades.” When shown these cards and asked to identify them, “the
anomalous cards were almost always identified, without apparent hesitation or puzzlement, as normal”
321 does not fit their paradigm, they initially interpret such data as due to
personal failures to properly carry out their experiments. If such data are
reproduced consistently, scientists will work to explain them in ways that
preserve the paradigm itself. Finally, if they are unable to explain the
empirical data, scientists will generally move on to other areas of
research rather than reject the theories that the data contradict. As
Kuhn put it, “Paradigms are not corrigible by normal science at all”
(Kuhn 1996: 122).
Sometimes, however, empirical findings that conflict with scientific
paradigms – “anomalies” – are sufficiently disturbing to provoke
“extraordinary science,” examining the anomaly in greater detail and
seeking to explain it within the broad contours of one’s paradigm.
Generally, anomalies are resolved within the dominant paradigm with
only minor tweaks. Sometimes, however, an anomaly is sufficiently
problematic, or an alternative paradigm sufficiently attractive, to prompt
a crisis and eventually even a “scientific revolution.” This transition from
an old paradigm to a new one “is far from a cumulative process” (Kuhn
1996: 86), more like a “gestalt switch” than a refinement of the old
paradigm. One comes to see science in a new light; theories and even
data of the old paradigm are often not even translatable into the new one.
Kuhn point out, for example, that whereas many people today think of
Einstein’s physics as a refinement of Newton’s, within which Newtonian
physics is merely an approximation, in fact “Einstein’s theory can be
accepted only with the recognition that Newton’s was wrong” (Kuhn
1996: 100) and even the most basic “variables and parameters” in each’s
theory – the variables referring to “time, mass, etc.” – have different
meanings, different physical referents, in the two theories. The
“fundamental structural elements of which the universe . . . is composed”
are different in the two systems; the apparent similarity of Einstein’s
laws of motion at slow speeds to Newton’s laws is merely superficial
(Kuhn 1996: 101-2). Similarly, in any true scientific revolution, the whole
“conceptual network through which scientists view the world” changes
(Kuhn 1996: 102). Put another way, one at once deeply Kantian and
deeply historicist, “after a revolution, scientists are responding to a
different world,” or, even more radically, “when paradigms change, the
world itself changes with them” (Kuhn 1996: 111).230
(Kuhn 1996: 63, see Bruner and Postman 1949 for the original study). People literally saw cards that
matched their categories. Similarly, scientists literally see data in terms of the paradigm within which they
work.
230
This historicism about the world permeates Kuhn’s work, though there are some glimmers of a more
transhistorical conception of reality, as when he suggests that before a revolution is possible, “Nature itself
322 Scientific revolutions do not simply replace a falsified theory with
one that fits all the empirical evidence. Often, in fact, new paradigms fit
available evidence worse than old ones. Because previous evidence was
collected in order to confirm the old paradigm, the new paradigm often
has a very difficult time making sense of it. Kuhn points out that
Copernicus’s astronomy did not predict the motions of the planets any
better than the Ptolemaic astronomy that it replaced, Lavoisier’s
chemical revolution that paved the way for modern chemistry
“deprive[ed] chemistry of some actual and much potential explanatory
power” (Kuhn 1996: 107, cf. 131), and “in this century the striking
quantitative success of both Plank’s radiation law and the Bohr atom
quickly persuaded many physicists to adopt them even though, viewing
physical science as a whole, these contributions created many more
problems than they solved” (Kuhn 1996: 154). What new paradigms
bring is not primarily a better way of dealing with old evidence but a
whole new way of looking at the world, new criteria for success in
science, new assumptions about what sorts of empirical problems are
worth investigating, new ways of interpreting empirical data, new
experimental techniques, and even new criteria for deciding amongst
competing theories. Whereas “progress” makes sense “during periods of
normal science” where a paradigm provides accepted standards of
progress, it does not make sense as a way of measuring the shift from
one paradigm to another. Thus, Kuhn claims, “a decision [between
competing paradigms] can only be made on faith,” or, more precisely,
“There must be a basis, though it need be neither rational nor ultimately
correct, for faith in the particular [paradigm] chosen” (Kuhn 1996: 158).
But then “[w]e may . . . have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit,
that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them
close and closer to the truth” (Kuhn 1996: 170).231
Kuhn developed his notion of paradigm shifts primarily within the
philosophy of natural sciences, and his overall theory has led to a wide
growth in investigations of the historical and social conditions that shape
scientific practice and theories. Thus sociologists of science have offered
detailed studies of the social, cultural, and even psychological factors
that shape developments of scientific theory and practice. Feminist
philosophers of science have shown ways in which the male-dominance
of scientific work has skewed the way that data is perceived, collected,
and interpreted (e.g. Longino 1990). At their most extreme, historicist
must first undermine professional security by making prior achievements seem problematic” (Kuhn 1996:
169).
231
See, however, Kuhn 1977, where he seeks to recover a sense of objectivity and even “progress” in
science.
323 studies defend the social construction of “scientific facts” or “quarks” (see
Latour and Woolgar 1986 and Pickering 1984). Kuhn’s concept of a
“paradigm shift” has also filtered into our culture more generally,
resulting in a historicist conception of knowledge according to which
human experiences, beliefs, and practices are shaped by paradigms that
structure not only how we interpret our world but literally what we
perceive. Our world is constituted by our paradigms, and paradigms
shift. They can differ between different groups of people and can change
– often quite abruptly – over time. What the world looks like from-within,
including the most basic norms for how one evaluates one’s beliefs, is
historically-conditioned.
This Kuhnian historicist account of human knowledge is, in some
respects, strikingly Kantian. Like Kant, Kuhn suggests that human
experience is structured by forms of cognition that precede that
experience. With his claim that different scientists inhabit different
worlds, Kuhn even endorses something like Kant’s Copernican turn (see
Kuhn 1966: 110). With Kant, moreover, Kuhn gives reasons to reject a
strong scientific realism by showing how science results from
presuppositions human beings bring to analysis of the world. Scientific
theories, whether about atoms or about human nature, are always
constructed in the context of prior commitments of those who construct
them. While this need not wholly undermine the “rationality” of science
nor even some sort of scientific “objectivity” (see Kuhn 1977), it calls into
question the strong scientific realism implicit in philosophical
naturalism. Kuhn goes further in this respect than Kant, claiming that
“the notion of a match between the ontology of a theory and its ‘real’
counterpart in nature . . . seems . . . illusive in principle” (Kuhn 1966:
206, cf. too McMullin 1995).
But while he supports something like Kant’s Copernican turn and
even something like the rejection of strong scientific realism implied by
Kant’s transcendental idealism, Kuhn’s picture is radically different from
Kant’s in one important respect.232 Kant’s transcendental anthropology of
232
In my discussion of Kuhn’s importance for Kant, I ignore the fact, obvious in Kuhnian hindsight, that
Kant’s own empirical psychology reflects contingent paradigms of thought. This point would not be
particularly problematic for Kant. Though proud of his tri-partite conception of the human mind, Kant
recognized that his empirical anthropology was revisable. And even if not particularly attuned to how
certain notions (such as that of a “faculty”) were historically contingent, Kant was well aware that central
aspects of psychology in his day – including the use of physiognomy, which Kant largely rejected, and the
role of natural predispositions, which Kant defended – involved presuppositions that might to be
overturned.
324 cognition seeks universal conditions of possibility of any human
experience. Kuhn’s paradigms structure experience for particular groups
of human beings at particular times in particular contexts. Kuhn
historicizes and relativizes Kant’s Copernican turn. Paradigms that are “a
priori” in the sense that they structure one’s experience of the world are
not necessarily “a priori” in the stronger sense of being unrevisable in the
light of further empirical research (or even, as has been emphasized by
post-Kuhnian sociology of science, of changing social conditions). What
scientific theorizing looks like from-within is determined in part by
historically contingent facts. This raises the prospect that the
transcendental forms of cognition that Kant argues to be conditions of
possibility of any human experience might merely be historically local
paradigms. For Kant, the idea of data that could contradict
transcendental forms of intuition or categories of experience was literally
not humanly thinkable. For Kuhn, such data is not only thinkable but
actual. The history of science shows that even the most apparently
necessary claims can be abandoned in the context of a scientific
revolution that radically restructures our whole approach to our world.
As a vague and general point, the assertion of historical
contingency human cognition need not be fatal to Kant’s transcendental
anthropology. Kant’s account of empirical concepts leaves room for the
development of concepts that shape one’s experience of the world, even
when these concepts are themselves ultimately rooted not in the
necessary structure of human cognition as such but in the contingent
ways in which human beings have responded to particular sets of
experiences. Kant’s accounts of prejudice further suggest a framework
for thinking about cognitive structures that are contingent but
nonetheless “a priori” in the sense that they shape the way we experience
the world. Kant’s theory of biology comes even closer to a sort of Kuhnian
approach to paradigms; in the case of natural organisms, experience of
the world gives rise to an a priori principle for further investigation of
that world. And Kant’s philosophy of history provides some basis for
thinking that human perspectives on the world can change. Thus Kant
could allow that, in addition to a priori and universal structures of human
cognition, there are also historically contingent mental structures that
shape our experience of the world.
Unfortunately, historicist philosophy of science does not let Kant
get off that easily. First, the details of Kuhn’s history of science suggest
that the particular structures Kant assumed to be a priori are not. For
Kant, space, time, causation, and a continuum of degrees of sensible
properties are among the most fundamental a priori conditions of the
possibility of any human experience. By virtue of the aprioricity of space,
325 we can know that (Euclidean) geometry applies to the empirical world. By
virtue of the principle of causation, we can know a priori that every
alteration has a cause that determined it to occur. But relativity theory
seems to require rejecting Euclidean space, and Einstein’s notion of
“space-time” is inconsistent with Kant’s careful distinction between space
and time. Meanwhile, dominant interpretations of quantum mechanics
imply that deterministic causation is not universal, that alterations occur
probabilistically, the result, at least in part, of random chance. Thus the
specific positive metaphysical claims of Kant’s transcendental
anthropology of cognition seem to be rejected by the best science of our
day.
But the problem is even deeper. Precisely because Kant’s
transcendental anthropology of cognition did such a good job picking out
the best candidates for the most basic presuppositions of human
experience, if even these presuppositions are historically conditioned,
there seems little hope for any truly universal structure of human
cognition. All categories by means of which we make sense of the world
seem open to revision. The fact that some philosophers suggest rejecting
the principle of identity (a=a) and even the principle of non-contradiction
in order to better make sense of contemporary physics drives this point
home even more forcefully. Not only the details of Kant’s transcendental
anthropology but even the very idea that there could be a universallyhuman transcendental structure of cognition seem vulnerable to
historicist critique.
II. Historicism and the Human Sciences: Foucault
While the history of natural science contributes important
historicist dimensions to understanding human cognition, an even more
radical historicism has emerged in those sciences devoted to studying
human beings as such. The hero of this brand of historicism is Michel
Foucault, whose detailed historical analyses of key concepts and
practices employed in human self-understanding threaten the
universality of not only Kantian cognitive categories but his whole
transcendental anthropology. By historically analyzing ways of thinking,
Foucault challenges Kant’s universalism, and the central target of
Foucault’s work – insofar as one can pick out a central target – is the
historically-conditioned nature of human subjectivity itself. Foucault
aims to show the historical emergence and thereby contingency of
precisely the conception of the human being that lies at the heart of
Kant’s anthropology.
326 In developing his historicist approach, Foucault avoids blanket
theoretical claims about human historicity. Claiming that “human
thinking is always historically-bound,” like trite relativist claims that “all
truths are relative,” is a self-undermining proposition, a purportedly
absolute truth that all truths are merely relative. But Foucault neither
assumes an omniscient posture nor makes such overarching
pronouncements. Instead, while recognizing and even embracing the
historical-situatedness of his own work, Foucault “analyzes specific
rationalities” (Foucault 1982: 210), studying particular developments in
structures of human knowledge and society. Thus Foucault’s first major
work, A History of Madness (1961), traces the origin of our concept of
“mental illness,” showing how “mental disease, with the meanings we
now give it, is made possible” (Foucault 1988:270, Foucault
1961/2006:504) And Foucault’s History of Sexuality shows, among other
things, how sexual categories and even the basic structure of ethical life
shifts from ancient Greece to Christian Europe to the present. By
emphasizing detailed studies of particular cases – the “gray, meticulous,
and patiently documentary . . . accumulation of source material”
(Foucault 1984:76) – Foucault eschews appeals to timeless truths
without making absolute claims about the impossibility of such truths.
Foucault’s detailed studies model historicist thinking while avoiding the
self-contradictions of dogmatic theoretical relativism. Thus Foucault’s
threat to Kant is not the threat of a theory that undermines Kant’s
anthropology, but a historicist way of thinking that provides an
alternative to Kant’s anthropology and shows that anthropology to be
historically-local and historically-determined rather than universal.
For Foucault, the “accumulation of source material” is neither a
way of tracing the factual flow of history nor a way of describing
historical “progress” towards the present. Instead, like Kuhn,233 Foucault
emphasizes the historicity of the basic structures of human thought and
action. Foucault describes his approach as “deliberately both historical
and critical, in that it is concerned . . . with determining the conditions of
possibility of” particular forms of experience (Foucault 1994: xix).
Foucault’s historical method includes two key components: “archeaology”
and “genealogy.” The former lays out the “episteme” of a particular
historical epoch, the “epistemological field” that defines the “conditions of
possibility” of knowledge at a particular time. Foucault refers to this as a
“historical a priori” that is “not a condition of validity . . ., but a condition
for the reality of statements” (Foucault 1969/1982: 127). Whereas Kant’s
a priori categories of experience are purportedly universal, formal
233
The similarity to Kuhn is not wholly coincidental. Foucault’s early mentors included Bachelard and
Canguilhem, whose histories of natural science anticipated Kuhn’s. See Gutting 1989 and 2001.
327 structures of any possible human cognition, Foucault’s historical a priori
is a historically contingent set of conditions that structure neither what
could be thought nor what is actually justified but only what actually is
thought at any given time. To this archaeological excavation of historical
epistemological fields, Foucault adds a genealogical component that
traces how different fields arise and change, appropriate and dominate
one another. It is “the history of morals, ideals, and metaphysical
concepts” (Foucault 1984: 86).234 Consistent with both Kuhnian
historiography and Nietzschean genealogy, Foucault’s histories
emphasize contingency and complexity in historical changes and reject
any sense of “progress” towards some supra-historical ideal (such as
Kant’s suggestion that human history is teleologically ordered towards
increasing civilization, cultivation, and moralization (7:342)).
Foucault (like Nietzsche but unlike Kuhn) explains the emergence,
modification, and reinterpretation of various epistemic fields in terms of
power or domination. While Kuhnian paradigms are relatively benign
structures of thought, and Kantian categories are necessary conditions
that function to empower humans to know the world, Foucaultian
epistemes are moves in a “hazardous play of dominations” (Foucault
1984: 83, cf. Foucault 1977: 27). The simplistic way of understanding
Foucault, as merely pointing out that people often advance agendas by
trying to get others to think like them, fails to get Foucault’s more
complex point. For one thing, precisely because it is so ubiquitous,
Foucault does not see power as intrinsically problematic (See Foucault
1982:220). Foucault’s approach to power does not center on its use by
some human agents to dominate and control other human agents. For
Foucault, power involves systems of knowledge and action that constrain
and enable further knowing and acting (Foucault 1977: 27-8, see too
Foucault 1984:150). Whereas Kuhn emphasizes the role that individual
scientists play in the emergence of new scientific paradigms, Foucault
focuses on larger social and institutional forces that are both “made up”
of human actions and also “determine the forms and possible domains”
of human thought and action. Thus, for example, “a certain way of
rendering men docile and useful . . . required the involvement of definite
relations of knowledge . . . [and thereby] . . . made the human sciences
historically possible” (Foucault 1977: 305). The power structures of
234
Foucault scholars often distinguish between a period within which archeology is Foucault’s primary
method of history (beginning with History of Madness and ending with The Order of the Things and The
Archeology of Knowledge) and a period within which genealogy dominates his approach (in Discipline and
Punish and The History of Sexuality). But although Foucault does not explicit articulate genealogy as
governing his approach until “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History” (1971) elements of both methods are evident
through his work. The shift between early and later works is primarily one of emphasis.
328 modern society shifted from an emphasis on establishing the absolute
power of the king over subjects to punishing free and equal citizens to
establishing “normality” in a population. The present “carceral society”
that seeks “docile and useful” human bodies depends upon knowledge of
human beings as subject-objects capable of (self-)control/responsibility
and allows for techniques of observation that make the construction of
this sort of knowledge possible. This does not mean that “human
sciences emerged from the prison” (Foucault 1977: 305); Foucault is not
claiming some sort of plot on the part of political leaders to set up
empirical human sciences in order to better control their subjects. His
point is not about some particular human agents dominating over
others, but about a power-knowledge system that requires both certain
forms of domination and certain forms of knowledge (cf. Foucault
1990:95, Foucault 1980: 203).
This de-centering of the subject as a locus of power and knowledge
arises from Foucault’s historicizing of the very notion of a human
“subject.” For Foucault, the subject itself is a recent historical
emergence, a part of our present episteme, and one the contingency of
which Foucault aims to reveal. Foucault’s work as a whole is a “history of
the different modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made
subjects” (Foucault 1982: 208) While revealing the contingency of this
conception of man as subject-object, Foucault refuses simply to adopt
the episteme he analyzes. Instead, his genealogical methodology effects a
new way of studying power and knowledge, one that does not depend
upon “man” as subject.
As a result, Foucault’s historical a priori is much more radical
than Kuhn’s. Kuhnian paradigms can be understood as historically
shifting a priori structures of cognition and one might even historicize
Kant’s transcendental anthropology to take them into account. But
Foucault calls into question the whole transcendental perspective, the
whole idea of the thinking subject as the locus of cognition/knowledge.
[Genealogy] needed to be something more than the simple
relativization of the . . . [transcendental] 235 subject. I don’t believe the
problem can be solved by historicizing the subject . . . , fabricating a
subject that evolves through the course of history. One has to
dispense with a constituent subject, to get rid of the subject itself,
that’s to say, to arrive at an analysis which can account for the
235
Foucault says “phenomenological” here since his targets are Husserl and Heidegger, but he says
virtually the same thing about Kantian transcendental subjects. See, e.g., Foucault 1969/1982: 128 for a
similar claim about the “formal a priori.”
329 constitution of the subject within a historical framework. And this is
what I would call genealogy, that is, a form of history which can
account for the constitution of knowledge, discourses, domains of
objects, etc., without having to make reference to a subject which is
either transcendental in relation to the field of events or runs in its
empty sameness throughout the course of history. (Foucault 1984:
58-9, see too 73)
Foucault’s historical a priori is not a subjective from-within perspective
that changes through different historical conditions. For Foucault,
neither knowledge nor the a priori are primarily “within” subjects.
Knowledge is part of a knowledge-power structure that constrains and
includes human actions; the “subject” (of knowledge) that is the focus of
Kant’s transcendental anthropology (of cognition) is, for Foucault, a
recent innovation of our present knowledge-power complex, an
innovation wrapped up with domination in the service of docile normalcy,
an innovation that – in theory but especially in historical practice –
Foucault seeks to resist and reinterpret. By describing how “we
constitute ourselves as subjects of knowledge” (Foucault 1983: 237),
Foucault de-privileges Kant’s “transcendental” perspective, reinterpreting
it as a contingent perspective created by historically local power relations
(cf. Foucault 1973: 310, 322).
While the human “subject” is one way of describing the notion of
“man” at the heart of Foucault’s project, this “subject” is not merely the
subject of Kant’s transcendental anthropology. Foucault has in mind the
whole “empirico-transcendental doublet” that seemingly characterizes
Kant’s anthropology as a whole. For Foucault, Kant inaugurated a shift
from the Classical conception of thinking as essentially representation
with a view of human cognition as something that orders the world in
terms of its own nature. But for Foucault, this shift leads to a problem,
since “man appears in his ambiguous position as an object of [empirical]
knowledge and as a subject which knows” which leads, at least in its 19th
and 20th century forms, to an “analytic of finitude,” where thinkers aim
to show how “man’s being will be able to provide a foundation in their
own positivity for all those forms that indicate to him that he is not
infinite” (Foucault 1973:312, 315). In the end, Foucault argues that this
analytic is irresolvable, that the 19th and 20th centuries represent a series
of failed attempts to analyze the human being as “a being such that
knowledge will be attained in him of what makes all knowledge possible”
(Foucault 1973:318, see too 322). The result an intellectual culture that
“produces, surreptitiously and in advance, the confusion of the empirical
and the transcendental . . . [a]nd so we find philosophy falling asleep
once more . . ., this time not in the sleep of Dogmatism but that of
330 Anthropology [where a]ll empirical knowledge, provided it concerns man,
can serve as a possible philosophical field in which the foundation of
knowledge, the definition of its limits, and, in the end, the truth of truth
must be discovered” (Foucault 1973:341). Foucault thus suggests a shift
away from “man” as object of anthropological investigation towards a
“Nietzschean . . . promise of the superman,” a refusal – “with a
philosophical laugh” – to give into the myth of “man” (Foucault
1973:342-3).236
While Kuhn’s historical analyses of sciences primarily call into
question Kant’s transcendental anthropology of cognition, Foucault’s
history of “man” challenges virtually every aspect of Kant’s anthropology.
Archeological and genealogical investigations of how empirical human
sciences are caught up in systems of domination and control reveal the
contingency and potential dangers of these sciences. These analyses
challenge naturalist attempts to use empirical study of human beings as
comprehensive answers to the question “What is the human being?”, but
they also call into question Kant’s own empirical (and pragmatic)
anthropology, which, like its more contemporary forms, depends upon
classification and observation in the service of normalization and control.
Moreover, Foucault’s genealogical treatments of sexuality – which quickly
evolve into a wholesale genealogy explaining how “we constitute
ourselves as moral agents” (Foucault 1983: 237) – aim to show that the
way we (and Kant) think of ethics is historically local. On Foucault’s
account, “[N]obody is obliged in classical ethics . . . But, if they want to
have a beautiful existence, . . . a good reputation, . . . to be able to rule
others, they have to do” certain things (Foucault 1983: 240). Kant’s
transcendental anthropology of volition starts from the “fact” that human
beings are morally obligated and reasons from that fact to the basic
structure of obligation (the categorical imperative) and the conditions of
possibility of responsibility (transcendental freedom). If moral
responsibility itself is merely an aspect of modern European knowledgepower, Kant’s moral philosophy merely answers the question “What
ought I – as an 18th century modern man – do?” and his “anthropology”
is really just a study of human beings living within a particular,
236
Strikingly, however, Foucault recognizes that this criticism of “anthropology” and the “empiricotranscendental doublet” does not apply to Kant himself. Not only is “surreptitious . . . confusion of the
empirical and the transcendental” enacted “even though Kant had demonstrated the division between them”
(Foucault 1973:341), but Foucault rightly notes that “The Kantian moment,” rather than being a part of the
Modern Age and susceptible to its problems, is rather “the link between the two [the Classical and the
Modern ages]” (Foucault 1973:343). Moreover, Foucault’s own project, as much as he might want to
escape the modern episteme of empirico-transcendental doublet, falls prey to precisely the confusion he
notes in other historicist thinkers, that of using empirical investigation of human beings – in Foucault’s
case, of historical epistemes – to make transcendental claims about human norms and possibilities.
331 contingent system of knowledge-power.237 The moral law is “universal”
only in the sense that it represents a particularly modern-European
ambition to subordinate all diversity and particularity (“savagery” and
“deviance”) into a single overarching system of normalcy and control. And
“autonomy” is really just a way in which the observational systems of the
modern world seek to impose power through creating human beings who
regulate themselves. For Foucault, “Kant introduces one more way in our
tradition whereby the self is not merely given but is constituted in
relationship to itself as subject” (Foucault 1983: 252)
In the end, even the very question “What is the human being?” is
suspect: “the notion of human nature seems to me mainly to have played
the role of …designating certain types of discourse….” (Foucault 1984:
4). “[M]an, as a primary reality with its own density, as the difficult object
and sovereign subject of all possible knowledge” is a recent innovation,
something that “has no place” even in the Classical era of Descartes,
much less in ancient or medieval forms of human life (Foucault 1973:
310). And even if the question could make sense, Kant’s answer to it is,
at best, the careful analysis of a particular episteme that arose during
the 18th century and still plays a substantial role in our self-conceptions,
the human being as “empirico-transcendental doublet.” Moreover, the
purpose of Foucault’s “genealogy of the subject” is not, as in Kant’s
“Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History,” to show the
emergence of a from-within perspective that is now, for all intents and
purposes, the necessary structure of human beings as such. Instead,
Foucault aims to disclose the contingency of human subjectivity as it
emerged in our culture in order to open up possibilities for revising who
we are:
Maybe the target now is not to discover what we are, but to refuse
what we are . . . We have to promote new forms of subjectivity
through refusal of [the] kind of individuality which has been imposed
on us for several centuries. (Foucault 1982: 216)
Rather than transcendental justification of the structure of subjectivity
through analysis of its conditions of possibility, Foucault offers a
genealogy of the emergence of our distinctive forms of subjectivity in
order to refuse those forms. Summing up his relationship with Kant,
Foucault explains,
237
One might even wonder whether Kant’s answer to “What is the human being?” can continue to be our
answer. If Kant’s conception of the subject is as far from the Greeks’ as Foucault suggests, it might
reasonably be seen as equally far from our own conceptions. Insofar as this is true (and it is certainly true to
some extent), Foucault deserves no small part of the credit/blame for our own transformed understandings
of subjectivity, freedom, and responsibility.
332 If the Kantian question was that of knowing what limits knowledge
has to renounce transgressing, it seems to me that the critical
question today has to be turned back into a positive one: in what is
given to us as universal, necessary, obligatory, what place is occupied
by whatever is singular, contingent, and the product of arbitrary
constraints? The point is, in brief, to transform the critique
conducted in the form of necessary limitation into a practical critique
that takes the form of a possible transgression.
This entails and obvious consequence: that criticism is no longer
going to be practiced in the search for formal structures with
universal value, but rather as a historical investigation into the
events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize
ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying. In that
sense, this criticism is not transcendental, and its goal is not that of
making a metaphysics possible: it is genealogical in its design and
archaeological in its method.
Archaeological – and not transcendental – in the sense that it will
not seek to identify the universal structures of all knowledge or of all
possible moral action, but will seek to treat the instances of discourse
that articulate what we think, say, and do as so many historical
events. And this critique will be genealogical in the sense that it will
not deduce from the form of what we are what it is impossible for us
to do and to know, but it will separate out, from the contingency that
has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being, doing, or
thinking what we are, do, or think. It is not seeking to make possible
a metaphysics that has finally become a science; it is seeking to give
new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work of
freedom. (Foucault 1984: 45-6)
III. Human Diversity Today
Historicism is one important form of a general contemporary trend
towards emphasizing human diversity. For historicists, there can be no
uniform answer to the question “What is the human being?” because
human beings change throughout time. But even at any given time,
humanity includes substantial diversity. The most important kinds of
diversity to receive attention over the past 200 years are differences
based on sex or gender, race or ethnicity, and culture. In chapter five, we
discussed Kant’s (over)attentiveness to such distinctions and looked at
some contemporary responses to Kant’s accounts of sex, gender, race,
333 and ethnicity. This section focuses on the important role that increased
awareness of cultural difference plays in conceptions of “the” human
being. Recognizing and appreciating the distinctness of various different
human groups is not a wholly new phenomenon. Kant was writing after
over 200 years of European exploration of the globe, and he was a
voracious reader of the travel literature of his day. Montaigne, one of
Kant’s literary heroes, wrote essays defending the practices of
“cannibals” in the Americas, exposing the culture-boundedness of
European prejudices, and promoting greater tolerance and
understanding of human diversity. But with increased globalization over
the past hundred years, diversity has become more obvious, more
important, and more endangered than ever before.
Increased awareness of human diversity and interactions between
groups with different cultures brings with it both practical and
philosophical challenges. Like historicism, the awareness of human
diversity threatens Kant’s anthropology with relativism. If some cultures
do not ascribe moral responsibility to one another, or do not see morality
as universal, that would call into question Kant’s moral philosophy. If
some cultures do not understand the world in terms of necessary causal
interactions between spatial-temporal objects, that would threaten his
epistemology. Kant’s empirical anthropology, with its tidy classification of
human mental states, is based upon the introspection and limited
observations of a man who never went more than 90 miles from home.
Today one might wonder whether there really are empirically universal
characteristics of human nature. Even Kant’s conception of historical
progress, which sees human “unsocial sociability” driving human
progress, might seem incompatible with the existence of relatively
peaceful and stable cultures.
Practically, the problems are equally severe. What responsibilities
do we have with respect to those from other cultures? For Kant,
enlightenment arises through the vibrant exchange of ideas aiming
towards the truth. But this truth-orientation is also an orientation
towards finding agreement, or conformity. As “multiculturalism” and
“pluralism” have come to be taken as goods in their own right, one might
question Kant’s emphasis on reaching agreement. Might it not be better
to allow, protect, and even promote widely divergence conceptions of
reality amongst different human groups. Efforts to preserve dying
languages can be seen as part of this general interest. Morally, the
problems are even more severe. If “we” share, broadly speaking, Kant’s
commitment to respect for humanity, how should this respect manifest
itself in interactions with those from other cultures? If women in a
particular culture are mistreated or abused, should “we” refrain from
334 interfering out of respect for the culture or should we intervene out of
respect for the woman? Or is there some other option? Politically, the
problems of diversity are acute. Kant argued that no political order is
fully just until it becomes part of a global federation of states. Since our
planet is finite and interconnected, no set of people has an absolute right
to assert sovereignty over its territory without getting some sort of
consent from all other people on earth. Kant used this insistence upon
consent to argue against unjust colonization of other peoples that was
widespread during the 18th century.238 But he also recognizes that his
own theory of universal consent is susceptible to an all-too-common
“Jesuitism” that would “ask whether . . . we should not be authorized to
found colonies, by force if need be, in order to establish a civil union . . .
and bring these human beings (savages) into a rightful condition”
(6:266).
One popular way of reacting to human diversity is to embrace
cultural relativism about truth, virtue, and beauty. As in the case of
historicism, there are both methodological and substantive versions of
this relativism. Methodologically, at least a limited relativism has become
the norm among contemporary cultural anthropologists. In studying
other cultures, anthropologists typically focus on discerning the
practices, presuppositions, and values of a particular culture without
aiming to assess the value of those practices in terms of any supposed
absolute standard. Clifford Geertz, arguably the preeminent
contemporary cultural anthropologist, makes explicit a “relativist bent”
that is “in some sense implicit in the field as such” (Geertz 2007:44). And
Ruth Benedict, in her classic Patterns of Culture (Benedict 1934/2005),
explains:
To the anthropologist, our customs and those of a New Guinea tribe
are two possible social schemes for dealing with a common problem,
and insofar as he remains an anthropologist he is bound to avoid any
weighing of one in favor of the other. (Benedict 1934/2005: 1)
Methodologically, the relativist bent of anthropologists commits them to
engaging in a different project than that of philosophers or even many
psychologists. Rather than trying to figure out the best way of dealing
with various problems that might arise in societies (whether one’s own of
that of another), the anthropologist observes and seeks to understand
how other cultures see and respond to those problems. To avoid
projecting one’s values onto other cultures and to remain sensitive to the
nuances of other cultures, some sort of relativism – at least in the
238
(See PP 8:357-60, MM 6:353)
335 negative sense of refraining as much as possible from evaluating other
cultures in terms of one’s own – has proven immensely valuable for
understanding human diversity.
Substantive relativism takes this relativist bent further, claiming
that basic concepts of truth and value are culture-relative not merely in
the sense that what people find true and valuable is largely culturebound, but that truth and value are in fact culturally relative.
Methodological relativism simply refrains from asking ultimate questions
about Truth or Goodness. Substantive relativism claims that there are no
(universal) answers to those questions, that “morality differs in every
society, and is a convenient term for socially approved habits,” so “we do
not any longer make the mistake of deriving . . . morality . . . directly
from . . . human nature. We do not elevate it to the dignity of a first
principle. (Benedict 1934) Geertz too sees relativism not merely as a
methodological presupposition of anthropological research but as a
necessary consequence of anthropological insight:
One cannot read too long about Nayar matriliny, Aztec sacrifice, the
Hopi verb, or the convolutions of the hominid transition and not
begin at least to consider the possibility that, to quote Montaigne . . .,
“each man calls barbarism whatever is not his own practice . . . for
we have no other criterion of reason that the example and idea of the
opinions and customs of the country we live in.” That notion,
whatever its problems, and however more delicately expressed, is not
likely to go away unless anthropology does. (Geertz 2001: 44-5)
As much as Geertz and Benedict see substantive relativism as a
consequence of anthropological study, however, it does not follow
logically from the fact of human diversity, nor from the methodological
relativism that enhances our understanding of that diversity. It would be
perfectly sensible to recognize that human beings hold different beliefs
about physics, for example, and even to study different cultures’
mathematical systems without evaluating their soundness, while still
affirming that, for instance, projectiles really do travel on parabolic paths
and spells cannot transform lead into gold. Similarly, it would be
perfectly sensible to recognize that human beings have different sets of
moral values regulating interactions, while still affirming that, for
example, value systems within which malicious deception is condoned or
slavery is promoted are wrong.
Moreover, in its most blatant form, substantive relativism is simply
self-defeating. Benedict rightly notes that “the recognition of cultural
relativity carries with it its own values,” and while these “need not be
336 those of the [prior] absolutist philosophies” (Benedict 1934/2005: 278),
they are just as absolutist as those.239 As anthropologist D. Sperber has
noted, “while the best evidence for relativism [is] in the writings of
anthropologists, the best evidence against relativism is . . . the very
activity of anthropologists” (Sperber 1982: 180). Strikingly, substantive
relativism turns out to be a particularly parochial value system; while
there may be some other cultures that believe in epistemic and moral
relativism, most do not, and the particular forms of relativism dominant
today have emerged only in the context of moral and anthropological
developments in “the West” in the past hundred years. Substantive
relativism of this dogmatic sort is just as ethnocentric and absolutist as
any other substantive dogma.
There are, however, less dogmatic sorts of relativism that still go
beyond the merely methodological relativism of contemporary
anthropology. For one thing, anthropological study, like the historical
studies of Foucault and Kuhn, can show that the from-within perspective
that Kant took for granted is not as universal as he supposed. Geertz
makes this connection explicit. Citing his own pioneering work in
cultural anthropology, he notes,
[T]he constructivism of Thomas Kuhn and . . . Foucault . . . suddenly
made a concern with meaning-making an acceptable pre-occupation
for a scholar to have [and] they provided the . . . speculative
instruments to make the existence of someone who saw human
beings as, quoting myself . . . “suspended in webs of meaning they
themselves have spun” a good deal easier . . . [In] Bali, . . . I tried to
show that kinship, village form, the traditional state, . . . and, most
infamously, the cockfight could be read as texts, or to quiet the
literal-minded, “text-analogues” – enacted statements of . . .
particular ways of being in the world. (Geertz 2001: 17)
When we look back at Geertz’s anthropological work, the connections
become clear. Even in 1973, Geertz emphasized that “The whole point of
[his] . . . approach to culture is . . . to aid us in gaining access to the
conceptual world in which our subjects live so that we can, in some
extended sense of the term, converse with them” (Geertz 1973: 24). In
that context, “descriptions of Berber, Jewish, or French culture must be
cast in terms of the constructions we imagine Berbers, Jews, or
Frenchman to place upon what they live through” (Geertz 1973: 15). In
such a context, one comes to see our own “ideas, our values, our acts,
239
Benedict herself often appeals to her own “objective point of view” (e.g. Benedict 1934: 7-8) on other
cultures, drawing on a non-relativist epistemic ideal in defense of her anthropological method.
337 even our emotions [as] cultural products” (Geertz 1973: 50). Putting
ourselves in other “worlds” makes Kant’s kind of transcendental
anthropology impossible, not because of a dogmatic assertion that there
are no universals, but simply because we come to see new possibilities –
and hence new “conditions of possibility.” One need not deny a universal
point of view to make one’s own point of view seem provincial. And a
transcendental analysis of a provincial and contingent point of view falls
short of the anthropo-logy in which Kant was so interested.
As in the case of historicism, of course, this very general sort of
objection is most important when fleshed out in terms of specific points
of comparison between what Kant took to be universal aspects of human
nature and what anthropologists find in other cultures. For example,
Ruth Benedict – drawing on the work of Reo Fortune – describes the
Dobu people of the South Pacific in ways particularly problematic for
Kant’s moral philosophy:
The Dobuan is dour, prudish, and passionate, consumed with
jealousy and suspicion and resentment. Every moment of prosperity
he conceives himself to have wrung from a malicious world by a
conflict in which he has worsted an opponent. The good man is the
one who has many such conflicts to his credit, as anyone can see
from the fact that he has survived with a measure of prosperity. It is
taken for granted that he has thieved, killed children and his close
associates by sorcery, cheated whenever he dared. [T]heft and
adultery are the object of the valued charms of the valued men of the
community. (Benedict 1934/2005:168-9)
As troubling as is the general fact that moral norms might differ from one
context to another, the details of these differences seem to pose
particular problems for Kant. Whatever the Dobuans mean by the “good”
man, they cannot mean the man who acts only on maxims that he can
will to be universal. A “good” man, on Benedict’s reconstruction of the
Dobu people, is one who acts on maxims that precisely cannot be
universalized, one who exploits and misuses his fellows for his own
benefit. And thus any “transcendental anthropology of volition” for the
Dobu will, it seems, have to look very different from Kant’s.
Along with this undoing of the foundations of Kant’s universalist
anthropology, many of those interested in human diversity add an ethical
and pragmatic “relativist bent.” Geertz, for example, largely accepts the
point that substantive relativism is self-undermining. But he takes this
precisely as a reason not to worry about objecting to it. As he puts it,
“The image of vast numbers of anthropology readers running around in
338 so cosmopolitan a frame of mind as to have no views as to what is and
isn’t true, or good, or beautiful, seems to me largely a fantasy” (Geertz
2001: 46). By contrast, however, the thought of lots of Kantians running
around interpreting everyone in terms of their own prejudices about
knowledge, goodness, and even beauty is one worthy of genuine concern:
“provincialism . . . [is a] more real concern [than relativism]” (Geertz
2001: 46). And in that context, studying different ways of being in the
world facilitates a sort of humility about one’s own ways, an openness to
possibilities, a valuing of differences. Especially in a world where “alien
turns of mind are mostly not really elsewhere, but alternatives for us,
hard nearby” (Geertz 2001: 83), we do not need a Kantian, universalist
anthropology but rather a proliferation of “connoisseur[s] . . . of alien
turns of mind,” of whom “the connoisseur par excellent . . . has been the
ethnographer (the historian too, to a degree, and in a different way the
novelist, but I want to get back on my own reservation), dramatizing
oddness, extolling diversity, and breathing broadmindedness” (Geertz
2001: 82-3).
The undermining of the possibility of Kantian naïveté about the
universality of one’s own perspective, combined with a ethical sense of
the importance of broadmindedness, tolerance, and understanding
others, leads to a new vision for how to go about answering the question,
“What is the human being?”
If we want to discover what the human being amounts to, we can
only find it in what human beings are: and what human beings are,
above all other things, is various. It is in understanding that
variousness – its range, its nature, its basis, and its implications –
that we shall come to construct a concept of human nature that,
more than a statistical shadow and less than a primitive dream, has
both substance and truth . . . To be human here is thus not to be
Everyman; it is to be a particular kind of man, and of course men
differ . . . [I]t is in a systematic review and analysis of [different ways
of being human] – of the Plain’s Indian’s bravura, the Hindu’s
obsessiveness, the Frenchman’s rationalism, the Berber’s anarchism,
the American’s optimism – that we shall find out what it is, or can be,
to be a man. (Geertz 1973: 52-3)240
240
Throughout this quotation, I’ve changed “man” and “men” to “human being” or “human beings.”
Importantly, too, Geertz adds that this “series of tags” is one that “I should not like to have to defend” and,
further, that “we must . . . descend in detail, past the misleading tags, past the metaphysical types, past the
empty similarities to grasp firmly the essential character of not only the various cultures but the various
sorts of individuals within each culture, if we wish to encounter humanity face to face” (Geertz 1973: 53).
339 Even without going as far as substantive relativism, contemporary
cultural anthropology – and its spin-offs into cultural studies,
postcolonial studies, gender studies, and studies of diversity in all its
forms – invites a shift in perspective. Just as historicists argue against a
single notion of “human being” for all times, cultural anthropologists
object to a cross-cultural conception of the human being, replacing it
with rich variety. And as in the case of historicism, while there are
potential implications of cultural anthropology for his empirical
anthropology, the cultural-anthropological threat to Kant is most acute
in the context of his transcendental anthropology.241
IV. Kantian Responses to Historicism
Kuhn, Foucault, Benedict, and Geertz all draw attention to
fundamental human differences that not only reflect empirical variations
but also affect how humans see and live in their worlds. They threaten
not only Kant’s empirical claims, but his transcendental anthropology.
While the specific claims of each thinker would require very specific
responses, there are three general strategies that a contemporary
Kantian might use to respond to these challenges, what I will call
“sticking to one’s guns,” “strategic retreat,” and “surrender.”
Sticking to one’s guns
The “guns” to which Kant would stick in these cases are the basic
tenets of his transcendental anthropology. A gun-sticking Kantian would
refuse to give up the central claims that all human volition involves an
awareness of the moral law and all human cognition involves spatialtemporal intuition and a priori cognitive categories such as causation.
With respect to challenges posed by scientific developments, this would
involve denying that relativity theory and quantum mechanics, as
generally interpreted, provide actual cognition of the world. Any
contradiction between Kant’s transcendental anthropology and Einstein’s
physics would be bad news for Einstein, not for Kant. With respect to
Foucault and Geertz, Kant might simply deny that these figures properly
interpreted human history or diverse cultures, or he might deny that the
241
Empirically, cultural anthropologists do not challenge as much of Kant’s conception of human beings as
one might imagine. Virtually none doubt that people in other cultures have cognitions, desires, or capacities
to develop habits. And much recent work shows many universal human characteristics (see Pinker 2002
and Spiro 1987). The real challenge comes from the way in which cultural diversity can undermine Kant’s
from-within accounts of thought, feeling, and action.
340 interpretations really represent counter-examples to his transcendental
anthropology.
While sticking to one’s guns might seem simply pig-headed, it is
not wholly unjustified. Regarding developments in science, Kant’s
arguments for the aprioricity of our forms of cognition were based on
conditions for arriving at genuine empirical understandings of the world.
And it is not entirely clearly that modern scientific theories are literally
understandable in their non-Kantian forms. The mathematics of
relativity theory and quantum mechanics does not conflict with Kant’s a
priori structures of human cognition. Kant never claimed that it would be
impossible to think about what would follow from rejecting one or more of
Euclid’s axioms, only that it would be impossible to actually cognize such
a world, that is, to fill in one’s concepts with intuitions of objects. And
when “explaining” objects in quantum-mechanical or relativist terms,
scientists notoriously turn to metaphor and analogy, which suggests that
a literal understanding of modern physics is not yet forthcoming. For a
gun-sticking Kantian, intuitive comprehensibility would be a constraint
on scientific realism, and Kant himself proposes a similar approach
against those in his day (and ours!) who assume the existence of a
vacuum.
Nearly all natural philosophers, since they perceive a great difference
in the quantity of matter of different sorts in the same volume . . .
infer that this volume . . . must be empty in all matter, although to be
sure in different amounts. But . . . their inference rest[s] solely on a
metaphysical presupposition . . . for they assume that the real in
space . . . is everywhere one and the same and can be differentiated
only according to its . . . amount. Against this presupposition, . . . I
oppose a transcendental proof, which, to be sure, will not explain the
variation in the filling of space, but which still will entirely obviate the
alleged necessity of the presupposition . . . which has the merit of at
least granting the understanding the freedom to think of this
difference in another way. (A173-4/B215-6)
It is unnecessary to enter into the details of this particular debate here;
the general point is that Kant is willing to set his transcendental proof
against the “unanimous” decrees of “nearly all natural philosophers,”
and to do so even when he cannot himself explain the phenomena that
their theories purport to explain. Similarly, a Kantian today might insist
that quantum mechanics and relativity theory cannot be adequate
explanations of the world, since they are inconsistent with our forms of
intuition and thus literally incomprehensible as applied to objects. They
can still be good models for prediction, but not for understanding, and
341 rejecting scientific realism here may even “have the merit” of encouraging
work in new directions in physics. Akin to Einstein’s early critique of
quantum mechanics, we might see Kant as insisting that the fact that
scientists have not found deterministic laws does not imply that there are
no deterministic laws.242 Kant might even go further, pointing out that
appeals to sub-atomic quantum states and bendable space-time that
cannot be literally understood in the way we understand objects of
experience reflects a 21st century version of the classic metaphysical
temptation to turn to things-in-themselves – thinkable but non-intuitable
psuedo-objects – as a shortcut for explaining the empirical world.243
Similarly, with respect to Foucaultian genealogy and Geertzian
anthropology, sticking to his guns is more plausible than it might at first
appear. One approach here is an attitude towards cultural difference
that many think Kant actually adopted. One might maintain Kant’s
transcendental anthropology while still admitting human diversity by
simply insisting that some peoples and cultures are not “human” in the
fullest sense.244 If a particular group conceives of decision-making purely
in categories of beauty (as Foucault suggests for the ancient Greeks) or
prudence (as Benedict suggests for the people of Dobu), then Kant might
just say that such people lack a fully developed predisposition to
personality, lack a genuine moral sense, and, in that sense, are not really
“human.” Whether or not this would warrant treating them with
disrespect would remain an open question, but it would be a way of
saving Kant’s philosophical account from anthropological challenge. As
offensive as the approach sounds, there is some degree to which it is
unavoidable. We do see the world through our own eyes and our own
values, and while our perspective might change through understanding
others, there simply is not – if relativist cultural anthropology is right – a
single perspective that all groups share. But since we do need to decide
what to believe and how to act, we will, at least in practice, think and act
in accordance with norms we think best, and we will thereby at least
implicitly view other groups as seeing through the wrong eyes. Even the
relativist bent shared by Benedict, Geertz and Foucault is a particular
bent developed in a particular culture, one not shared by many other
242
See Einstein et. al. 1935, but cf. Bohm 1951 and Bell 1964, 1987. For discussion, see Baggott 2004
(which explains how experimental work has largely vindicated indeterminist interpretations of
quantum mechanics against the Bohm-Bell deterministic interpretation) and Cushing 1994 (which
offers a sustained defense of Bohm’s deterministic interpretation.
243
For a Kantian argument that treats unobservables in science in roughly this way, see Hanna 2006.
244
For a treatment of Kant’s accounts of diversity as a form of “alienology,” see Cohen 2010.
342 people in many other cultures. Insofar “What is the human being?” is a
normative question about how best to be human, it is almost inevitable, if
we know enough about human diversity, to see at least some forms of
diversity as failures to live up what it means to be a human in the fullest
sense.
But there are other, less judgmental, ways for a Kantian to stick to
her guns. One important move for the Kantian will be to distinguish
between particular knowledge or value claims and the overall structure of
knowledge- or value-claims. Even if other cultures, for example, disagree
about what causes particular kinds of changes, they may still agree on
the notion of temporal succession (and thereby on some shared
conception of causation). Even if cultures disagree about, say,
cannibalism, they might still adhere to some general conception of
respect for others. And even if – as in Benedict’s account of the Dobu –
some cultures do not even believe in anything that could be called
Kantian respect, they might still adhere to a sense of “goodness” as
something that would be “good” for anyone. Thus one of Benedict’s
Dobuans might say that anyone who successfully exploits and abuses
others is “good.” And in such a case, Kant might be able to run
transcendental arguments to show that built into this conception of
goodness is a standard of goodness at variance with the particular
ethical prescriptions of Benedict’s Dobu.
Kant also could rightly insist upon a difference between fromwithin standpoints of evaluation and deliberation and a people’s actual
customs and practices. Kant admits that human beings are “radically
evil” and even that this evil manifests itself in corrupting social networks
to the point that “someone already counts as good when his evil is
common to a class” (6:33). Moreover, given variable conditions, human
inclinations and prejudices develop in different ways, with
correspondingly different manifestations of immorality in different
cultures. Thus just as the Dobu might excuse the immorality of adultery
and witchcraft and praise its prudence, those on Wall Street might
excuse the immorality of competitive “sharp practice” and praise the
returns one brings home to one’s shareholders. In neither case are these
forms of praise reflections of a different moral code; they just reflect the
ordinary way in which social forms of radical evil corrupt our strict
application of the moral law we recognize from-within.
Finally, Kant might rightly point out that much of the perceived
variation amongst cultures could be due to a prejudgment or inclination
towards novelty, one widely shared by the sorts of people that typically
become anthropologists and (Foucauldian) historians. Kant emphasizes,
343 from a multiplicity of descriptions of countries one can prove, if one
wants to, that Americans, Tibetans, and other genuine Mongolian
peoples have no beard, but also, if it suits you better, that all of them
are by nature bearded . . .; that Americans and Negroes are each a
race, sunk beneath the remaining of the human species in their
mental predispositions, but on the other side by just as apparent
records that as regards their natural predispositions, they are to be
estimated equal to every other inhabitant of the world; so it remains
to the choice of the philosopher whether he wants to assume
differences in nature or wants to just everything in accordance with
the principle “Everything is as it is with us.” (8:62)
As we saw above, a certain relativistic bent – and often even an
orientalizing fascination with the exotic (see Said 1979, Obeyesekere
1993, 2005) – is not only a natural result of anthropological study, but a
sort of dispositional and methodological presupposition of certain kinds of
anthropological investigation (including, alas, Kant’s). Likewise,
Foucault’s genealogical and archaeological projects, as much as they
seem to provide evidence of the historical emergence of frameworks of
thought and action, ultimately presuppose a historicist approach to
structures of human knowledge-power. In his own Anthropology, Kant
points out that “without . . . a plan . . . all acquired knowledge [of the
world] can yield nothing more than fragmentary groping around and no
science,” and for Kant, this plan requires that “General knowledge always
precede local knowledge,” that is, that one have a sense of the human
being in general before studying local variations (7:120). Whether or not
one agrees with this methodological prescription, it is worth noting that
anthropologists studying the world with this sort of Kantian methodology
may come to very different conclusions that those who begin with a more
relativistic bent. There is reason for at least some skepticism about the
empirical findings – and their interpretations – offered by the more
relativistically-inclined anthropologists amongst us.
Thus whereas Foucault focuses on the emergence of contemporary
notions of subjectivity, a Kantian historicist might instead look for
Kantian conceptions of subjectivity in historical periods when Foucault
denies them and in cultural contexts where contemporary
anthropologists claim not to find them. Where Foucault claims that
“nobody is obliged in classical ethics,” Kant might claim that classical
notions of “beautiful existence” are taken, even in ancient Greece, as “to-
344 be-chosen” in ways that correspond to categorical “obligation.”245
Historical ways of describing subjectivity would be merely different
“formulae” for common underlying transcendental structures of human
beings that Kant elucidates in terms of “obligation,” “freedom,” and
“autonomy.” It is worth emphasizing here that Kant’s moral anthropology
and conception of subjectivity were at variance even with what one may
have discovered – as an anthropologist or historian – about his own time.
Kant emphasizes the independence of conscience from religion, the
importance of adhering to strict principles, the extent to which morals
must be carefully distinguished from the pursuit of happiness. Kant saw
these claims as implicit in the volitional structure of his compatriots (and
human beings in general), but all of them could have been occluded in a
historical or anthropological study of his culture. 246
This skepticism, of course, can lead to a different way of doing
anthropology, but time must still tell whether this sort of Kantian
cultural anthropology could hold up to the empirical facts on the ground.
There are, however, promising hints that an anthropology that leaves
more room for human universals – especially of the rational variety in
which Kant would be most interested – may be more fruitful than
anthropologists like Benedict and Geertz suggest.247 Perhaps the most
famous example in recent anthropology is the debate between two of the
preeminent anthropologists of our time – Gananath Obeyesekere and
Marshall Sahlins – regarding the Hawaiians’ reception of Captain Cook.
While Sahlins undertook that study largely with the “relativist bent” of a
European interested in the exotic and developed a picture of native
Hawaiians that makes them seem very different from Europeans then
and now, Obeysekere went into the study with a skepticism about the
nature of European anthropological and “myth-making” practices and
called into question exoticizing descriptions of the reception of Cook
245
Kant’s ethics, in fact, is often referred to as “deontological,” from the Greek term “dei,” which refers to
that which is binding or what it behooves one to do, as in the Iliad’s “ti de dei polemizemenai . . Argeious”
(why do the Argives have to fight?”) (Il.9.337).
246
The fact that Kant sees his philosophical account of the unconditional nature of morality as
unrecognized (and thus unreflected) in even the best moral philosophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries implies that the absence of similarly worked out accounts of moral obligation in the ancients
would come as no surprise. Moreover, Foucault’s historical claims are far from non-controversial, and there
is substantial empirical support not only for universal and transhistorical moral norms but also for some
basic conceptions of subjectivity and obligation that are universal and transhistorical.
247
See, e.g., Bok 2002, Brown 1991, Goodenough 1970, Pinker 1993, Schwarz and Bilsky 1990, and Spiro
1954.
345 shared by modern anthropologists and ultimately even Hawaiians
themselves.248
To take a less famous and more pointed example, Susanne
Kuehling has recently published a book-length study of the Dobu people
in which she makes clear not only the profound limitations of the original
field research on which Benedict relied (by an anthropologist – Fortune –
who had access to a single Dobuan for a mere month’s time and wrote
with “the imperial attitude of his time” (Kuehling 2005:14)) but also how
“Benedict’s travesty” (Kuehling 2005:136) warped even that “vastly
oversimplified” account to portray an “even darker” picture of the Dobu
“as an extreme example of human moral possibilities” (Kuehling
2005:16), a “characterization . . . that bears no resemblance to [the]
Dobu” experienced by Kuehling over the course of several years of
intense fieldwork. In sharp contrast to the “inverted morality” portrayed
by Benedict, Kuehling highlights the Dobu’s “egalitarian ethic” (Kuehling
2005:117) and emphasizes that among the Dobu an “ethics of respect,
self-discipline, and generosity are the keys to appropriate behavior”
(Kuehling 2005:69). Of course, Kuehling’s own account, which highlights
the “ethics of exchange” as a framework for understanding the Dobu,
does not show that the Dobu share the general presuppositions of Kant’s
moral anthropology, but she goes into her study with a different agenda,
with a different “general knowledge,” and thus Kant would be
unsurprised that she neither looks for nor finds the sort of
“predisposition to personality” in which a Kantian anthropologist would
be particularly interested. What she clearly shows, however, is the
importance of taking any anthropological “counter-examples” to Kantian
transcendental anthropology with a grain of salt. And she thus justifies
at least a provisional Kantian sticking-to-one’s-guns, an unwillingness to
take as given the “observations” and “facts” of anthropologists who go
into the field with deeply non- or even anti-Kantian presuppositional
frameworks.
Strategic retreat
248
A full discussion of this very interesting debate would take us far beyond the scope of this book. For a
clear overview with references to further sources, see Borofsky and Kane 1997.
346 Strategic retreat involves giving up specific a priori structures,
such as Euclidean space, Newtonian deterministic causation, or specific
formulations of the categorical imperative, but preserving more general a
priori structures, roughly corresponding to Kant’s. Just as contemporary
psychology requires revising details of Kant’s empirical anthropology but
not his overall framework, historicist or anthropological studies might
require revising merely details of Kant’s transcendental anthropology.
Alternative, one might strategically retreat by limiting the scope of Kant’s
a priori structures, insisting that they underlie ordinary experience but
not scientific or moral theorizing.
As with sticking-to-one’s-guns, strategic retreat is more plausible
and more significant than it might first appear. With respect to relativity
theory, for example, Henrik Lorentz had developed an alternative to
Einsteinian special relativity theory that is both “empirically equivalent”
to it and makes use of an “essentially classical spatio-temporal
structure” (Friedman 2001:87). The probabilistic causation of quantum
mechanics already fits with a slightly modified version of Kant’s approach
to causation. For Kant, the fundamental role of causation is to preserve
the directionality of time. Kant assumed that the only causal principle by
means of which one could order the world would be a principle according
to which, given some cause, its effect necessarily followed according to a
deterministic rule. Quantum mechanics conceives of causation as a
principle according to which, given some initial state, its succeeding state
is determined by a probabilistic rule. While giving up the necessity of the
effect given the cause would be an important shift from Kant’s category of
causation, it would not require giving up the basic structure of
succeeding states following from previous ones according to rules.
One might imagine retreating further, such that one ends up with
increasingly thin a priori structures of cognition. Kuhn himself argues for
some form of this approach, defending general epistemic virtues such as
accuracy, consistency, breadth of scope, simplicity, and fruitfulness in
generating new findings as general characteristics of any good scientific
theory (Kuhn 1977). Similarly, Kant might argue that whatever particular
structures human beings use to interpret their world, they make use of
certain a priori principles to guide empirical cognition in general. This
strategy could be extended to variations in conceptions of the world
discovered by anthropologists. While other cultures may allow for
witchcraft, cycles of time, or radically different approaches to
understanding the world, one might still find common basic structures
underlying all these approaches. Even something like Foucault’s
analysis of earlier forms of subjectivity might leave common structures –
say, some general notion of normativity or basic distinction between a
347 from-within and an objective perspective – that are common to different,
historically-local ways of conceptualizing these structures.
Beyond changing particular claims while keeping more general
ones, an important sort of strategic retreat, especially in the scientific
context, might be the concession of historicism with respect to scientific
cognition while preserving Kant’s transcendental anthropology for what
one might call ordinary cognition.249 Even if scientists now think of the
world as involving probabilistic causation and non-Euclidean space,
ordinary human experience is universally and ahistorically based on
Kant’s a priori cognitive structures. Especially conjoined with a
deprivileging of scientific cognition, such a retreat preserves a
substantial role for Kant’s transcendental anthropology of cognition while
leaving science subject to historicist interpretation. (One might do
something similar with other cultures, arguing that, say, religious or
mythical beliefs might violate Kant’s categories of experience while
everyday interactions would still be governed by them.) This sort of
retreat is not Kant’s, in that Kant saw his transcendental anthropology
as providing metaphysical conditions of possibility not only of
“experience” but also of “natural science.”250 And this approach is not
without its problems. For one thing, even ordinary human cognition
seems less universal as Kant suggests, in part because ordinary
experience is – like science – shaped by historically contingent cultural
paradigms. Moreover, while Kant allows for distinctions between
apparently contradictory perspectives (such as the empirical and the
practical), he does so only after carefully explaining why those
perspectives do not actually conflict with one another, why they can be
taken to refer to different worlds, and how those different worlds relate to
one another. To allow for legitimate scientific theories that seem to
conflict with conditions of possibility of experience, Kant would have to
show that this conflict is merely apparent and explain how the scientific
understanding of the world relates to the commonsensical one. Such a
project may be possible, but it represents a considerable burden for this
sort of strategic retreat.
Surrender.
249
One might also, especially vis a vis something like Foucault’s historicism, strategically retreat by
limiting the scope of one’s transcendental analysis to the present (and recent past), such that whatever
morality looked like “from-within” for ancient Greeks, it involves moral responsibility and personal
accountability now.
250
See especially his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science.
348 Strategic retreat might go so far that virtually nothing worth saving
is left of Kant’s transcendental anthropology. Even the most basic
cognitive and volitional values might be exposed as historically
contingent. In this context, one might simply need to concede that Kant’s
transcendental anthropology must be replaced by a historicist one. Even
outright surrender, however, need not involve a wholesale rejection of the
insights of Kant’s transcendental anthropology. For example, arguably
the most exciting Kantian philosopher of science today – Michael
Friedman – has defended a “modified version of a Kantian philosophy of
science” centered around the concept of a “relativized yet still constitutive
a priori” (Friedman 2001:71). Friedman embraces the historical
contingency of cognitive structures by which human beings make sense
of the world while sustaining a commitment to the status of these
structures as constitutive of (our understanding of) that world. For
Friedman, even a relativized a priori is an important contribution to
contemporary philosophy of science in that it implies, against Quine’s
holistic “fabric” of knowledge, that knowledge has a structure with
“fundamental asymmetries,” such that within any (scientific) body of
knowledge, there are “necessary presuppositions constituting the
conditions of possibility of the properly empirical parts” (Friedman 2001:
35, 37). Even if every aspect of human knowledge is in principle revisable
in the light of further experience, there is a fundamental distinction
between the ways that specific empirical laws and the (relativized) a
priori structures of cognition are revisable in the light of experience. Even
when historicized, the general approach of Kant’s transcendental
anthropology contributes to understanding human beings. In fact, one
might even argue, it is Kant’s transcendental anthropology of cognition,
and especially his emphasis on the role of cognitive structures in
constructing our experience, that makes a Kuhnian sort of historicism
possible. Without Kant, one might be able to trace, as Quine does, the
evolution of different ways of thinking about the world. But one would be
unable to see, as Kuhn does, the way that historically changing ways of
looking at the world actually structure and constrain human experience
itself.
In the context of Foucault, too, surrender would require a radical
reorientiation of Kant’s anthropology but need not require rejecting it
entirely. Importantly, a strategy like Friedman’s – that concedes the
historicity of a priori structures of cognition – would not constitute a
sufficient concession to Foucault, since Foucault historicizes the whole
notion of a priori structures of an individual subject. In the case of
Foucault, at least, “surrender” is little more than conversion, a
replacement of Kant with Foucault. But arguably, this replacement
349 remains within the general sphere of Kant. Foucault read Kant’s “What is
Enlightenment?” as a proto-historicist work (see Foucault 1984: 32-50),
and Foucault’s intellectual career began with his effort to struggle
through problems in Kant’s Anthropology (see Foucault 2008). Thus
Foucault is a sort of radically-historicized Kant, and in that sense,
Foucault himself is an excellent model for what a “Kantian-Foucaultian”
might look like.
Finally, even a complete Kantian surrender to cultural relativism
could still be interesting and important. In particular, Kantian
distinctions can help cultural anthropologists more effectively study
other cultures. The difference between transcendental and empirical
anthropology is itself an important one for cultural anthropologists. It is
one thing to describe the way people act and even the way they use
normative language, and it is another thing to investigate the way that
thoughts and actions appear from-within. The latter task is, of course,
much more difficult than the former for an “outsider,” and if the fromwithin perspectives of others are radically incommensurable with our
own, it may even be impossible. But clarifying the distinction will force
anthropologists to direct attention and articulate their views in more
precise ways. Moreover, even within transcendental anthropology, there
is an important distinction between the first-order normative claims that
one makes from-within and the elucidation of conditions of possibility for
those claims. For example, it is one thing to say, from-within, that the
boat is moving downstream; it is another to show – as Kant claims to do
– that a condition of possibility of the legitimacy of judgments like this is
the projection of a category of causality onto the world. The investigation
of transcendental conditions of possibility of “alien” ways of thinking and
valuing could be an extremely exciting sort of Kantian philosophical
anthropology (here using “anthropology” in something like its
contemporary sense), a development of different transcendental
anthropologies (here using “anthropology” in something like its Kantian
sense).
V. Conclusion: the problem of normativity
In various ways, historians, historicist philosophers, and
anthropologists challenge Kant’s anthropology. The last section looked at
a series of approaches that Kantians can use to respond to these
challenges while preserving, to varying degrees, a distinctively “Kantian”
approach to historical and cultural diversity. But regardless of which of
these approaches one adopts, there will arise a further important
350 question, one that mere descriptions of human difference and historical
change cannot answer: What are the implications of human differences
for how we, here and now, should think, feel, and act? What is the best
response to the diversity? Substantive relativism? Transcendental
historicism? Kantian universalism? Something else? As descriptions of
human difference and historical change, these historicist and
anthropological accounts are challenging and illuminating. But in
themselves, they don’t tell us what to do with these descriptions, what
effects they should have on how we think and feel and act.
In his Birth of the Clinic, Foucault highlights this problem: his
method “is concerned – outside of all prescriptive intent – with
determining the conditions of possibility of medical experience in modern
times” (Foucault 1994: xix, emphasis added). In their pivotal study of
Foucault, Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow add, with respect to
Foucault’s self-proclaimed goal of “seeking to give new impetus . . . to the
undefined work of freedom” (Foucault 1984: 45-6) by resisting the “docile
normalcy” of carceral society,
What is wrong with carceral society? Genealogy undermines a stance
which opposes it on the grounds of natural law or human dignity . . .
Genealogy also undermines opposing carceral society on the basis of
subjective preferences and intuitions . . . What are the resources
which enable us to sustain a critical stance? (Dreyfus and Rabinow
1982: 206) 251
The same point could be made with respect to Kuhn. If the categories
and practices of modern science are those of paradigms that emerged
recently and may be transcended, what should we do? Should we oppose
normal science and try to think of what is truly necessary? Should we
simply embrace a scientific process that may be leading us down a
misguided path? Similarly, Benedict and Geertz argue that our moral
and epistemic values may not be shared by other cultures. If this is true,
what should we do? Should we abandon those values? Should we adopt
the values of the Dobu? (If so, whose Dobu?) Of the Balinese? (Whose
Balinese?) Some new set of values?
These questions are simply a reminder that there is, in fact, a
from-within, norm-governed perspective. And they are a reminder that
empirical descriptions of the world in which we live – whether these are
natural-scientific or historical – are insufficient to answer normative
251
Foucault seems to recognize that history provides no guide here: “The historian’s essential role . . . [is to
provide] a topological and geological survey of the battlefield . . . But as for saying, ‘Here is what you must
do!’, certainly not” (Foucault 1980:62).
351 questions about how we ought to think, or feel, or act. Foucault, Kuhn,
and Benedict show that the fact that one holds a particular normative
standard can be explained in terms of historical and cultural conditions.
But when I, or you, or Foucault or Benedict, decide whether or not to
apply a standard, even one that has been revealed as historically-local,
we cannot merely think about that standard in historicist or culturallyrelativist terms. While Foucault’s histories or Geertz’s ethnographies
might broaden our range of possible ways of thinking and acting, they
cannot in the end tell us how to decide, within that range, what to think
or do.
One response to this predicament – Kant’s – is to look again, fromwithin, at the ever-better-understood world in which we live. As we gain
new insights into other time periods and other cultures, we can ask
ourselves transcendental questions about those insights themselves:
what are the conditions of possibility of historical knowledge? How is it
possible that we are able to know such things about other cultures?
What are the limits of such knowledge-claims? For Kant, the answers to
these questions will include his general conditions of possibility for
knowledge (space, time, causality, etc), and will likely include other more
specific conditions of possibility (in the way that biological knowledge
requires assuming purposiveness). We can go further, developing our
transcendental anthropology of volition in the light of new insights about
other cultures. What sorts of obligations might one have towards people
with different moral norms? What are the conditions of possibility of
mutual respect across cultural difference? What are my duties towards
very different others, especially as I come into greater contact with them?
And while these questions, for Kant, involve various new subsidiary
moral principles, they all require application of the universal moral law.
One might, of course, seek other normative responses to the
situation of historical and cultural diversity. In chapter eleven, we will
look at several such responses, responses that preserve the basic notion
that there are norms that can and should govern our thought and action
from-within, but that vary regarding the universality and foundations of
those norms. One might also – like Nietzsche – take diversity as a basis
for liberation into a creativity that rises above present values. The lesson
of historicism and cultural diversity, one might think, is that we should
stop looking for absolute standards “out there,” and start making
cognitive and volitional standards for ourselves. In its most influential
modern form, this emphasis expresses itself in existentialism, to which
we now turn.
352 353 Chapter 10: Existentialism
In 1966, in a review for the French journal L’Arc, Jean-Paul Sartre
– who would become the preeminent voice of existentialism for a
generation – criticized Foucault’s On the Order of Things – the book in
which he most pointedly discussed Kant’s conception of the human
being:
What do we find in The Order of Things? Certainly not an archaeology
of human sciences. Archaeology . . . studies a style that had been
designed and implemented by men. This style could thereafter
present itself as a natural state, taking the allure of something given.
It is nonetheless the result of a practice, the development of which
the archaeologist traces. What Foucault offers is . . . a geology: . . .
Each layer defines the conditions of possibility of a certain type of
thought that triumphs for a certain period. But Foucault does not tell
us what is most interesting: how every thought is built from these
conditions, nor how people pass from one thought to another. This
would require the intervention of praxis, thus history, and this is
precisely what he refuses. Certainly its perspective remains
historical. It distinguishes the epochs that precede from those that
come after. But he replaces the cinema with the magic lantern, the
movement with a succession of static states. (Sartre 1966)252
As we saw in the last chapter, historicists such as Kuhn and Foucault
rightly pointed out the role of a “historical a priori,” a set of structures or
paradigms that shape the way human beings think about and act within
the world. Sartre, in one sense, agrees wholeheartedly with this
historicist turn. Like Foucault (and Kuhn), Sartre insists that humans
see the world in the context of styles of thinking that structure possible
ways of thinking and acting. Like historicists, Sartre sees these a priori
structures of cognition as historically contingent rather than universal
across all times and peoples. But Sartre, Foucault, and other
historicists253 focus too much on looking at human beings from-without
252
At the time of the review, Foucault had not yet articulated his “genealogical” method, which arguably
comes closer to what Sartre sought in that it offers at least some outlines of explanations of the
development of different modes of thought. Precisely because these explanations are offered “fromwithout,” however, and especially given Foucault’s radical questioning of the subjectivity that lies at the
heart of Sartre’s existentialism, Sartre would still see Foucault’s account as replacing the cinema (within
which subjectivity takes center stage) with the magic lantern (where all changes happen externally).
(Though cf. Foucault’s Care of the Self, where he moves closer to Sartre.)
253
Kuhn, however, like prior Anglo-American historians of science and unlike Foucault, tends to write a
history of science within which individuals loom large. Thus Kuhn provides more room for individual
human paradigm choices that are undetermined by “evidence” and even by the social interests and power
relations.
354 and thereby fail to recognize the role of human subjectivity for effecting
shifts in the paradigms that structure humans’ experiences (including
the ways historicists see the world). Similarly, Sartre argues that natural
scientists who see human beings in terms of various natural forces (of
biology or psychology) fail to recognize the role of subjectivity in defining
the meaning and significance of our natural condition. Whereas
historicists and naturalists see human beings primarily as the products
of historical or natural forces, Sartre insists that history and even biology
(insofar as they are significant) are products of humans’ responses to
their situations. And this opens the way for thinking of paradigms as
expressions of human freedom rather than mere forces that constrain us.
Alongside the rise of naturalist and historicist approaches to
human beings, the past century has seen the birth and development of
“existentialist” approaches to being human that emphasize the
perspective from which one sees oneself as a free albeit finite being
confronting a world of possibilities. Existentialism has its origins in the
19th century (especially in the work of Kierkegaard254 and Nietzsche255)
but came to its own during the 20th century, as the spread of science and
technology both radically increased the range of options for human
beings and radically narrowed our self-conceptions. The material
expansion of choices for many people (especially in the developed world)
heightened the sense that who we are is largely up to us. Existentialism
rejects naturalist and historicist approaches as the last word on what it
means to be human, prioritizes our sense of ourselves from-within, and
emphasizes the importance of freedom for human life. The “existential
phenomenology” developed in different ways by Heidegger, Sartre,
Merleau-Ponty, and others has exerted an important influence not only
on contemporary philosophy but on our culture and popular conceptions
of what it means to be human.
At the same time, the past twenty or thirty years have seen a turn
away from the perceived egocentrism of traditional (especially Sartrean)
existentialism. The rise of “deconstructive” approaches to the self,
especially in the work of Derrida and Levinas, has combined
254
Or at least, of Kierkegaard’s pseudonyms. For the purpose of this chapter, I treat Kierkegaard as the
author of his pseudonym’s views. For Kierkegaard’s own discussion of his relationship with his
pseudonyms, see Kierkegaard 1992.
255
One might also include Dostoyevsky here, and both Kierkegaard and Nietzsche are complicated
antecedents of existentialism, for different reasons. More generally, with the exception of Sartre, there is no
figure who can unambiguously be counted an existentialist, and many who might qualify under one or
another description. For some general discussions of existentialism, see the works at the end of this chapter.
355 existentialist resistance to formulaic reductions of human life with an
emphasis on the radical and primordial heteronomy required by one’s
interactions with “alterity” (the incomprehensible otherness of another).
This has brought a shift away from the “ontological” and first-personal
perspective of existentialism towards ethical and radically secondpersonal approaches.
In many respects, existentialism is the most Kantian of the
contemporary approaches to the human being that we have discussed so
far. Like Kant, existentialists emphasize the importance of freedom and
finitude for making sense of being human. And like Kant, existentialists
focus on what being human means from-within, rather than analyzing
human beings as objects in the world. But existentialists radicalize and
modify these Kantian themes. Where Kant defends freedom-as-autonomy
subject to a moral law with a determinate form, Sartre insists upon an
“absolute freedom” that can appeal to no “book of ethics” (Sartre 1993:
25) and Kierkegaard describes an “absolute duty” that suspends the
ethical (Kierkegaard 2006). Where Kant emphasizes finitude primarily in
the contexts of sensibility and inclination, existentialists attend in detail
to what it means for human beings to have a past, a body, and to be
located in a particular situation. Finally, while Kant offers accounts of
cognition, feeling, and volition “from-within,” these faculties are, at least
broadly speaking, taken as self-consciously reflective and highly
structured. By contrast, existentialists aim to analyze what they take to
be more fundamental, primordial “from-within” perspectives, those of
everyday lived experiences of a meaningful world.
To better highlight the significance of these existentialist
developments of Kantian themes, this chapter focuses on five key aspects
of existentialist thought, drawing primarily from the existentialist
philosophies of Sartre and the early Heidegger.
(1) Human “existence.” Existentialists use the notion of “existence” (or
“Da-sein” or being “for-itself”) to distinguish the way humans exist
from the being of things in the world.
(2) Freedom. As for Kant, focusing on the “from-within” perspective of
human being leads to emphasizing human freedom.
(3) “Being-in-the-world.” The from-within perspective of human being
is not distinct from practical engagement with concrete situations in
the world.
356 (4) Angst, Bad faith, and Authenticity. Unlike Kantian freedom, which
is paradigmatically a freedom to obey moral law, existentialist
freedom is groundless. Angst is the experience of this groundless
freedom; bad faith and inauthenticity are ways of pretending that we
are not really free.
(5) Others. Human being-in-the-world is always also being with- or
for-others (other human beings).
From my discussion of existentialist approaches to others (or “the
Other”), I turn to the late Heidegger and Levinas (and implicitly also
Derrida), who extend existentialist insights but rethink the Other in ways
that open space for what has come to be associated with
“postmodernism” or “deconstructionism,” but which I describe as
“heteronomous” existentialism. I conclude this chapter by discussing
ways Kant might appropriate and respond to existentialism.
1. Existence
The name “existentialism” was first used by Gabriel Marcel to
describe the circle that grew up around Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir
in Paris in the 1940s (See de Beauvoir 1987: 45-6; and Cooper
1990:1).256 The classic formulations of existentialism are Sartre’s claim
that “existence precedes essence”257 and Heidegger’s that “The ‘essence’
of Da-sein lies in its existence” (Heidegger 1953:42, see too 117).258
“Existence” contrasts with anything like a human nature (Sartre 1993:
30) or essence that defines the human being. A human being “exists
before he can be defined by any concept” (Sartre 1993: 15). What we do
with our lives – our “existence” – defines who, and what, we are. Like
cultural or historical relativists, existentialists deny that there is any
universal answer to the question, “What is the human being?” But
existentialists contrast universal human nature not with locally-defined
traits but with “subjectivity,” the idea that “Man is nothing else but what
256
Although Sartre’s formulaic claim that existence precedes essence has become existentialism’s most
famous articulation, the first to put the term “existence” to use in the way central to existence-ialism was
Soren Kierkegaard: “That the knowing spirit is an existing spirit, and that every human being is such a
spirit existing for himself, I cannot repeat often enough” (Kierkegaard 1992: 189).
257
“Existentialism is a Humanism,” in Existentialism and Human Emotions, p. 13, hereafter abbreviated as
E.
258
All quotations from Heidegger’s Being and Time are from the translation by Joan Stambaugh. Page
numbers are to the seventh German edition.
357 he makes of himself” (Sartre 1993: 13, 15). The answer to Kant’s
question is a matter of how we decide to answer it in our lives. If a
human being is anything at all, it is “the being whose being is a question
for us” or the being that is always “for-itself.”
Martin Heidegger set the stage for modern existentialism by using
Kierkegaard’s concept of “existence” to develop an “existential analysis”
(Heidegger 1953:13) of what Heidegger calls “Da-sein.” The German
“Dasein” is one of many German words for “existence,” and Germans
often refer, for instance, to the Dasein (existence) of a table or chair. But
Heidegger uses “Da-sein” in its root meaning of being (Sein) here or there
(Da), and he contrasts this sort of Being with the “Being of beings” like
tables and chairs.259 One important implication of Heidegger’s
reinterpretation of this term is that Da-sein ceases to be a noun
(existence) or even an adjective (existent), and becomes, first and
foremost, a verb (as in to-be-there, or being-there).260 Like Kierkegaard,
Heidegger aims to shift away from thinking of human beings as static
objects of study and towards human being, as a sort of activity. The
question “What is the human being?” shifts from being about an object –
the human being – to being about an adverb: that is, what is a “human”
way of being (see BT 45)? What is the sort of “be-ing” that is human?
In order to think about the human be-ing without slipping into
forms of thought that have been centered on the analysis of beings (as
objects), Heidegger develops a whole new vocabulary of philosophical
analysis. His use of Da-sein rather than “human being” is part of this
shift, but Heidegger’s new terminology does not end there. Analysis of the
“nature” of particular “beings” he calls “ontical,” while the sort of analysis
that Heidegger proposes for Da-sein is “ontological,” an analysis of the
be-ing of Da-sein rather than an analysis of human beings as objects.
And in the context of distinguishing between these sorts of analysis,
Heidegger reintroduces the notion of “existence”:
The “essence” of Da-sein lies in its existence. The characteristics to
be found in this being are thus not objectively present “attributes” of
an objectively present being which has such and such an “outward
appearance,” but rather possible ways for it to be, and only this . . .
We shall call the characteristics of being of Da-sein existentials. They
are to be sharply delimited from the determinations of the being of
259
Though see, for example, Heidegger’s early lectures on Aristotle (in Heidegger 2009), where he moves
towards his conception of Dasein by beginning with Aristotlean notions of ordinary objects.
260
This implication does not exhaust the importance of the term Da-sein, for Heidegger. For more on the
significance of the “Da-” of “Da-sein,” see section three, below.
358 those beings unlike Da-sein which we call categories. (Heidegger
1953:42, 44)
While an object might have various properties that inhere in it as a sort
of essence, Da-sein has various ways of be-ing as different modes of its
own activity. For example, Heidegger contrasts the sort of spatiality that
one ascribes to objects, where one might be included in another or beside
another, with Da-sein’s existential “being-in-space,” which is a way
humans “be” in the world. Similarly, for Heidegger, a mood like fear is
not merely a “state” of a human being, but a way of be-ing (human)
(Heidegger 1953:140ff.). More famously, Heidegger discusses death not
as a state that brings a particular human being’s life to an end, but as
an existential “being-toward-death:” “Death is a way to be that Da-sein
takes over as soon as it is” (Heidegger 1953:245, cf. 236-67). Heidegger’s
“existential” analyses of Da-sein end up driving him towards complicated
German neologisms that require even more complicated English
translations, such as his characterization of Da-sein as “being-ahead-ofoneself-already-in (the world) as being-together-with (innerworldly beings
encountered)” (Heidegger 1953:192). But for our purposes, the main
point of these neologisms is that they reflect Heidegger’s efforts to rethink
human be-ing using terms that refer to ways of being rather than types
of beings.261
The emphasis on human being as a way of being has roots in the
early 20th century philosophical movement called “phenomenology.”
Chapter eleven discusses phenomenology as a normative approach, but
for this chapter, it is important briefly to discuss it as background to
existentialism. Edmund Husserl (1859-1938), who was Heidegger’s
mentor and heavily influenced Sartre, developed a method for focusing
on phenomena of consciousness to gain insight into the essence of
conscious experience. Husserl insists on bracketing scientific claims
about the world in order to focus on what he calls the “life-world
[Lebenswelt]” and to isolate what he calls the “transcendental ego”
(Husserl 1975:11). The point, in Kantian terms, is to gain insight into
basic structures of naïve (pre-scientific) engagement with the world fromwithin. While criticizing central details of Husserl’s account,262
existentialists in the 20th century maintain this focus on from-within
accounts of engagement with our “life-world.”
261
Sartre takes from Heidegger this emphasis on human being as a way of being but cashes it out in
terminology of the “in-itself” and “for-itself.” Tables, chairs, waterfalls, and stars are “in-themselves” in
that their essence is not an issue for them. But human being is “for-itself” in that “one must be what one is”
(Sartre 1956: 101, and passim), that is, what one “is” is a task set for the human being. A table simply is
what it is; a human must be what it is.
262
For a concise summary of criticisms, see Cooper 1990: 39-78.
359 For existentialists, the from-within perspective is privileged in that
only for existing human being – what Heidegger calls “Da-sein” and
Sartre the “for-itself” – does a world come to “be” at all: “the rise of man .
. . causes a world to be discovered” (Sartre 1956: 59, see too Heidegger
1953:12). Existential analysis makes empirical description of human
beings secondary. The world is a world only for a human in-the-world.
Empirical human sciences are deprivileged; rather than God’s-eye views
of human objects, sciences are among ways humans can “be” in the
world: “As ways in which human beings behave, sciences have this
being’s (the human being’s) kind of being . . . [but s]cientific research is
neither the sole nor the most immediate kind of being of this being that
is possible” (Heidegger 1953:11). Science is a human practice, a way of
existing in the world, so existential analyses of Being-in-the-world
explain the possibility of empirical science, rather than vice versa. All of
this should sound familiar, and existentialists’ emphasis on existence
can be put in rather Kantian terms: Rather than treating humans as
objects in the world, existentialists focus attention on what it is like to be
human, what living a human life is like from-within.
But existentialists modify this Kantian transcendental perspective
in several respects. In contrast to Kant’s transcendental arguments for
conditions of possibility of essential ways of human being, the
phenomenological method of 20th century existentialists focuses on rich
description of what appears or is “disclosed” in humans’ lived experience.
For example, Heidegger directs attention to the experience of hammering
(Heidegger 1953:69), and Sartre offers detailed existential descriptions of
phenomena as diverse as sexual attraction (Sartre 1956: 497f.), shame
(Sartre 1956: 350f.), smoking a cigarette (Sartre 1956: 73), and giving in
to fatigue during a mountain-climb (Sartre 1956: 584f.). This contrast
should not be overdone, of course. Kant was also interested in carefully
describing what one finds from-within and existentialists often lay out
conditions of possibility of phenomenologically-disclosed structures of
human being. Generally, however, Kant is more interested in arguing for
certain a priori principles as necessary conditions of possibility of what
he takes to be fairly obvious aspects of our “from-within” perspective,
while existentialists are more interested in carefully describing that
perspective in ways that are often far from obvious.
This difference in method is tied to a difference in what we might
call naïveté. Kant takes the basic from-within structures of thought,
volition, and even feeling to be transparent to reflection. Proper thought
involves justified ascriptions of objective properties and relations
amongst objects situated in (Euclidian) space and ((Levinas
1998a:jective)